Adaptation and Natural Selection
eBook - ePub

Adaptation and Natural Selection

A Critique of Some Current Evolutionary Thought

  1. English
  2. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  3. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Adaptation and Natural Selection

A Critique of Some Current Evolutionary Thought

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

Biological evolution is a fact—but the many conflicting theories of evolution remain controversial even today. When Adaptation and Natural Selection was first published in 1966, it struck a powerful blow against those who argued for the concept of group selection—the idea that evolution acts to select entire species rather than individuals. Williams's famous work in favor of simple Darwinism over group selection has become a classic of science literature, valued for its thorough and convincing argument and its relevance to many fields outside of biology. Now with a new foreword by Richard Dawkins, Adaptation and Natural Selection is an essential text for understanding the nature of scientific debate.

Frequently asked questions

Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Yes, you can access Adaptation and Natural Selection by George Christopher Williams in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Biological Sciences & Evolution. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

CHAPTER 1
Image
Introduction
Image
MANY of the contributions to evolutionary thought in the past century can be put in one of two opposed groups. One group emphasizes natural selection as the primary or exclusive creative force. The other minimizes the role of selection in relation to other proposed factors. R. A. Fisher (1930, 1954) showed that many of the proposed alternatives could be discounted with the acceptance of Mendelian genetics and a logical investigation of its relation to selection. Even without Mendelian genetics, Weismann (1904) effectively championed natural selection against some of its rivals of the nineteenth century. His only serious errors are traceable to his ignorance of the Mendelian gene.
The contest was decisively won by natural selection, in my opinion, when by 1932 the classic works of Fisher, Haldane, and Wright had been published. Yet even though this theory may now reign supreme, its realm still supports some opposition, perhaps more than is generally realized. Many recent discussions seem on the surface to conform to the modern Darwinian tradition, but on careful analysis they are found to imply something rather different. I believe that modern opposition, both overt and cryptic, to natural selection, still derives from the same sources that led to the now discredited theories of the nineteenth century. The opposition arises, as Darwin himself observed, not from what reason dictates but from the limits of what the imagination can accept. It is difficult for many people to imagine that an individual’s role in evolution is entirely contained in its contribution to vital statistics. It is difficult to imagine that an acceptable moral order could arise from vital statistics, and difficult to dispense with belief in a moral order in living nature. It is difficult to imagine that the blind play of the genes could produce man. Major difficulties also arise from the current absence of rigorous criteria for deciding whether a given character is adaptive, and, if so, to precisely what is it an adaptation. As I will argue at some length, adaptation is often recognized in purely fortuitous effects, and natural selection is invoked to resolve problems that do not exist. If natural selection is shown to be inadequate for the production of a given adaptation, it is a matter of basic importance to decide whether the adaptation is real.
I hope that this book will help to purge biology of what I regard as unnecessary distractions that impede the progress of evolutionary theory and the development of a disciplined science for analyzing adaptation. It opposes certain of the recently advocated qualifications and additions to the theory of natural selection, such as genetic assimilation, group selection, and cumulative progress in adaptive evolution. It advocates a ground rule that should reduce future distractions and at the same time facilitate the recognition of really justified modifications of the theory. The ground rule—or perhaps doctrine would be a better term—is that adaptation is a special and onerous concept that should be used only where it is really necessary. When it must be recognized, it should be attributed to no higher a level of organization than is demanded by the evidence. In explaining adaptation, one should assume the adequacy of the simplest form of natural selection, that of alternative alleles in Mendelian populations, unless the evidence clearly shows that this theory does not suffice.
Evolutionary adaptation is a phenomenon of pervasive importance in biology. Its central position is emphasized in the current theory of the origin of life, which proposes that the chemical evolution of the hydrosphere produced at one stage an “organic soup” of great chemical complexity, but lifeless in its earliest stages. Among the complexities was the formation of molecules or molecular concentrations that were autocatalytic in some manner. This is a common chemical property. Even a water molecule can catalyze its own synthesis. Only rarely would a molecule be formed that would produce chance variations among its “offspring” and have such variations passed on to the next “generation,” but once such a system arose, natural selection could operate, adaptations would appear, and the Earth would have a biota.
The acceptance of this account of the origin of life implies an acceptance of the key position of the concept of adaptation and at least an abstract criterion whereby life may be defined and recognized. We are dealing with life when we are forced to invoke natural selection to achieve a complete explanation of an observed system. In this sense the principles of chemistry and physics are not enough. At least the one additional postulate of natural selection and its consequence, adaptation, are needed.
This is a very special principle, uniquely biological, and must not be invoked unnecessarily. If asked to explain the trajectory of a falling apple, given an adequate description of its mechanical properties and its initial position and velocity, we would find the principles of mechanics sufficient for a satisfying explanation. They would be as adequate for the apple as for a rock; the living state of the apple would not make this problem biological. If, however, we were asked how the apple acquired its various properties, and why it has these properties instead of others, we would need the theory of natural selection, at least by implication. Only thus could we explain why the apple has a waterproof wax on the outside, and not elsewhere, or why it contains dormant embryos and not something else. We would find that an impressive list of structural details and processes of the apple can be understood as elements of a design for an efficient role in the propagation of the tree from which it came. We attribute the origin and perfection of this design to a long period of selection for effectiveness in this particular role.
The same story could be told for every normal part or activity of every stage in the life history of every species in the biota of the Earth, past or present. For the same reason that it was once effective in the theological “argument from design,” the structure of the vertebrate eye can be used as a dramatic illustration of biological adaptation and the necessity for believing that natural selection for effective vision must have operated throughout the history of the group. In principle, any other organ could be used for illustration although the adaptive design of some parts may not be as immediately convincing as that of the optics of the eye.
This book is based on the assumption that the laws of physical science plus natural selection can furnish a complete explanation for any biological phenomenon, and that these principles can explain adaptation in general and in the abstract and any particular example of an adaptation. This is a common but not a universal belief among biologists. There are many statements in the recent literature that imply that natural selection can account for some of the superficial forms that adaptation can take, but that adaptation as a general property is something elemental and absolute in living organisms. This is what Russell (1945, p. 3) meant when he said that “directive activity” is an “irreducible characteristic of life.” His position was especially clear in his treatment of regeneration, which I will consider on pp. 83-87.
A more recent attack on the adequacy of the simple form of the theory of natural selection is seen in the work of Waddington (1956, 1957, 1959), who conceded that selection is important at every level of adaptive organization, but that it is inadequate by itself and must be supplemented by “genetic assimilation.” Another recent attack on the adequacy of natural selection was made by Darlington (1958), who endowed the chromosomes and genes with an evolutionary spontaneity well beyond what is contained in the traditional concept of chance mutation, and with a long-range foresight that allows preparation for the future needs of the population. I will discuss Waddington’s and Darlington’s work later on.
Even among those who have expressed the opinion that selection is the sole creative force in evolution, there are some inconsistent uses of the concept. With some minor qualifications to be discussed later, it can be said that there is no escape from the conclusion that natural selection, as portrayed in elementary texts and in most of the technical contributions of population geneticists, can only produce adaptations for the genetic survival of individuals. Many biologists have recognized adaptations of a higher than individual level of organization. A few workers have explicitly dealt with this inconsistency, and have urged that the usual picture of natural selection, based on alternative alleles in populations, is not enough. They postulate that selection at the level of alternative populations must also be an important source of adaptation, and that such selection must be recognized to account for adaptations that work for the benefit of groups instead of individuals. I will argue in Chapters 4 through 8 that the recognition of mechanisms for group benefit is based on misinterpretation, and that the higher levels of selection are impotent and not an appreciable factor in the production and maintenance of adaptation.
DIFFICULTIES in interpretation, especially with respect to the many supposedly group-related adaptations, may result from inappropriate criteria for distinguishing adaptations from fortuitous effects. They are also encouraged by imperfections of terminology. Any biological mechanism produces at least one effect that can properly be called its goal: vision for the eye or reproduction and dispersal for the apple. There may also be other effects, such as the apple’s contribution to man’s economy. In many published discussions it is not at all clear whether an author regards a particular effect as the specific function of the causal mechanism or merely as an incidental consequence. In some cases it would appear that he has not appreciated the importance of the distinction. In this book I will adhere to a terminological convention that may help to reduce this difficulty. Whenever I believe that an effect is produced as the function of an adaptation perfected by natural selection to serve that function, I will use terms appropriate to human artifice and conscious design. The designation of something as the means or mechanism for a certain goal or function or purpose will imply that the machinery involved was fashioned by selection for the goal attributed to it. When I do not believe that such a relationship exists I will avoid such terms and use words appropriate to fortuitous relationships such as cause and effect. This is a convention in general use already, perhaps unconsciously, and its appropriateness is supported in discussions by Muller (1948), Pittendrigh (1958), Simpson (1962), and others.
Thus I would say that reproduction and dispersal are the goals or functions or purposes of apples and that the apple is a means or mechanism by which such goals are realized by apple trees. By contrast, the apple’s contributions to Newtonian inspiration and the economy of Kalamazoo County are merely fortuitous effects and of no biological interest.
It is often easy, in practice, to perceive functional design intuitively, but unfortunately disputes sometimes arise as to whether certain effects are produced by design or merely as by-products of some other function. The formulation of practical definitions and sets of objective criteria will not be easy, but it is a problem of great importance and will have to be faced. An excellent beginning was made by Sommerhoff (1950), but apparently no one has built upon the foundation he provided. In this book I will rely on informal arguments as to whether a presumed function is served with sufficient precision, economy, efficiency, etc. to rule out pure chance as an adequate explanation.
A frequently helpful but not infallible rule is to recognize adaptation in organic systems that show a clear analogy with human implements. There are convincing analogies between bird wings and airship wings, between bridge suspensions and skeletal suspensions, between the vascularization of a leaf and the water supply of a city. In all such examples, conscious human goals have an analogy in the biological goal of survival, and similar problems are often resolved by similar mechanisms. Such analogies may forcefully occur to a physiologist at the beginning of an investigation of a structure or process and provide a continuing source of fruitful hypotheses. At other times the purpose of a mechanism may not be apparent initially, and the search for the goal becomes a motivation for further study. Adaptation is assumed in such cases, not on the basis of a demonstrable appropriateness of the means to the end but on the indirect evidence of complexity and constancy. Examples are (or were) the rectal glands of sharks, cypress “knees,” the lateral lines of fishes, the anting of birds, the vocalization of porpoises.
The lateral line is a good illustration. This organ is a conspicuous morphological feature of the great majority of fishes. It shows a structural constancy within taxa and a high degree of histological complexity. In all these features it is analogous to clearly adaptive and demonstrably important structures. The only missing feature, to those who first concerned themselves with this organ, was a convincing story as to how it might make an efficient contribution to survival. Eventually painstaking morphological and physiological studies by many workers demonstrated that the lateral line is a sense organ related in basic mechanism to audition (Dijkgraaf, 1952, 1963). The fact that man does not have this sense organ himself, and had not perfected artificial receptors in any way analogous, was a handicap in the attempt to understand the organ. Its constancy and complexity, however, and the consequent conviction that it must be useful in some way, were incentives and guides in the studies that eventually elucidated the workings of an important sensory mechanism.
I have stressed the importance of the use of such concepts as biological means and ends because I want it clearly understood that I think that such a conceptual framework is the essence of the science of biology. Much of this book, however, will constitute an attack on what I consider unwarranted uses of the concept of adaptation. This biological principle should be used only as a last resort. It should not be invoked when less onerous principles, such as those of physics and chemistry or that of unspecific cause and effect, are sufficient for a complete explanation.
For an example that I assume will not be controversial, consider a flying fish that has just left the water to undertake an aerial flight. It is clear that there is a physiological necessity for it to return to the water very soon; it cannot long survive in air. It is, moreover, a matter of common observation that an aerial glide normally terminates with a return to the sea. Is this the result of a mechanism for getting the fish back into water? Certainly not; we need not invoke the principle of adaptation here. The purely physical principle of gravitation adequately explains why the fish, having gone up, eventually comes down. The real problem is not how it manages to come down, but why it takes it so long to do so. To explain the delay in returning we would be forced to recognize a gliding mechanism of an aerodynamic perfection that must be attributed to natural selection for efficiency in gliding. Here we would be dealing with adaptation.
In this example it would be absurd to recognize an adaptation to achieve the mechanically inevitable. I believe, however, that this is essentially what is done by those who propose that gene mutation is a mechanism for ensuring evolutionary plasticity Whatever the gene may be, it is part of the mundane world and therefore not perfect, in its self-duplication or in any other features. Its occasional alteration is physically inevitable. I will say more about this and related matters on pp. 138-141.
A frequent practice is to recognize adaptation in any recognizable benefit arising from the activities of an organism. I believe that this is an insufficient basis for postulating adaptation and that it has led to some serious errors. A benefit can be the result of chance instead of design. The decision as to the purpose of a mechanism must be based on an examination of the machinery and an argument as to the appropriateness of the means to the end. It cannot be based on value judgments of actual or probable consequences.
This can also be illustrated with an example that will probably not be controversial. Consider a fox on its way to the hen house for the first time after a heavy snowfall. It will probably encounter considerable difficulty in forcing its way through the obstructing material. On subsequent trips, however, it may follow the same path and have a much easier time of it, because of the furrow it made the first time. This formation of a path through the snow may result in a considerable saving of time and food energy for the fox, and such savings may be crucial for survival. Should we therefore regard the paws of a fox as a mechanism for constructing paths through snow? Clearly we should not. It is better, because it avoids the onerous biological principles of adaptation and natural selection, to regard the trail-blazing as an incidental effect of the locomotor machinery, no matter how beneficial it may be. An examination of the legs and feet of the fox forces the conclusion that they are designed for running and walking, not for the packing or removal of snow. At any rate, the concept of design for snow removal would not explain anything in the fox’s appendages that is not as well or better explained by design for locomotion.
Although the construction of a path through the snow should not be considered a function of the activities that have this effect, the fox does adaptively exploit the effect by seeking the same path on successive trips to the hen house. The sensory mechanisms by which it perceives the most familiar and least obstructed routes and the motivation to follow the path of least effort are clearly adaptations.
Sometimes the important effect of an adaptation from man’s point of view may not be its function. Biologically, the brewing of beer is not the function of the glycolytic enzymes of yeast. The production of guano is an important effect, for man’s agricultural interests, of the digestive mechanisms of a number of species of marine birds, but this effect is not their function. Many non-biologists think that it is for their benefit that rattles grow on rattlesnake tails.
I ASSUME that modern biologists would be nearly unanimous in agreeing that the effects mentioned above are not functions. More controversial problems of the same sort will be considered in later chapters. Perhaps one more example can be mentioned here, one that is obviously important but can only be considered rather speculatively. Do we really understand the function of man’s cerebral hypertrophy? The importance of this unique character to civilized man is that it enables nearly everyone to learn at least a simple trade; it enables many of us to enjoy good literature and play a fair hand of bridge; and it enables a few to become great scientists, poets, or generals. The human mind has presumably been responsible for analogous benefits for as long as man has had a culturally based society. Despite the arguments that have been advanced (e.g., Dobzhansky and Montague, 1947; Singer, 1962), I cannot readily accept the idea that advanced mental capabilities have ever been directly favored by selection. There is no re...

Table of contents

  1. Cover Page
  2. Title Page
  3. Copyright Page
  4. Contents
  5. Foreword
  6. Preface (1996)
  7. Preface
  8. 1. Introduction
  9. 2. Natural Selection, Adaptation, and Progress
  10. 3. Natural Selection, Ecology, and Morphogenesis
  11. 4. Group Selection
  12. 5. Adaptations of the Genetic System
  13. 6. Reproductive Physiology and Behavior
  14. 7. Social Adaptations
  15. 8. Other Supposedly Group-Related Adaptations
  16. 9. The Scientific Study of Adaptation
  17. Literature Cited
  18. Index