Princeton Monographs in Philosophy
eBook - ePub

Princeton Monographs in Philosophy

Consciousness and Concernment - Updated Edition

  1. 280 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Princeton Monographs in Philosophy

Consciousness and Concernment - Updated Edition

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

John Locke's theory of personal identity underlies all modern discussion of the nature of persons and selvesā€”yet it is widely thought to be wrong. In this book, Galen Strawson argues that in fact it is Locke's critics who are wrong, and that the famous objections to his theory are invalid. Indeed, far from refuting Locke, they illustrate his fundamental point.Strawson argues that the root error is to take Locke's use of the word "person" as merely a term for a standard persisting thing, like "human being." In actuality, Locke uses "person" primarily as a forensic or legal term geared specifically to questions about praise and blame, punishment and reward. This point is familiar to some philosophers, but its full consequences have not been worked out, partly because of a further error about what Locke means by the word "conscious." When Locke claims that your personal identity is a matter of the actions that you are conscious of, he means the actions that you experience as your own in some fundamental and immediate manner.Clearly and vigorously argued, this is an important contribution both to the history of philosophy and to the contemporary philosophy of personal identity.

Frequently asked questions

Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on ā€œCancel Subscriptionā€ - itā€™s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time youā€™ve paid for. Learn more here.
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlegoā€™s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan youā€™ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, weā€™ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Yes, you can access Princeton Monographs in Philosophy by Galen Strawson in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Philosophy & Philosophy History & Theory. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Chapter One

Introduction

ITā€™S WIDELY HELD that Lockeā€™s account of personal identity, first published in 1694, is circular and inconsistent, and blatantly so. Locke, however, thought long and hard about the matter.1 He discussed it extensively with friends and colleagues, and was a profoundly intelligent, generally very careful, and exceptionally sensible philosopher. He made no foolish error.
Why has he been so misunderstood? I blame certain influential commentators, in whose vanguard one finds one of the worst readers of other philosophers in the history of philosophy: the good Bishop Berkeley. Thomas Reid is also to blame, for although he is a great (and often funny) philosopher, and sometimes accurate enough in his renderings of the views of his predecessors, he enjoys mockery too much to be reliable, heā€™s too free with the word ā€œabsurd,ā€ and his misreading of Lockeā€™s views on personal identity, which follows Berkeleyā€™s, is spectacular.2 Bishop Butler is the other main reprobate, although the objection to Locke for which he is well known is not his, having been put by John Sergeant in 1697 and by Henry Lee in 1702, among others.3
History has designated Butler and Reid as the main representatives of the circularity and inconsistency objections, and their influence has been such that few since then have had a chance to read what Locke wrote without prejudice. The tide of misunderstanding was already high in 1769, when Edmund Law provided an essentially correct account of Lockeā€™s position in his Defence of Mr. Lockeā€™s Opinion Concerning Personal Identity. His intervention was, however, little noticed.
The extent of the misreading of Locke is remarkable. Edmund Law judged it an ā€œendlessā€ task to ā€œunravel all the futile sophisms and false suppositions, that have been introduced into the present questionā€; he ā€œendeavoured [only] to obviate such as appeared most material, and account for themā€ (1769: 36). If, however, one embarks on Lockeā€™s discussion confident that his view will not contain any glaring error, it becomes hard to understand how he can have been so misread for so long. For he makes his central point extremely plain, and he does so, it must be said, over and over and over again. To read the wonderfully fluent and imaginative text of 2.27 of An Essay concerning Human Understanding is to see how familiar Locke is with his material, how easy in exposition he is, how he has thought through the objections, and how much heā€™s enjoying himself. Locke likes to vary his terms, and is sometimes loose of expression by modern lights, but not in a way that makes it possible for a moderately careful reader to misread him in the manner of Butler, Berkeley, Reid, and many who have followed them.4
The following essay records my line of thought as I read and reread, and sometimes struggled with, Lockeā€™s chapter. I spend the next several sections introducing a number of distinctions that I believe to be useful, extracting some central notions for inspectionā€”notably person, consciousness, concernmentā€”before returning them to context. The discussion lacks a standard expository structure, and itā€™s not meant to be introductory. I assume basic familiarity with Lockeā€™s text, and criticize other accounts of it only indirectly. I think that almost all the elements of a correct view of his theory of personal identity are now to be found in the writings of a few Locke scholars, among whom Udo Thiel stands out,5 but misunderstanding is still widespread in the philosophical community as a whole.
The interpretative situation was hardly better in the eighteenth century, as just observed.6 Law was honestly amazed that Locke had been so ā€œmiserably misunderstoodā€ā€”that so many ā€œingenious writersā€ had been ā€œso marvellously mistakenā€ about Lockeā€™s views on personal identity, and had engaged in so much irrelevant and ā€œegregious triflingā€ on the matter (1769: 23, 21). Law cites, as an ā€œextraordinary instanceā€ (p. 22) of this trifling, the inconsistency argument that Berkeley gave in his Alciphron (1732), and for a version of which Reid later became famous (see p. 53 below).7
The root cause of the misunderstanding, perhaps, is the tendency of most of Lockeā€™s readers to take the term ā€œpersonā€ as if it were only a sortal term of a standard kind, i.e. a term for a standard temporal continuant, like ā€œhuman beingā€ or ā€œthinking thing,ā€ without paying sufficient attention to the fact that Locke is focusing on the use of ā€œpersonā€ as a ā€œforensicā€ term (Ā§26), i.e. a term that finds its principal use in contexts in which questions about the attribution of responsibility (praise and blame, punishment and reward) are foremost. No doubt itā€™s natural enough to take ā€œpersonā€ only in the first way, but this doesnā€™t excuse the perversity of doing so when reading what Locke says, and says again and again. (The common mistake of thinking that Locke means memory by ā€œconsciousnessā€ is, relatively speaking, a smaller mistake.) That said, Locke must also bear some of the responsibility for the misreadingā€”a point addressed by Law in the brief appendix to his Defence.
1 His central thought on the question was in place by 1683; see Ayers 1990: 2.255.
2 Berkeley 1732: 304ā€“5, Reid 1785: Ā§3.6. Reid also follows Berkeley in mistakenly attributing to Locke the view that secondary qualities are in the mind (1764: Ā§6.6). He makes many other such errors.
3 Butler 1736: 441. Sergeant picked up the objection for which Butler is known from a debate in which Robert South (1693) made it validly against a proposal by William Sherlock (1690). See Ayers 1990: 2.257, 269; Thiel 1998: 875ā€“77, 898. Leibniz does not make it in his Nouveaux Essais, contrary to the initial appearance (c. 1704: 236 [2.27.9]).
4 Mackie sufficiently answers the Butler objection in Problems from Locke (1976: 186ā€“87).
5 See e.g. Thiel 1998, 2011.
6 See Thiel 2011, chap. 4.
7 ā€œMany historians of philosophy, with all their intended praise,Ā .Ā .Ā .Ā attribute mere nonsenseĀ .Ā .Ā .Ā to past philosophers. They are incapable of recognizing, beyond what the philosophers actually said, what they really meant to sayā€ (Kant 1790: 160). ā€œIf we take single passages, torn from their context, and compare them with one another, contradictions are not likely to be lacking, especially in a work that is written with any freedom of expressionĀ .Ā .Ā .; but they are easily resolved by those who have mastered the idea of the wholeā€ (Kant 1787: Bxliv).

Chapter Two

ā€œPersonā€

THE WORD ā€œPERSONā€ has a double use, both now and in the seventeenth century. In its most common everyday use, today as in the seventeenth century, it simply denotes a human being considered as a whole, a person1, as I will say. Its next most common everyday use, which I will call the person2 use, is the one that allows us to say, of a single human being, ā€œSheā€™s not the same person anymore,ā€ or ā€œHeā€™s become a completely different person.ā€ When Henry James writes, of one of his early novels, ā€œI think of . . . the masterpiece in question . . . as the work of quite another person than myself . . . a rich . . . relation, say, who . . . suffers me still to claim a shy fourth cousinship,ā€1 he knows perfectly well that heā€™s the same human being (person1) as the author of that book, but he doesnā€™t feel heā€™s the same person2 as the author of that book, and we all know what he means, even though the notion of a person2 is not a precise one. James is using the word ā€œpersonā€ in the familiar way that allows one to distinguish the person or self that one is from the human being that one is considered as a whole. His claim is that he no longer relates to his early novel in such a way as to feel that heā€”he who is here now in the person2 senseā€”is its author.
The current everyday person2 use of ā€œpersonā€ is closely connected to the notion of personality, but we ordinarily think of personality as a property of a creature, a property that can change, and not as itself a thing of any sort; whereas when we use ā€œpersonā€ to mean a person2, we naturally take it to denote a thing or entity that isnā€™t just a property. We take it to denote a persisting subject of experience, a self; we donā€™t feel weā€™re using the word just as a way of talking about personality, where personality is a mere property of a person1. When people say, ā€œShe isnā€™t the same person anymore,ā€ using ā€œpersonā€ in the person2 sense, they tend to feel that theyā€™re saying something more than merely that a person1ā€™s personality has changed, although they may also allow a sense in which this is all that has happened.
At the same time, we donā€™t feel obliged to come up with clear identity conditions for these supposed entities, these persons in the person2 sense. For while people sometimes look back to a past time and say categorically, ā€œIā€™m not the same person any more,ā€ i.e. not the same person2, they donā€™t usually think thereā€™s some sharp dividing line between the person2 in the past and the person2 present now (except, perhaps, in rare cases, e.g. those that involve a radical conversion).
I think that the person2 use of ā€œpersonā€ gives us some useful insight into Lockeā€™s use of ā€œperson,ā€ because itā€™s related, although itā€™s not the same. A Lockean person, a Person, as Iā€™ll say, marking my employment of the term in his sense with a capital letter, is certainly not a person1, because a Person doesnā€™t have the same identity conditions as a person1. A person1 is simply a human being (a man, in Lockeā€™s terminology, in which ā€œmanā€ refers equally to male and female). Itā€™s a human being considered as a thing of such a kind that same human being doesnā€™t immediately entail same Person. In Ā§15 Locke famously and explicitly considers imaginary cases in which Persons switch human bodies: cases in which one has to do with the same man (human being) even though one doesnā€™t have to do with the same Person, and, conversely, cases in which one has to do with the same Person even though one doesnā€™t have to do with the same man (Ā§15). (Note that Lockeā€™s functional definition of Personhood (see chapter 8) doesnā€™t restrict Personhood t...

Table of contents

  1. Cover
  2. Half title
  3. Title
  4. Copyright
  5. Contents
  6. Preface
  7. Chapter 1: Introduction
  8. Chapter 2: ā€œPersonā€
  9. Chapter 3: ā€œPerson . . . is a forensic termā€
  10. Chapter 4: Concernment
  11. Chapter 5: Consciousness
  12. Chapter 6: ā€œConsciousness . . . is inseparable from thinkingā€
  13. Chapter 7: ā€œFrom the insideā€
  14. Chapter 8: ā€œPersonā€ā€”Lockeā€™s Definition
  15. Chapter 9: Consciousness Is Not Memory
  16. Chapter 10: Personal Identity
  17. Chapter 11: Psychological Connectedness
  18. Chapter 12: Transition (Butler Dismissed)
  19. Chapter 13: ā€œBut next . . . ā€: Personal Identity without Substantial Continuity
  20. Chapter 14: ā€œAnd therefore . . . ā€: [I]-transfers, [Ag]-transfers, [P]-transfers
  21. Chapter 15: ā€œA fatal error of theirsā€
  22. Chapter 16: A Fatal Error of Lockeā€™s?
  23. Chapter 17: Circularity?
  24. Chapter 18: The Distinction between [P] and [S]
  25. Chapter 19: Concernment and Repentance
  26. Chapter 20: Conclusion
  27. Postface
  28. Appendix 1: ā€œOf Identity and Diversityā€ by John Locke
  29. Appendix 2: A Defence of Mr. Lockeā€™s Opinion Concerning Personal Identity by Edmund Law
  30. References
  31. Index