Einstein, Tagore and the Nature of Reality
eBook - ePub

Einstein, Tagore and the Nature of Reality

Partha Ghose

  1. 238 Seiten
  2. English
  3. ePUB (handyfreundlich)
  4. Über iOS und Android verfĂŒgbar
eBook - ePub

Einstein, Tagore and the Nature of Reality

Partha Ghose

Angaben zum Buch
Buchvorschau
Inhaltsverzeichnis
Quellenangaben

Über dieses Buch

The nature of reality has been a long-debated issue among scientists and philosophers. In 1930, Rabindranath Tagore and Albert Einstein had a long conversation on the nature of reality. This conversation has been widely quoted and discussed by scientists, philosophers and scholars from the literary world. The important question that Tagore and Einstein discussed was whether the world is a unity dependent on humanity, or the world is a reality independent on the human factor. Einstein took the stand adopted by Western philosophers and mathematicians, namely that reality is something independent of the mind and the human factor. Tagore, on the other hand, adopted the opposite view. Nevertheless, both Einstein and Tagore claimed to be realists despite the fundamental differences between their conceptions of reality. Where does the difference lie? Can it be harmonized at some deeper level? Can Wittgenstein, for example, be a bridge between the two views? This collection of essays explores these two fundamentally different conceptions of the nature of reality from the perspectives of theories of space-time, quantum theory, general philosophy of science, cognitive science and mathematics.

HĂ€ufig gestellte Fragen

Wie kann ich mein Abo kĂŒndigen?
Gehe einfach zum Kontobereich in den Einstellungen und klicke auf „Abo kĂŒndigen“ – ganz einfach. Nachdem du gekĂŒndigt hast, bleibt deine Mitgliedschaft fĂŒr den verbleibenden Abozeitraum, den du bereits bezahlt hast, aktiv. Mehr Informationen hier.
(Wie) Kann ich BĂŒcher herunterladen?
Derzeit stehen all unsere auf MobilgerĂ€te reagierenden ePub-BĂŒcher zum Download ĂŒber die App zur VerfĂŒgung. Die meisten unserer PDFs stehen ebenfalls zum Download bereit; wir arbeiten daran, auch die ĂŒbrigen PDFs zum Download anzubieten, bei denen dies aktuell noch nicht möglich ist. Weitere Informationen hier.
Welcher Unterschied besteht bei den Preisen zwischen den AboplÀnen?
Mit beiden AboplÀnen erhÀltst du vollen Zugang zur Bibliothek und allen Funktionen von Perlego. Die einzigen Unterschiede bestehen im Preis und dem Abozeitraum: Mit dem Jahresabo sparst du auf 12 Monate gerechnet im Vergleich zum Monatsabo rund 30 %.
Was ist Perlego?
Wir sind ein Online-Abodienst fĂŒr LehrbĂŒcher, bei dem du fĂŒr weniger als den Preis eines einzelnen Buches pro Monat Zugang zu einer ganzen Online-Bibliothek erhĂ€ltst. Mit ĂŒber 1 Million BĂŒchern zu ĂŒber 1.000 verschiedenen Themen haben wir bestimmt alles, was du brauchst! Weitere Informationen hier.
UnterstĂŒtzt Perlego Text-zu-Sprache?
Achte auf das Symbol zum Vorlesen in deinem nÀchsten Buch, um zu sehen, ob du es dir auch anhören kannst. Bei diesem Tool wird dir Text laut vorgelesen, wobei der Text beim Vorlesen auch grafisch hervorgehoben wird. Du kannst das Vorlesen jederzeit anhalten, beschleunigen und verlangsamen. Weitere Informationen hier.
Ist Einstein, Tagore and the Nature of Reality als Online-PDF/ePub verfĂŒgbar?
Ja, du hast Zugang zu Einstein, Tagore and the Nature of Reality von Partha Ghose im PDF- und/oder ePub-Format sowie zu anderen beliebten BĂŒchern aus Physical Sciences & Physics. Aus unserem Katalog stehen dir ĂŒber 1 Million BĂŒcher zur VerfĂŒgung.

Information

Verlag
Routledge
Jahr
2016
ISBN
9781134859412
Auflage
1
Thema
Physics

1 Einstein, the reality of space and the action–reaction principle

Harvey R. Brown and Dennis Lehmkuhl
For me it is an absurdity to ascribe physical properties to ‘space’.
Albert Einstein to Ernst Mach1
That a real thing has to be presupposed as the cause for the preference of inertial systems over non-inertial systems is a fact that physicists have only come to understand in recent years.
Einstein2

Introduction

It was striking in the 2012 seminar ‘The Nature of Reality’ at the Indian Institute of Advanced Study, Shimla, that so many speakers independently referred to the quip by Albert Einstein in his 1930 dialogue with Rabindranath Tagore that he, Einstein, was more religious than the great Bengali polymath. Of course, what Einstein was getting at is the fact that at the heart of the physical sciences, at least as he saw it, is a commitment to the reality of an external world whose goings-on are governed by laws that contain no fundamental reference to conscious agents, and in particular to human observers. For Tagore, all truth is human truth, if one is to take his claims literally.3 For Einstein, the ultimate truth about the physical world transcends the human realm. Einstein was a ‘realist’, but his realism was of a modest, or non-metaphysical, kind. It is the job of physicists, he argued, to come up with models of a mind-independent reality that are explanatory of our phenomenological experiences of natural regularities, within the laboratory and without. However, whether such models, when judged successful, correspond to the way the world ‘really’ is, is a question Einstein thought best to leave aside. There are some philosophical questions for which Einstein thought the best response is a smile, and this was one of them. But Einstein stressed that even this weak, pragmatic take on truth involved a leap of faith. He made it clear, particularly in his 1949 Autobiographical Notes, that Nature’s connivance in allowing for the success in the scientific venture as he conceived it could not be a foregone conclusion.4 It was conceivable for Einstein that the mind, say, could be the bedrock of reality, but he felt that there was no good reason to start with that premise, and good reasons not to. Realism for Einstein was more a programme than a doctrine; it was a dogma about which he was careful not to be dogmatic.
Several years after the development of his 1915 general theory of relativity (GR), Einstein began to stress that physical space, or rather, the metric field, not only constitutes a fundamental, autonomous element of objective reality, it plays a causal role in accounting for the inertial motion of bodies.5
He compared this with the active role of space in the cases of Newtonian mechanics (NM) and special relativity (SR). In these cases, such putative action is clearly not reciprocated by bodies or fields: they do not act back on space-time structure, so the so-called action–reaction principle is violated. In contrast, in his relativistic theory of gravity (GR), Einstein was to see the vindication of the principle. The metric can have a dynamical life of its own in the absence of matter fields (though, as we shall see, this goes against Einstein’s original expectations), but, more to the point, when the latter exist, the metric affects and is affected by them.6
Whether Einstein’s reasoning is correct is open to doubt. What is debatable is not the claim that GR is consistent with the action–reaction principle; it is the claim that the older theories involving absolute space-time structures are not. More specifically, it is the assertion that such structures act in the relevant sense. Clearly, if they do not (as Newton himself argued regarding space; see below), then the fact that material bodies do not act back on them constitutes no violation of the action–reaction principle. The case for the view that absolute space-time structures of the kind that appear in NM and SR are not fundamental causal entities in their own right, but rather codifications of certain bare facts concerning the movement of bodies or behaviour of fields has been made a number of times, in different ways.7 One curious instance is arguably in a letter Einstein himself wrote to Ernst Mach in late 1913;8 another is due to Moritz Schlick in correspondence with Einstein in 1920.9 We shall return to the second case below; it turns out to be directly related to the main concern of this chapter, which is, why would Einstein start systematically emphasising the action–reaction principle in his defence of GR only in the 1920s?

The action–reaction principle

It is a venerable tradition in natural philosophy to assert that a substance is the seat of actions on other substances, and in turn subject to the actions of these other substances: the action–reaction principle (AR). In his pre-Principia manuscript De Gravitatione et Aequipondio Fluidorum10 (or De Grav for short), Newton insisted that natural philosophers tacitly understand substance as an entity that acts on things, even if they don’t state this explicitly. He distinguished two kinds of action, one that stimulates the perceptions of thinking beings, and one between material bodies, as in collisions. (Later, he would extend this second kind to action at a distance.)11 This distinction today seems of little import, and the fundamental premise, that it is interactions between systems that count in physics and not their intrinsic properties, is close to the heart of the ‘structural realist’ position that has been much discussed in recent years in the philosophy of science. Be that as it may, Newton is clearly appealing to a principle in the De Grav that is more fundamental and general than what he would later designate as his third law of motion in the Principia—though the latter is often referred to as the law of action–reaction. (We shall see shortly how space, for Newton, is a kind of exception to this fundamental principle.)
Leibniz, whose views on the nature of space and time were so different from Newton’s, nonetheless shared the same intuition. In fact, when defining substance as that which acts and can be acted upon, he understood that he was adopting the view of the scholastics.12 Caution must be exercised, however, in attributing AR, as it is standardly understood today, to Leibniz. In the light of his doctrine of pre-established harmony, the meaning of causation, or rather interaction, within his deep metaphysics is almost certainly at odds with those views adopted by the majority of current metaphysicians,13 not to mention physicists—and its scope is still controversial.14
If there is a questionable aspect of AR, it is less the claim that substances act (how otherwise could their existence be known to us?) than the notion that they are necessarily acted back upon, that action must be reciprocal. If all substances act, they do so in relation to other substances; these other substances therefore cannot be immune from external influences. Now it might seem arbitrary on a priori grounds to imagine that the ‘sensitivity’ of such substances is not universal. That is to say, it might seem arbitrary to suppose that not all substances react to others. But no such abstract qualms can be entirely compelling; Nature must have the last say.
Nowadays, it is well known in the foundations of physics that the de Broglie-Bohm (‘pilot wave’) interpretation of quantum mechanics, in its standard form, involves a dynamical agent (the wave function) that acts on corpuscles (point particles) but is not acted back upon, at least by the corpuscles. It is noteworthy that David Bohm himself clearly found such violation of AR uncomfortable in his (first) 1952 formulation of the theory and attempted to remedy it, as have others after him.15 While defenders of the original pilot-wave theory can legitimately argue that AR is not a logical necessity, others see its violation as a blemish in the theory.16 It seems fair to say that currently within the physics community, there is no consensus supporting the failure of AR in quantum theory.
For his part, Einstein himself had already stated in 1922 that it is ‘contrary to the mode of scientific thinking to conceive of a thing 
 which acts itself, but which cannot be acted upon’.17 The object of Einstein’s ire in 1922 was NM and his own creation, SR. Yet there is no hint in his writings around the time of the development of SR in 1905 that Einstein considered either of these theories to incorporate a violation of the action–reaction principle; at any rate, the explicit condemnation came later. Why? In all probability, because it was part of an honest sales pitch for GR, his greatest and most radical contribution to science, after Einstein was reluctantly forced to concede, because of results by de Sitter, that the theory as a whole was not consistent with ‘Mach’s Principle’, even though special solutions are. It seems that this change of tack on Einstein’s part was consolidated in the mentioned 1920 correspondence with the physicist-philosopher Moritz Schlick.
But before examining the evolution of Einstein’s views on the causal role of space-time, it is worth briefly visiting Newton’s own views on the nature of absolute space, especially as expounded in the De Grav. This manuscript contains a hard-hitting critique of Descartes’s relational theory of motion and the positive reasons why Newton felt compelled to posit the existence of absolute space; these important lines of reasoning have been discussed extensively in the literature.18 What concerns us is Newton’s insistence that space, despite its reality, does not act on either our sense organs (which is patent) or on our bodies. If it is a substance, it is by Newton’s own reasoning sui generis in its causal inefficacy, and ultimately, Newton had no interest in classifying it as either substance or accident.19
When, in the context of discussions relevant to this chapter, Newtonian space is assigned a causal role, it is usually to account for inertia, i.e., the privileged existence of inertial frames, or equivalently, the special motions of force-free bodies. In the De Grav, Newton explicitly renounced such a role. He stated that the reason why projectiles that are not being acted upon by other bodies moving in straight lines and at uniform speed is precisely that space has no ability to help or hinder any change in the motion of bodies!20

Einstein on absolute space

Einstein and Mach

Einstein’s tortuous road to the 1915 field equations of his unhappily named general theory of relativity followed a number of fundamental, partially overlapping, conceptual signposts, apart from th...

Inhaltsverzeichnis

  1. Cover
  2. Title
  3. Copyright
  4. Contents
  5. List of figures
  6. Preface
  7. Introduction
  8. 1 Einstein, the reality of space and the action–reaction principle
  9. 2 The hole argument and the nature of space-time: a critical review from a constructivist perspective
  10. 3 Quantum information and reality, especially the reality of the past and future
  11. 4 Einstein and Tagore, Newton and Blake, Everett and Bohr: the dual nature of reality
  12. 5 Toward relational reality: from Einstein and Tagore to Gaudiya Vaishnava Vedanta
  13. 6 Science, poiesis and visions of reality
  14. 7 Physical reality and the unobservables of physical nature
  15. 8 High-energy physics and post-empiricism
  16. 9 Cognitive constraints on the perception of reality
  17. 10 Embodied cognition and the constructivist view of reality
  18. 11 Incompleteness theorems and realities: a tale of three great thinkers
  19. Appendix 1: the Tagore-Einstein conversation on the nature of reality
  20. Appendix 2: the Tagore-Einstein dialogue on youth, causality and music
  21. Contributors
  22. Index
Zitierstile fĂŒr Einstein, Tagore and the Nature of Reality

APA 6 Citation

Ghose, P. (2016). Einstein, Tagore and the Nature of Reality (1st ed.). Taylor and Francis. Retrieved from https://www.perlego.com/book/1630562/einstein-tagore-and-the-nature-of-reality-pdf (Original work published 2016)

Chicago Citation

Ghose, Partha. (2016) 2016. Einstein, Tagore and the Nature of Reality. 1st ed. Taylor and Francis. https://www.perlego.com/book/1630562/einstein-tagore-and-the-nature-of-reality-pdf.

Harvard Citation

Ghose, P. (2016) Einstein, Tagore and the Nature of Reality. 1st edn. Taylor and Francis. Available at: https://www.perlego.com/book/1630562/einstein-tagore-and-the-nature-of-reality-pdf (Accessed: 14 October 2022).

MLA 7 Citation

Ghose, Partha. Einstein, Tagore and the Nature of Reality. 1st ed. Taylor and Francis, 2016. Web. 14 Oct. 2022.