Why Race Still Matters
eBook - ePub

Why Race Still Matters

Alana Lentin

  1. English
  2. ePUB (apto para móviles)
  3. Disponible en iOS y Android
eBook - ePub

Why Race Still Matters

Alana Lentin

Detalles del libro
Vista previa del libro
Índice
Citas

Información del libro

'Why are you making this about race?' This question is repeated daily in public and in the media. Calling someone racist in these times of mounting white supremacy seems to be a worse insult than racism itself. In our supposedly post-racial society, surely it's time to stop talking about race? This powerful refutation is a call to notice not just when and how race still matters but when, how and why it is said not to matter. Race critical scholar Alana Lentin argues that society is in urgent need of developing the skills of racial literacy, by jettisoning the idea that race is something and unveiling what race does as a key technology of modern rule, hidden in plain sight. Weaving together international examples, she eviscerates misconceptions such as reverse racism and the newfound acceptability of 'race realism', bursts the 'I'm not racist, but' justification, complicates the common criticisms of identity politics and warns against using concerns about antisemitism as a proxy for antiracism. Dominant voices in society suggest we are talking toomuchabout race. Lentin shows why we actually need to talk about it more and how in doing so we can act to make it matter less.

Preguntas frecuentes

¿Cómo cancelo mi suscripción?
Simplemente, dirígete a la sección ajustes de la cuenta y haz clic en «Cancelar suscripción». Así de sencillo. Después de cancelar tu suscripción, esta permanecerá activa el tiempo restante que hayas pagado. Obtén más información aquí.
¿Cómo descargo los libros?
Por el momento, todos nuestros libros ePub adaptables a dispositivos móviles se pueden descargar a través de la aplicación. La mayor parte de nuestros PDF también se puede descargar y ya estamos trabajando para que el resto también sea descargable. Obtén más información aquí.
¿En qué se diferencian los planes de precios?
Ambos planes te permiten acceder por completo a la biblioteca y a todas las funciones de Perlego. Las únicas diferencias son el precio y el período de suscripción: con el plan anual ahorrarás en torno a un 30 % en comparación con 12 meses de un plan mensual.
¿Qué es Perlego?
Somos un servicio de suscripción de libros de texto en línea que te permite acceder a toda una biblioteca en línea por menos de lo que cuesta un libro al mes. Con más de un millón de libros sobre más de 1000 categorías, ¡tenemos todo lo que necesitas! Obtén más información aquí.
¿Perlego ofrece la función de texto a voz?
Busca el símbolo de lectura en voz alta en tu próximo libro para ver si puedes escucharlo. La herramienta de lectura en voz alta lee el texto en voz alta por ti, resaltando el texto a medida que se lee. Puedes pausarla, acelerarla y ralentizarla. Obtén más información aquí.
¿Es Why Race Still Matters un PDF/ePUB en línea?
Sí, puedes acceder a Why Race Still Matters de Alana Lentin en formato PDF o ePUB, así como a otros libros populares de Social Sciences y Demography. Tenemos más de un millón de libros disponibles en nuestro catálogo para que explores.

Información

Editorial
Polity
Año
2020
ISBN
9781509535729
Edición
1
Categoría
Social Sciences
Categoría
Demography

1
Race beyond Social Construction

Useful though it may once have been for denaturalizing race, the well-worn piety that race is a social construct (with exculpatory quotation marks to prove it) does not get us very far. It simply begs further questions: ‘Under what circumstances was (or is) race constructed?’; ‘Has race been differently constructed under different circumstances?’, and so on.
Patrick Wolfe, ‘Race and the Trace of History’ (2011: 274)
In 2017, Meryl Streep presided over the jury of the Berlin Film Festival.1 During a press conference and in answer to a question from an Egyptian journalist, she remarked,
I don’t know very much about, honestly, the Middle East, ... and yet I’ve played a lot of different people from a lot of different cultures. And the thing I notice is that we’re all – I mean there is a core of humanity that travels right through every culture, and after all, we’re all from Africa originally, you know? We’re all Berliners, we’re all Africans, really. (Streep 2016)
Although she denies this, Streep’s comments were widely understood to be an explanation for the all-white composition of the film festival jury. ‘We’re all Africans, really’, is a particularly dismissive response to the observation of the structural inequalities that result in all-white conference panels, white-dominated media, the white curriculum, and the overwhelming whiteness of the majority of parliaments in countries whose population is increasingly multiracial.
Speaking clearly about race is difficult, as this episode shows. It always invites multiple and competing readings. Because of its inherent instability, lending itself to myriad interpretations, race is a particularly polyvalent term or, as mentioned in the Introduction, a ‘sliding signifier’ (S. Hall 2017). The body of knowledge you may be thinking about might be completely different to the political implications I have in mind or separate again from the feeling hearing ‘We’re all Africans, really’, spoken by Meryl Streep might have for another person, a victim of modern-day enslavement in Libya, say. But even the comment itself contains several layers. The article Streep wrote in defence of her remarks emphasized the cultural richness of the Berlin Film Festival, which screens films from around the world. She explained that the comment was made in response to a question about Middle Eastern cinema. So, while it seems strange that what came to Streep’s mind was a genetic study about DNA and human evolution, it reveals that talk of race and talk of culture are regularly exchanged in commonsense discourse. The reaching for the standard colourblind response – we are all one, human race – papers over the undeniable fact that no number of films from around the world overcomes the persistence of white domination over the Eurocentric culture industry. It is telling too that the preceding words – ‘We’re all Berliners’ – a repurposing of the words of another American in Berlin, John F. Kennedy, were not seized upon in the same way. We know that we are precisely not all Berliners; some of us are being confined in camps on the outer fringes of eastern Europe built to stop too many people from becoming Berliners.
Biological ideas of race never completely disappeared from either scientific or public discourse. However, the more apparent resurgence of racial science, and the link to what its popular proponents call ‘race realism’, is apparent in genetic science and medicine (Roberts 2012) and in the development of technologies of security and surveillance for the control both of ‘unruly’ racialized groups (Vitale and Jefferson 2016) and of migrants and asylum seekers at the highly policed borders of the Global North (Andersson 2016). It is also a powerful narrative that propels the white supremacist right forward, attaching itself to the conspiracies of ‘white genocide’ and ‘great replacement’ that construe ethnonational populations as organically weakened by culturally inferior imposters, most prominently today Muslims (Camus 2015). Brenton Tarrant, the white supremacist terrorist who murdered fifty-one Muslim worshippers in Christchurch in March 2019, wrote a manifesto entitled ‘The Great Replacement’ in which he interviewed himself on the motives for the attack: ‘Was the attack anti-immigration in origin? Yes, beyond all doubt, anti-immigration, anti-ethnic replacement and anti-cultural replacement.’
In this chapter, I make the case that the current terms available in the public sphere to discuss race are not fit for purpose. As I stated in the Introduction, racial literacy is not a feature of western educational systems, whose remit is largely to recreate the Eurocentric nation-state in its own image. Race and racism, therefore, remain special interest subjects. We are not, then, equipped with the tools necessary for challenging racial pseudoscience discourse. For example, there was barely a murmur when, in October 2019, Australian Home Affairs Minister Peter Dutton proposed that DNA testing is required to verify the Australian citizenship claims of women currently trapped in Syria after the fall of the Islamic State (SBS 2019). Of course, there is no link between DNA and citizenship, yet what Dutton’s statement reveals is that it is easy to conflate the two because both are commonly understood to be ‘about race’.
The current terms available in the public sphere to discuss race are not fit for purpose.
In the next chapter, I discuss the relationship between racial structures and racist practices such as violence, discrimination, and exclusion in greater detail. For now, I suggest that the failure to connect racism to race as a regime of power allows singular definitions of race as biological categories to define public conversations. Because of the failure to unearth the many cross-cutting functions of race as a regime of power, we have come to see eighteenth- and nineteenth-century pseudoscientific racial classifications as synonymous with race in general. This has two consequences which are relevant to our discussion here. First, we have been unable to interrogate how race is assembled from a multiplicity of rationales, including the geographical, the religious, the cultural, the visual, and the biological, all of which intersect with other regimes of power, most significantly gender. Second, this has paradoxically allowed a biological understanding of race to be retained, particularly within scientific and medical discourses, with a flow-on effect on everyday ways of understanding and talking about human difference.
One of the most serious problems for us today is that what I have referred to as the ‘silence about race’ has allowed biological race, in a similar fashion to gender determinism, to become a currency on the ‘marketplace of ideas’ (A. Lentin 2008). Though it never left, with the renewed élan of white supremacy, race seems to have found new wings in these ‘post-postracial’ times, well after the waning of the racial optimism of the early years of the Obama era. In the rest of this chapter, I explore the context in which ideas of racial science are resurgent. I argue that we must find ways of countering them that go beyond what I shall suggest is the insufficient proposition that race is a social construct that has no basis in scientific fact. This is a truism that only takes us so far, and which risks misappropriation by those with anything but antiracist intentions. I query how we can retain the conceptual utility of race as something that is necessary to understand in the aim of achieving better historical, political, and sociological literacy, while rejecting the false premises of racial science. These inquiries might help us makes sense of the persistent political and social impact that race continues to have.

Eugenics redux

In May 2018, the Monash Bioethics Review published an article by a University of San Diego assistant professor of philosophy, Jonathan Anomaly, titled ‘Defending Eugenics’, in which he argues that ‘future people would be better off if people with heritable traits that we value had a greater proportion of children’ (Anomaly 2018: 25). Anomaly attempts to avoid the charge of racism by arguing that the virtues of eugenics should not be obscured by the ends to which these ideas were put by the Nazis. However, it is impossible to dissociate an idea from the context in which it emerged and the practices to which it led.2 The article came to my notice via a tweet from author and academic Sunny Singh on 12 November that year, the same day as the announcement of a new academic journal, the Journal of Controversial Ideas, founded under the editorship of Peter Singer, Jeff McMahan, and Francesca Minerva, which would allow academics to publish controversial ideas pseudonymously. Peter Singer, the Australian utilitarian bioethicist well known for his support for animal liberation, is also on the editorial board of the Monash Bioethics Review. It is not irrelevant that Singer has expressed disturbing views on race (Grey and Cleffie 2015). In an interview with the African-American philosopher George Yancy, he compared what he calls ‘speciesism’ to chattel-slavery, and argued that racism is mainly a past phenomenon and that discrimination against animals is more insidious (Yancy 2015).
During a BBC Radio 4 documentary, University Unchallenged, about so-called ‘viewpoint diversity’ in academia, co-editor Jeff McMahan, a professor of moral philosophy at Oxford, explained the need for the journal was due to ‘greater inhibition on university campuses about taking certain positions for fear of what will happen’ (Rosenbaum 2018). The complaint about the lack of diversity of perspective on university campuses has become ‘a central trope of the disingenuous both-sidesism’ of those who argue that too much concern with racism, sexism, or queerphobia is propelling a crisis of academic free speech (Mitchell 2018). According to those who bemoan a lack of ‘viewpoint diversity’, conservative or right-wing ideas are stifled by what they see as the overwhelming dominance of ‘liberal’ perspectives among teaching and administrative staff at UK and US colleges. According to one ‘conservative-leaning professor’, this liberal dominance hinders student learning and ‘threatens the free and open exchange of ideas’ (Abrams 2018). In fact, there are many attacks on academic free speech, but in the main they do not come from ‘liberals’. For example, Murdoch University in Western Australia took a case against one of its academics for blowing the whistle on the treatment of international students in 2019 (Knaus 2019).
Jonathan Anomaly also couches his article in these ‘viewpoint diversity’ terms, a frame in which racial ideas are presented as purportedly neutral, and just another topic of debate (Reiheld 2018). Proponents of such theories calls themselves ‘race realists’, and argue that there is nothing nefarious in research that finds that different groups in the population can be genetically ranked on a range of indices. The recent emboldening of the ‘race realists’ should not lead us to ignore the fact that, despite consensus within the international community that ‘current biological knowledge does not permit us to impute cultural achievements to differences in genetic potential’ (UNESCO 1968: 270), the use of racial taxonomy in biology and medicine has never stopped (Carter 2007; Fields and Fields 2012). Eugenicist ideas and practices did not completely exit the mainstream despite being disavowed after the Nazi Holocaust.3 For example, the 1994 book The Bell Curve, which argued that Black people have low IQ, has had enormous influence (Roberts 2015).
The book’s co-author, Charles Murray, is often claimed to be silenced, particularly following the 2017 protests against him at Middlebury College (Reilly 2017). However, Murray is in fact ‘ensconced at the center of the conservative policy establishment as an emeritus scholar at the American Enterprise Institute. In 2016, he won the Bradley Prize, a prestigious conservative award that carries a $250,000 stipend. He regularly publishes op-eds in the Wall Street Journal’ (Yglesias 2018).
Nevertheless, an important key to understanding today’s circulation and proliferation of nineteenth-century ideas about the purported genetic inferiority of people racialized as non-white is that their proponents are presented as brave, clamouring to be heard above the din of antiracist orthodoxy. It is of little surprise, then, that Jonathan Anomaly is also a frequent contributor to the right-libertarian Quillette, an online magazine edited by ‘Mistress of the Intellectual Dark Web’ Australian Claire Lehmann (Dale 2018). Lehmann herself has defended behavioural genetics, claiming that ‘it is measured by IQ testing, is genetically based, and correlates with success in life’ (Hochschild 2019). In one of his Quillette articles, Anomaly argues that ‘good’ science is often refuted on moral rather than scientific grounds (Anomaly 2017). Referring to proponents of the link between race and IQ, Edmund Wilson and Arthur Jensen’s argument that, as Anomaly puts it, ‘different racial groups probably have different cognitive propensities and capacities’, he claims that ‘they were harshly denounced, typically on moral grounds rather than on the scientific merit of their arguments. Their careers were threatened, and people who might otherwise pursue this research or publicly explain the evidence for these hypotheses learned to keep their mouths shut.’ Without irony, Anomaly is arguing that ‘best available evidence’ on what he calls ‘politically contentious scientific topics’ is refuted because of ‘the career-advancing opportunities open to those who symbolically reject sexism and racism’ (original emphasis). However, there is no evaluation of this evidence against the wider literature because, despite its claim to rigour, Quillette’s offerings are rather more hyperbolic than they are evidence-based.
It is vital to loudly oppose the notion that eugenics can ever constitute desirable public policy proposals, even those associated with what Anomaly calls ‘liberal eugenics’, which apparently ‘places more weight on individual liberty and less confidence in the wisdom of state agents than early manifestations of eugenics did’ (Anomaly 2018: 30; see also Agar 2004). It is also crucial to cast doubt on the proposition that these types of ideas have been marginalized. However, it is insufficient to argue against the contentions made by ‘race realists’ on scientific grounds alone. To do so is to misconstrue the terms of the race project, which were never purely scientific, but inherently political, and which actu...

Índice

  1. Cover
  2. Contents
  3. Title page
  4. Copyright page
  5. Acknowledgements
  6. Introduction
  7. 1 Race beyond Social Construction
  8. 2 ‘Not Racism™’
  9. 3 Making It about Race
  10. 4 Good Jew/Bad Jew
  11. Conclusion: Talking and Not Talking about Race
  12. References
  13. Index
  14. End User License Agreement
Estilos de citas para Why Race Still Matters

APA 6 Citation

Lentin, A. (2020). Why Race Still Matters (1st ed.). Wiley. Retrieved from https://www.perlego.com/book/1536767/why-race-still-matters-pdf (Original work published 2020)

Chicago Citation

Lentin, Alana. (2020) 2020. Why Race Still Matters. 1st ed. Wiley. https://www.perlego.com/book/1536767/why-race-still-matters-pdf.

Harvard Citation

Lentin, A. (2020) Why Race Still Matters. 1st edn. Wiley. Available at: https://www.perlego.com/book/1536767/why-race-still-matters-pdf (Accessed: 14 October 2022).

MLA 7 Citation

Lentin, Alana. Why Race Still Matters. 1st ed. Wiley, 2020. Web. 14 Oct. 2022.