Space, Time, Matter
eBook - ePub

Space, Time, Matter

Hermann Weyl

  1. 368 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (adapté aux mobiles)
  4. Disponible sur iOS et Android
eBook - ePub

Space, Time, Matter

Hermann Weyl

DĂ©tails du livre
Aperçu du livre
Table des matiĂšres
Citations

À propos de ce livre

`The standard treatise on the general theory of relativity.` — Nature
`Whatever the future may bring, Professor Weyl's book will remain a classic of physics.` — British Journal for Philosophy and Science
Reflecting the revolution in scientific and philosophic thought which accompanied the Einstein relativity theories, Dr. Weyl has probed deeply into the notions of space, time, and matter. A rigorous examination of the state of our knowledge of the world following these developments is undertaken with this guiding principle: that although further scientific thought may take us far beyond our present conception of the world, we may never again return to the previous narrow and restricted scheme.
Although a degree of mathematical sophistication is presupposed, Dr. Weyl develops all the tensor calculus necessary to his exposition. He then proceeds to an analysis of the concept of Euclidean space and the spatial conceptions of Riemann. From this the nature of the amalgamation of space and time is derived. This leads to an exposition and examination of Einstein's general theory of relativity and the concomitant theory of gravitation. A detailed investigation follows devoted to gravitational waves, a rigorous solution of the problem of one body, laws of conservation, and the energy of gravitation. Dr. Weyl's introduction of the concept of tensor-density as a magnitude of quantity (contrasted with tensors which are considered to be magnitudes of intensity) is a major step toward a clearer understanding of the relationships among space, time, and matter.

Foire aux questions

Comment puis-je résilier mon abonnement ?
Il vous suffit de vous rendre dans la section compte dans paramĂštres et de cliquer sur « RĂ©silier l’abonnement ». C’est aussi simple que cela ! Une fois que vous aurez rĂ©siliĂ© votre abonnement, il restera actif pour le reste de la pĂ©riode pour laquelle vous avez payĂ©. DĂ©couvrez-en plus ici.
Puis-je / comment puis-je télécharger des livres ?
Pour le moment, tous nos livres en format ePub adaptĂ©s aux mobiles peuvent ĂȘtre tĂ©lĂ©chargĂ©s via l’application. La plupart de nos PDF sont Ă©galement disponibles en tĂ©lĂ©chargement et les autres seront tĂ©lĂ©chargeables trĂšs prochainement. DĂ©couvrez-en plus ici.
Quelle est la différence entre les formules tarifaires ?
Les deux abonnements vous donnent un accĂšs complet Ă  la bibliothĂšque et Ă  toutes les fonctionnalitĂ©s de Perlego. Les seules diffĂ©rences sont les tarifs ainsi que la pĂ©riode d’abonnement : avec l’abonnement annuel, vous Ă©conomiserez environ 30 % par rapport Ă  12 mois d’abonnement mensuel.
Qu’est-ce que Perlego ?
Nous sommes un service d’abonnement Ă  des ouvrages universitaires en ligne, oĂč vous pouvez accĂ©der Ă  toute une bibliothĂšque pour un prix infĂ©rieur Ă  celui d’un seul livre par mois. Avec plus d’un million de livres sur plus de 1 000 sujets, nous avons ce qu’il vous faut ! DĂ©couvrez-en plus ici.
Prenez-vous en charge la synthÚse vocale ?
Recherchez le symbole Écouter sur votre prochain livre pour voir si vous pouvez l’écouter. L’outil Écouter lit le texte Ă  haute voix pour vous, en surlignant le passage qui est en cours de lecture. Vous pouvez le mettre sur pause, l’accĂ©lĂ©rer ou le ralentir. DĂ©couvrez-en plus ici.
Est-ce que Space, Time, Matter est un PDF/ePUB en ligne ?
Oui, vous pouvez accĂ©der Ă  Space, Time, Matter par Hermann Weyl en format PDF et/ou ePUB ainsi qu’à d’autres livres populaires dans Physical Sciences et Physics. Nous disposons de plus d’un million d’ouvrages Ă  dĂ©couvrir dans notre catalogue.

Informations

Année
2013
ISBN
9780486318424
CHAPTER I
EUCLIDEAN SPACE. ITS MATHEMATICAL FORMULATION AND
ITS RÔLE IN PHYSICS
§ 1. Deduction of the Elementary Conceptions of Space from
that of Equality
JUST as we fixed the present moment (“now”) as a geometrical point in time, so we fix an exact “here,” a point in space, as the first element of continuous spatial extension, which, like time, is infinitely divisible. Space is not a one-dimensional continuum like time. The principle by which it is continuously extended cannot be reduced to the simple relation of “earlier” or “later ”. We shall refrain from inquiring what relations enable us to grasp this continuity conceptually. On the other hand, space, like time, is a form of phenomena. Precisely the same content, identically the same thing, still remaining what it is, can equally well be at some place in space other than that at which it is actually. The new portion of Space Sâ€Č then occupied by it is equal to that portion S which it actually occupied. S and Sâ€Č are said to be congruent. To every point P of S there corresponds one definite homologous point Pâ€Č of Sâ€Č which, after the above displacement to a new position, would be surrounded by exactly the same part of the given content as that which surrounded P originally. We shall call this “transformation” (in virtue of which the point Pâ€Č corresponds to the point P) a congruent transformation. Provided that the appropriate subjective conditions are satisfied the given material tiling would seem to us after the displacement exactly the same as before. There is reasonable justification for believing that a rigid body, when placed in two positions successively, realises this idea of the equality of two portions of space ; by a rigid body we mean one which, however it be moved or treated, can always be made to appear the same to us as before, if we take up the appropriate position with respect to it. I shall evolve the scheme of geometry from the conception of equality combined with that of continuous connection—of which the latter offers great difficulties to analysis —and shall show in a superficial sketch how all fundamental conceptions of geometry may be traced back to them. My real object in doing so will be to single out translations among possible congruent transformations. Starting from the conception of translation I shall then develop Euclidean geometry along strictly axiomatic lines.
First of all the straight line. Its distinguishing feature is that it is determined by two of its points. Any other line can, even when two of its points are kept fixed, be brought into another position by a congruent transformation (the test of straightness).
Thus, if A and B are two different points, the straight line g = AB includes every point which becomes transformed into itself by all those congruent transformations which transform AB into themselves. (In familiar language, the straight line lies evenly between its points.) Expressed kinematically, this is tantamount to saying that we regard the straight line as an axis of rotation. It is homogeneous and a linear continuum just like time. Any arbitrary point on it divides it into two parts, two “rays”. If B lies on one of these parts and C on the other, then A is said to be between B and C and the points of one part lie to the right of A, the points of the other part to the left. (The choice as to which is right or left is determined arbitrarily.) The simplest fundamental facts which are implied by the conception “between” can be formulated as exactly and completely as a geometry which is to be built up by deductive processes demands. For this reason we endeavour to trace back all conceptions of continuity to the conception “between,” i.e. to the relation “A is a point of the straight line BC and lies between B and C” (this is the reverse of the real intuitional relation). Suppose Aâ€Č to be a point on g to the right of A, then Aâ€Č also divides the line g into two parts. We call that to which A belongs the left-hand side. If, however, Aâ€Č lies to the left of A the position is reversed. With this convention, analogous relations hold not only for A and Aâ€Č but also for any two points of a straight line. The points of a straight line are ordered by the terms left and right in precisely the same way as points of time by the terms earlier and later.
Left and right are equivalent. There is one congruent transformation which leaves A fixed, but which interchanges the two halves into which A divides the straight line. Every finite portion of straight line AB may be superposed upon itself in such a way that it is reversed (i.e. so that B falls on A, and A falls on B). On the other hand, a congruent transformation which transforms A into itself, and all points to the right of A into points to the right of A, and all...

Table des matiĂšres

  1. Cover
  2. Title Page
  3. Copyright Page
  4. Preface
  5. Translator’s Note
  6. Contents
  7. Introduction
  8. Chapter I: Euclidean Space. Its Mathematical Form and Its RĂŽle in Physics.
  9. Chapter II: The Metrical Continuum
  10. Chapter III: Relativity of Space and Time
  11. Chapter IV: General Theory of Relativity
  12. Appendix I
  13. Appendix II
  14. Bibliographical References
  15. Index
Normes de citation pour Space, Time, Matter

APA 6 Citation

Weyl, H. (2013). Space, Time, Matter ([edition unavailable]). Dover Publications. Retrieved from https://www.perlego.com/book/112449/space-time-matter-pdf (Original work published 2013)

Chicago Citation

Weyl, Hermann. (2013) 2013. Space, Time, Matter. [Edition unavailable]. Dover Publications. https://www.perlego.com/book/112449/space-time-matter-pdf.

Harvard Citation

Weyl, H. (2013) Space, Time, Matter. [edition unavailable]. Dover Publications. Available at: https://www.perlego.com/book/112449/space-time-matter-pdf (Accessed: 14 October 2022).

MLA 7 Citation

Weyl, Hermann. Space, Time, Matter. [edition unavailable]. Dover Publications, 2013. Web. 14 Oct. 2022.