Symmetrizing Syntax
eBook - ePub

Symmetrizing Syntax

Merge, Minimality, and Equilibria

Hiroki Narita, Naoki Fukui

  1. 272 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (adapté aux mobiles)
  4. Disponible sur iOS et Android
eBook - ePub

Symmetrizing Syntax

Merge, Minimality, and Equilibria

Hiroki Narita, Naoki Fukui

DĂ©tails du livre
Aperçu du livre
Table des matiĂšres
Citations

À propos de ce livre

Symmetrizing Syntax seeks to establish a minimal and natural characterization of the structure of human language (syntax), simplifying many facets of it that have been redundantly or asymmetrically formulated.

Virtually all past theories of natural language syntax, from the traditional X-bar theory to the contemporary system of Merge and labeling, stipulate that every phrase structure is "asymmetrically" organized, so that one of its elements is always marked as primary/dominant over the others, or each and every phrase is labeled by a designated lexical element. The two authors call this traditional stipulation into question and hypothesize, instead, that linguistic derivations are essentially driven by the need to reduce asymmetry and generate symmetric structures. Various linguistic notions such as Merge, cyclic derivation by phase, feature-checking, morphological agreement, labeling, movement, and criterial freezing, as well as parametric differences among languages like English and Japanese, and so on, are all shown to follow from a particular notion of structural symmetry. These results constitute novel support for the contemporary thesis that human language is essentially an instance of a physical/biological object, and its design is governed by the laws of nature, at the core of which lies the fundamental principle of symmetry.

Providing insights into new technical concepts in syntax, the volume is written for academics in linguistics but will also be accessible to linguistics students seeking an introduction to syntax.

Foire aux questions

Comment puis-je résilier mon abonnement ?
Il vous suffit de vous rendre dans la section compte dans paramĂštres et de cliquer sur « RĂ©silier l’abonnement ». C’est aussi simple que cela ! Une fois que vous aurez rĂ©siliĂ© votre abonnement, il restera actif pour le reste de la pĂ©riode pour laquelle vous avez payĂ©. DĂ©couvrez-en plus ici.
Puis-je / comment puis-je télécharger des livres ?
Pour le moment, tous nos livres en format ePub adaptĂ©s aux mobiles peuvent ĂȘtre tĂ©lĂ©chargĂ©s via l’application. La plupart de nos PDF sont Ă©galement disponibles en tĂ©lĂ©chargement et les autres seront tĂ©lĂ©chargeables trĂšs prochainement. DĂ©couvrez-en plus ici.
Quelle est la différence entre les formules tarifaires ?
Les deux abonnements vous donnent un accĂšs complet Ă  la bibliothĂšque et Ă  toutes les fonctionnalitĂ©s de Perlego. Les seules diffĂ©rences sont les tarifs ainsi que la pĂ©riode d’abonnement : avec l’abonnement annuel, vous Ă©conomiserez environ 30 % par rapport Ă  12 mois d’abonnement mensuel.
Qu’est-ce que Perlego ?
Nous sommes un service d’abonnement Ă  des ouvrages universitaires en ligne, oĂč vous pouvez accĂ©der Ă  toute une bibliothĂšque pour un prix infĂ©rieur Ă  celui d’un seul livre par mois. Avec plus d’un million de livres sur plus de 1 000 sujets, nous avons ce qu’il vous faut ! DĂ©couvrez-en plus ici.
Prenez-vous en charge la synthÚse vocale ?
Recherchez le symbole Écouter sur votre prochain livre pour voir si vous pouvez l’écouter. L’outil Écouter lit le texte Ă  haute voix pour vous, en surlignant le passage qui est en cours de lecture. Vous pouvez le mettre sur pause, l’accĂ©lĂ©rer ou le ralentir. DĂ©couvrez-en plus ici.
Est-ce que Symmetrizing Syntax est un PDF/ePUB en ligne ?
Oui, vous pouvez accĂ©der Ă  Symmetrizing Syntax par Hiroki Narita, Naoki Fukui en format PDF et/ou ePUB ainsi qu’à d’autres livres populaires dans Sprachen & Linguistik et Syntax in der Linguistik. Nous disposons de plus d’un million d’ouvrages Ă  dĂ©couvrir dans notre catalogue.

Informations

Éditeur
Routledge
Année
2021
ISBN
9781317371557

1

Symmetry of Merge

Why only Merge?

DOI: 10.4324/9781315671901-1

1.1 Introduction

Berwick and Chomsky (2015) raise the question of why it is only us, Homo sapiens, who can speak language, think in language, and make use of language for all sorts of purposes. Their answer is essentially that it’s because we are the only species that has Merge. Merge is, it is assumed, a recursive generative procedure of the human faculty of language that takes n (typically two) objects, Σ1, 
, Σn, and forms an unordered set, {Σ1, 
, Σn}.
  • (1) Merge(ÎŁ1, 
, ÎŁn) = {ÎŁ1, 
, ÎŁn}
The contemporary theory of bare phrase structure (Chomsky 1994 et seq.) hypothesizes that virtually every phrase structure of human language is uniformly generated by Merge, applied in an unbounded fashion. Structural representations generated by Merge are then variously utilized by human performance systems, notably by the Conceptual-Intentional (CI) system and the Sensorimotor (SM) system, thereby leading to various mental capacities of human cognition. According to Berwick and Chomsky, Homo sapiens is a unique organism, essentially by virtue of Merge and its various cognitive applications.
Now, we would like to pose the following question: Why only Merge?
The question is ambiguous, interpretable at least in three different manners.1 So, more specifically, we would like to ask:
Question 1: Why only Merge?—Why do linguists, Berwick and Chomsky, among others, want to claim that it is Merge that instantiates the only distinctive property of human language? What is supposed to be the empirical gain from this proposal?
Question 2: Why only Merge?—Why do they want to claim that Merge is the only species-specific property, disregarding other cognitive capacities of human beings, which may or may not be as innate, innovative, and/or specific?
Question 3: Why only Merge?—Why is it only Merge, and not any other devices, that has the properties it does and that was allowed to emerge by virtue of the evolution-development of human beings? That is, why is Merge as it is rather than any other way?
1 The three-way ambiguity of Why only us? is noted by Berwick and Chomsky (2019).
We can point to a rich body of literature that tries to answer Questions 1 and 2. In contrast, we feel Question 3 is not sufficiently addressed and discussed in the prior literature. The main purpose of this monograph is essentially to discuss what a possible answer to Question 3 should look like and how we may possibly approach it on empirical grounds.
In order to see how we are going to address, and possibly answer, Question 3, it is instructive to review what constitute the appropriate, and we believe the most enlightening, answers to Questions 1 and 2. In a nutshell, the answer to Question 1 would be that Merge is minimally necessary to capture the so-called “Basic Property” of human language. The answer to Question 2 would be that keeping to Merge only, due to its generality, presumably provides best explanations for a great many aspects of human language. We will discuss issues surrounding Questions 1 and 2 (§1.2 and §1.3) and then proceed to address Question 3 in §1.4.

1.2 Only Merge, because it is minimally necessary to capture the Basic Property of human language

We will first address Question 1. The answer to this question is related to a longstanding observation about the ordinary use of human language.
Thousands of years of linguistic investigation share the belief, commonly ascribed to Aristotle, that the grammar of natural language is in essence a system of pairing “sound” (or “signs”) with “meaning.” The enterprise of generative grammar initiated by Chomsky (1955/1975, 1957) is just a recent addition to this long tradition, but it provided a couple of important insights into the nature of human language that have revolutionized the perspective from which we study human language. At the core of this Chomskyan revolution lies an old observation, essentially due to Descartes and other rationalists, that the capacity to pair sounds and meanings in human language exhibits unbounded creativity: humans can produce and understand an infinitude of expressions, many of which are previously unheard of or are too long and/or senseless to be produced. This Cartesian observation can be called the “Basic Property” of human language, to adopt Chomsky’s (2015a:3, 2015b:4, etc.) formulation.
To illustrate, consider a simple declarative sentence in English, The boy read the book. A speaker of English can understand that this sentence has an internal structure consisting of two major constituents, the noun phrase (NP) the boy and the verb phrase (VP) read the book, and that these constituents are further decomposed into smaller units (as in: VP = [V read] [NP the book], etc.). Based on the hierarchical structure, s/he can also assign phonological and semantic interpretations to the expression: thus, s/he understands that the noun boy is the agent performing the action denoted by the verb read, that the definite article the induces a presupposition that there exists a contextually salient unique boy in the discourse, and so on. These interpretive properties are somehow encoded at the respective SM and CI interfaces, PHON and SEM. Moreover, such an expression can be infinitely expanded, for example, by adding optional adjuncts of various types (2), coordinating its constituents (3), or embedding it into another expression (4), showing various sorts of unbounded generation.
  • (2)
    1. the boy (often) (eagerly) read the book (carefully) (quickly) (at the station) (at 2pm) (last week) 

    2. the (smart) (young) (handsome) 
 boy (who was twelve years old) (who Mary liked) (whose mother was sick) 
 read the book.
  • (3)
    1. the boy read the book (and/or/but) the girl drank coffee (and/or/but) 

    2. [the boy (and/or/but not) the girl (and/or) 
] read the book.
  • (4)
    1. I know that [the girl believes that [it is certain that 
 [the boy read the book] 
]]
    2. The boy [(that/who) the girl [(that/who) the cat [
] bit] liked] read the book.
In this manner, human language yields an infinite number of SEM- and PHON-interpretable hierarchical structures. Let us call this observation the Basic Property of human language, (Chomsky 2015a:3, 2015b:4, etc.).
It is hypothesized by Chomsky (2004 et seq.) that the Basic Property essentially follows from the recursive application of Merge, understood as a simple set-formation operation that takes n (typically two) objects Σ1, 
, Σn and forms a set, {Σ1, 
, Σn}. If applied to two elements, say, the and book, Merge generates the set {the, book} in (5a). For expository purposes, we will occasionally represent the output sets of Merge with familiar tree diagrams. Thus, the set in (5a) can be represented as (5b), though it should be borne in mind that, strictly speaking, tree representations may not be equivalent to the set notation. In particular, order is irrelevant in such diagrams.2
2 Notice that (i) is as accurate a tree-graphic representation of (5a) as (5b) is.
That is, the application of Merge just leaves the two elements unordered.
  • (5)
Provided that Merge can apply iteratively, the output of Merge, {the, book}, can constitute another input to the same operation, say, with read, yielding (6).
  • (6)
Objects manipulated by recursive Merge—the atomic elements (lexical items, LIs) and set-theoretic objects like (5a) and (6a)—are called syntactic objects (SOs).
Merge can provide minimal but sufficient information about hierarchical structure. It specifically yields the term-of relation, recursively defined in set-theoretic terms as follows (adapted from Chomsky 1995b:227).3
3 Chomsky (1995b:227) defines term-of as follows:
  • (i) For any SO K, (a) K is a term of K, and (b) if L is a term of K, then the members of the members of L are terms of K.
Chomsky (1995b) assumes that Merge(α, ÎČ) yields { Îł, {α, ÎČ} }, with ...

Table des matiĂšres

  1. Cover Page
  2. Half Title Page
  3. Series Page
  4. Title Page
  5. Copyright Page
  6. Contents Page
  7. Preface Page
  8. 1 Symmetry of Merge: why only Merge?
  9. 2 Symmetry of phases: Cyclic Transfer and feature-equilibrium
  10. 3 Symmetry of agreement: Reducing Multiple Agree(ment) mechanisms into feature-equilibrium
  11. 4 Symmetry of labeling: beyond Chomsky’s Labeling Algorithm and universal/unique labeling condition
  12. 5 Symmetry of movement: criteria, freezing, and cyclicity
  13. 6 Conclusions
  14. References
  15. Appendix C List of propositions
  16. Index
Normes de citation pour Symmetrizing Syntax

APA 6 Citation

Narita, H., & Fukui, N. (2021). Symmetrizing Syntax (1st ed.). Taylor and Francis. Retrieved from https://www.perlego.com/book/3040917/symmetrizing-syntax-merge-minimality-and-equilibria-pdf (Original work published 2021)

Chicago Citation

Narita, Hiroki, and Naoki Fukui. (2021) 2021. Symmetrizing Syntax. 1st ed. Taylor and Francis. https://www.perlego.com/book/3040917/symmetrizing-syntax-merge-minimality-and-equilibria-pdf.

Harvard Citation

Narita, H. and Fukui, N. (2021) Symmetrizing Syntax. 1st edn. Taylor and Francis. Available at: https://www.perlego.com/book/3040917/symmetrizing-syntax-merge-minimality-and-equilibria-pdf (Accessed: 15 October 2022).

MLA 7 Citation

Narita, Hiroki, and Naoki Fukui. Symmetrizing Syntax. 1st ed. Taylor and Francis, 2021. Web. 15 Oct. 2022.