A Cultural History of the Emotions in Antiquity
eBook - ePub

A Cultural History of the Emotions in Antiquity

Douglas Cairns, Douglas Cairns

  1. 240 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (adapté aux mobiles)
  4. Disponible sur iOS et Android
eBook - ePub

A Cultural History of the Emotions in Antiquity

Douglas Cairns, Douglas Cairns

DĂ©tails du livre
Aperçu du livre
Table des matiĂšres
Citations

À propos de ce livre

This volume provides an overview of some of the salient aspects of emotions and their role in life and thought of the Greco-Roman world, from the beginnings of Greek literature and history to the height of the Roman Empire. This is a wide remit, dealing with a wide range of sources in two ancient languages, and in the full range of contexts that are covered by the format of this series. The volume's chapters survey the emotional worlds of the ancient Greeks and Romans from multiple perspectives – philosophical, scientific, medical, literary, musical, theatrical, religious, domestic, political, art-historical and historical. All chapters consider both Greek and Roman evidence, ranging from the Homeric poems to the Roman Imperial period and making extensive use of both elite and non-elite texts and documents, including those preserved on stone, papyrus and similar media, and in other forms of material culture. The volume is thus fully reflective of the latest research in the emerging discipline of ancient emotion history.

Foire aux questions

Comment puis-je résilier mon abonnement ?
Il vous suffit de vous rendre dans la section compte dans paramĂštres et de cliquer sur « RĂ©silier l’abonnement ». C’est aussi simple que cela ! Une fois que vous aurez rĂ©siliĂ© votre abonnement, il restera actif pour le reste de la pĂ©riode pour laquelle vous avez payĂ©. DĂ©couvrez-en plus ici.
Puis-je / comment puis-je télécharger des livres ?
Pour le moment, tous nos livres en format ePub adaptĂ©s aux mobiles peuvent ĂȘtre tĂ©lĂ©chargĂ©s via l’application. La plupart de nos PDF sont Ă©galement disponibles en tĂ©lĂ©chargement et les autres seront tĂ©lĂ©chargeables trĂšs prochainement. DĂ©couvrez-en plus ici.
Quelle est la différence entre les formules tarifaires ?
Les deux abonnements vous donnent un accĂšs complet Ă  la bibliothĂšque et Ă  toutes les fonctionnalitĂ©s de Perlego. Les seules diffĂ©rences sont les tarifs ainsi que la pĂ©riode d’abonnement : avec l’abonnement annuel, vous Ă©conomiserez environ 30 % par rapport Ă  12 mois d’abonnement mensuel.
Qu’est-ce que Perlego ?
Nous sommes un service d’abonnement Ă  des ouvrages universitaires en ligne, oĂč vous pouvez accĂ©der Ă  toute une bibliothĂšque pour un prix infĂ©rieur Ă  celui d’un seul livre par mois. Avec plus d’un million de livres sur plus de 1 000 sujets, nous avons ce qu’il vous faut ! DĂ©couvrez-en plus ici.
Prenez-vous en charge la synthÚse vocale ?
Recherchez le symbole Écouter sur votre prochain livre pour voir si vous pouvez l’écouter. L’outil Écouter lit le texte Ă  haute voix pour vous, en surlignant le passage qui est en cours de lecture. Vous pouvez le mettre sur pause, l’accĂ©lĂ©rer ou le ralentir. DĂ©couvrez-en plus ici.
Est-ce que A Cultural History of the Emotions in Antiquity est un PDF/ePUB en ligne ?
Oui, vous pouvez accĂ©der Ă  A Cultural History of the Emotions in Antiquity par Douglas Cairns, Douglas Cairns en format PDF et/ou ePUB ainsi qu’à d’autres livres populaires dans Storia et Storia dell'antica Grecia. Nous disposons de plus d’un million d’ouvrages Ă  dĂ©couvrir dans notre catalogue.

Informations

Année
2020
ISBN
9781350091641
Édition
1
Sujet
Storia

CHAPTER ONE


Medical and Scientific Understandings

GEORGE KAZANTZIDIS

INTRODUCTION

Hippocrates’ Epidemics 1.9 (2.650–2 L.) describes a deadly outbreak of fever on the island of Thasos with the following symptoms:
Now, those suffering from ardent fever, when fatal symptoms attended, showed signs from the beginning. For right from the beginning there was acute fever with slight rigors, sleeplessness, thirst, nausea, slight sweats about the head and collar-bones, but in no case all over the body, much delirium, phoboi, dusthumiai, very cold extremities, toes and hands, especially the latter. The exacerbation occurred on the even days; but in most cases the pains were the greatest on the fourth day, with sweat for the most part chilly, while the extremities could not now be warmed again, remaining livid and cold.
—trans. Jones 1923a: 173, modified
The list of symptoms cited above is characteristic of the way in which emotions are evaluated clinically in the Hippocratic corpus (see Fig. 1.1), the earliest collection of medical writings (fifth to fourth centuries BCE) to have survived from Greek antiquity, which will be the focus of this chapter. Phobos, “fear,” and dusthumiĂȘ, “despondency,” follow upon the observation that some of the patients show signs of mental disturbance. Indeed, when the suspicion is raised in medical texts that a patient’s mind has been affected, along with his or her body, emotions become increasingly significant as symptoms. At the same time, there is no indication that either fear or sadness is highlighted as if they were qualitatively different from the physical symptoms, for example cold extremities, sweat in the forehead, or nausea; in fact, the text shows no awareness of what we would today call patient “psychology.” In Hippocratic medicine, emotions are most often treated as an extension of the body, rather than independently. In this context, it is highly likely that phobos and dusthumiĂȘ have been adduced by the author as additional symptoms—confirming simply the presence of excessive coldness in the patients’ bodies.1 On the whole, even though early medical writers are keen on observing—and indeed develop a rich and refined vocabulary for—emotional anomalies, the overall tendency is to frame “affective” symptoms in a context which is predominantly concerned with what is happening inside the (material) body: “the body,” as Peter Singer puts it, “can be used,” in the medicine of this period, “to give an account of total experience.”2
Ebook
FIGURE 1.1: Portrait of Hippocrates holding his Apophthegms. Fourteenth-century Byzantine miniature.
The question of how Greek medical science understands the emotions necessarily implicates their relation to the body. In De anima 403a3–20, Aristotle seeks to identify whether the soul exists independently of the body by asking precisely whether the so-called pathĂȘ of the psychĂȘ (a generic term indicating everything that the soul undergoes, including the emotions) belong only to the soul;3 for if it could be proved that such emotions as anger and courage are not shared by the body, it would then follow that the soul can maintain an independent existence (403a10–12). As it happens, the hypothesis is soon dismissed—emotions cannot be experienced unless through the body (403a17–20)—but Aristotle, as is well known, places emphasis (both in De anima and in the Rhetoric) also on how they are formed mentally by complicated thoughts, evaluations, and judgments:4 thus, for instance, while both anger and fear are accompanied by an unpleasant sensation of pain (lupĂȘ), anger is specifically qualified by the belief that we have been wrongfully mistreated (Rhetoric 1378a31–3) whereas fear is experienced as a mental picture of some destructive or painful evil in the future (Rhetoric 1382a21–2).5
Hippocratics assume a more radical position: while they are certainly familiar with the fact that “feeling” involves “thinking,” for the most part they deliberately ignore the fact that emotions can be shaped cognitively by a separate mental faculty, and they prefer to analyze an emotion into its bodily and material coordinates. Aristotle is familiar with this tendency: the issue of what anger is, as we are told in De anima 403a29–b2, can be addressed differently, depending on the perspective we adopt; thus, the “dialectician” would try to understand its formal cause, describing it as “a desire for retaliation” which arises from one’s judgment that one has been wronged;6 the “natural scientist” (phusikos),7 on the other hand, would seek to define it materially, concluding that anger is “the boiling of blood and hot stuff around the heart.” As we look further into the Hippocratic corpus, we realize that the doctors’ profoundly “physical” understanding of emotions is not simply a matter of emphasis; on the contrary, it is a calculated attempt to sidestep the idea of a ruling mental faculty and to propose instead that appraisal in affective experience should be viewed as an organismic activity that is distributed across the body and in which the body operates as the prime sense-making mechanism. This is not to say that medical emotions lack “intelligence,” but that intelligence has been subsumed by a feeling and perceiving body which functions as the primary seat of emotion.8 As Michael Frede observes, one of the usual mistakes we make in our approach to ancient philosophical and medical texts is that we “underrate the physical to the extent that we tend to think of it as being determined by certain ultimate material constituents and a few basic properties of these material constituents”;9 yet, when we consider that the distinction between mind or soul and the body is not always evident in ancient sources and that in some of them psychic activity is conceived as a certain disposition of the body (see especially the Hippocratic On Regimen),10 it then follows that thinking or feeling is “something that a living body does in virtue of the soul, rather than something which the soul or the mind does for it.”11 In this context, the emphasis placed by the Hippocratics on the raw physicality of emotions will be discussed as a means of assigning to the body an enhanced role as a sense-making, appraising mechanism. The main underlying notion is that there is no need to discuss affect by presupposing a superimposing mental process; rather, it is the body that does the “feeling” and incorporates, in all its material dimensions, what we call “emotion.”

EMOTIONS IN HEALTH

Emotions are of interest to medical authors mainly as symptoms of disease—as an index of erratic behavior showing that the patient’s body is out of balance. This means that we lack a comprehensive medical account explaining how emotions arise under normal circumstances and how they are related to body and mind in a state of health. The most detailed attempt to speak about emotions in their natural state is found in On the Sacred Disease 14 (6.386 L.)—in a treatise which sets out to explain epilepsy by attributing its origin to the brain,12 the most important of all organs in the human body according to the author:
Men ought to know that from the brain, and from the brain only, arise our pleasures, joys, laughter, and amusement, as well as our sorrows, pains, griefs, and tears. It is especially through this organ that we think, see, hear, and distinguish the ugly from the beautiful, the bad from the good, the pleasant from the unpleasant. Sometimes we judge according to convention; at other times according to what we sense to be in the best for our interests.
—trans. Jones 1923b: 175, modified
Modern lists of “basic affects” or “basic emotions” typically include anger, disgust, fear, happiness, sadness, and surprise.13 In the Greek passage cited above we can easily recognize the equivalents of happiness/pleasure and sadness/distress.14 Furthermore, although disgust is not explicitly mentioned in the text, we can trace it behind the author’s remark that the brain helps us distinguish between “pleasant” and “unpleasant” things,15 in the same way that it allows us to make aesthetic judgments or ethical decisions. On that reading, disgust would be more directly linked to an appraising process—than, say, happiness or sadness—thus approximating to a “higher cognitive” emotion.16 Indeed, it is worth remembering that while disgust is seen by some as a basic affect, assumed to be triggered and executed on a largely automatic basis of instinctive reactions, there are those who argue that “the word is merely a rough generalizing label that captures the sensation of judging something to have polluting and defiling powers.”17 But with the exception of disgust, the relationship between affects and mental functions in the Hippocratic text—the latter including phronĂȘsis (“intelligence”), sunesis (“understanding”), and diagnĂŽsis (“discerning thinking”)18—remains for the most part obscure: while the brain is identified as the ultimate source for every psychic power in the body, there is no attempt by the author to discuss in detail the kind of thoughts and judgments that shape our feelings. In fact, when later in the treatise “fear” (phobos) is added to the list of emotions, its link to the brain is explained strictly in materialist terms: when too much bile enters the cavity of the head and raises the brain’s temperature, a person is seized by phobos, which subsides only after the humour has moved down to the body and back into the veins (On the Sacred Disease 15, 6.388 L.). In the same spirit, it is stated that the heart and the diaphragm—an area of the body that is be...

Table des matiĂšres

  1. Cover
  2. Half-Title Page
  3. Series
  4. Title Page
  5. Contents
  6. List of Illustrations
  7. General Editors’ Preface
  8. Introduction: Emotion History and the Classics
  9. 1 Medical and Scientific Understandings
  10. 2 Religion and Spirituality
  11. 3 Music and Dance
  12. 4 Drama
  13. 5 The Visual Arts
  14. 6 Literature
  15. 7 In Private: The Individual and the Domestic Community
  16. 8 In Public: Collectivities and Polities
  17. Notes on Contributors
  18. Notes
  19. References
  20. Index
  21. Copyright
Normes de citation pour A Cultural History of the Emotions in Antiquity

APA 6 Citation

Cairns, D. (2020). A Cultural History of the Emotions in Antiquity (1st ed.). Bloomsbury Publishing. Retrieved from https://www.perlego.com/book/3118830/a-cultural-history-of-the-emotions-in-antiquity-pdf (Original work published 2020)

Chicago Citation

Cairns, Douglas. (2020) 2020. A Cultural History of the Emotions in Antiquity. 1st ed. Bloomsbury Publishing. https://www.perlego.com/book/3118830/a-cultural-history-of-the-emotions-in-antiquity-pdf.

Harvard Citation

Cairns, D. (2020) A Cultural History of the Emotions in Antiquity. 1st edn. Bloomsbury Publishing. Available at: https://www.perlego.com/book/3118830/a-cultural-history-of-the-emotions-in-antiquity-pdf (Accessed: 15 October 2022).

MLA 7 Citation

Cairns, Douglas. A Cultural History of the Emotions in Antiquity. 1st ed. Bloomsbury Publishing, 2020. Web. 15 Oct. 2022.