Information, Natural Law, and the Self-Assembly of Rhythmic Movement
eBook - ePub

Information, Natural Law, and the Self-Assembly of Rhythmic Movement

Peter N. Kugler, Michael T. Turvey

  1. 482 pagine
  2. English
  3. ePUB (disponibile sull'app)
  4. Disponibile su iOS e Android
eBook - ePub

Information, Natural Law, and the Self-Assembly of Rhythmic Movement

Peter N. Kugler, Michael T. Turvey

Dettagli del libro
Anteprima del libro
Indice dei contenuti
Citazioni

Informazioni sul libro

Originally published in 1987, the introduction states: "the authors have successfully accomplished their program – to explain, based on physical representations, the observed relations among various parameters of wrist-pendulum oscillations. Thereby a set of new ideas and concepts, including those developed recently by the scientific school to which the authors belong, are introduced to biology. These concepts are closely related to the experimental data. This accomplishment makes the book especially attractive and demonstrates once more the productivity of applying physics to biology."

"Clear language, simple figures, and physical examples illuminate rather complicated problems. These attractive features should make the book intelligible to a variety of investigators in the field of motor control, not only to the specialists with physical and mathematical education."

From the foreword: " Kugler and Turvey have written strategic physical biology, and shown that, after all, dynamics (including both kinetics and kinematics) may support a unitary physical view of some of the profound operations of our brains… This is a grand start on what I hope is a larger program of demystifying behaviour."

Domande frequenti

Come faccio ad annullare l'abbonamento?
È semplicissimo: basta accedere alla sezione Account nelle Impostazioni e cliccare su "Annulla abbonamento". Dopo la cancellazione, l'abbonamento rimarrà attivo per il periodo rimanente già pagato. Per maggiori informazioni, clicca qui
È possibile scaricare libri? Se sì, come?
Al momento è possibile scaricare tramite l'app tutti i nostri libri ePub mobile-friendly. Anche la maggior parte dei nostri PDF è scaricabile e stiamo lavorando per rendere disponibile quanto prima il download di tutti gli altri file. Per maggiori informazioni, clicca qui
Che differenza c'è tra i piani?
Entrambi i piani ti danno accesso illimitato alla libreria e a tutte le funzionalità di Perlego. Le uniche differenze sono il prezzo e il periodo di abbonamento: con il piano annuale risparmierai circa il 30% rispetto a 12 rate con quello mensile.
Cos'è Perlego?
Perlego è un servizio di abbonamento a testi accademici, che ti permette di accedere a un'intera libreria online a un prezzo inferiore rispetto a quello che pagheresti per acquistare un singolo libro al mese. Con oltre 1 milione di testi suddivisi in più di 1.000 categorie, troverai sicuramente ciò che fa per te! Per maggiori informazioni, clicca qui.
Perlego supporta la sintesi vocale?
Cerca l'icona Sintesi vocale nel prossimo libro che leggerai per verificare se è possibile riprodurre l'audio. Questo strumento permette di leggere il testo a voce alta, evidenziandolo man mano che la lettura procede. Puoi aumentare o diminuire la velocità della sintesi vocale, oppure sospendere la riproduzione. Per maggiori informazioni, clicca qui.
Information, Natural Law, and the Self-Assembly of Rhythmic Movement è disponibile online in formato PDF/ePub?
Sì, puoi accedere a Information, Natural Law, and the Self-Assembly of Rhythmic Movement di Peter N. Kugler, Michael T. Turvey in formato PDF e/o ePub, così come ad altri libri molto apprezzati nelle sezioni relative a Psychologie e Experimentelle Psychologie. Scopri oltre 1 milione di libri disponibili nel nostro catalogo.

Informazioni

Editore
Routledge
Anno
2015
ISBN
9781317301080
Edizione
1
Argomento
Psychologie

1 Perspectives on Rhythmic Movement

Abstract

Rhythmic activity, such as bipedal and quadrupedal locomotion, obviously has a neural substrate. It is not clear, however, that a neurally oriented analysis of rhythmic movement will reveal its mechanism. Nor is it clear that the closely related motor-program perspective, with its emphasis on symbol strings, can provide much help in this matter. Arbitrariness plagues both of the orthodox perspectives on rhythmic movement, given their mutual lack of principled constraints. The first chapter sketches a law-based approach to animal movement, intimating how an account of biological phenomena might be fashioned that is methodologically continuous with the physical sciences. It identifies a central claim that natural phenomena at all scales are organized by a common set of (physical) strategies, although each scale may exhibit unique regularities. At their own scale, living systems are open to exchanges of matter and energy, they are self-sustaining and nondeterminate and they are dominated by information more than they are by forces. These characteristics of living things are discussed as factors that shape the regularities defining a physics of animal movement.

1.1. Rhythmic Phenomena in Biology

Rhythmic phenomena abound in biology at all levels of analysis (Aschoff, 1979; Berridge, Rupp, & Treherne, 1979; Iberall, 1972; Winfree, 1980). At the behavioral level, rhythms can be observed in which the entire body or parts of the body move in a cyclic, repetitive fashion. Running, swimming, flying, breathing, chewing, and grooming are the most cited examples, but rhythmic behaviors need not be so stereotypic, a fact attested to by the musical accomplishments of humans.
Although they are commonplace, behavioral rhythmicities are not well understood. To date, the efforts of neuroscience to explain behavior such as locomotion have been shaped in part by the issue of whether the behavior is generated centrally, by properties intrinsic to the central nervous system, or whether it is achieved by sensory feedback from moving parts of the body (Delcomyn, 1980; Evarts, Bizzi, Burke, Delong & Thach, 1971). Conventional wisdom and the weight of evidence favor the view of central pattern generation: A repetitive rhythmic output is said to be the product of a neural "oscillator" conceived either as a single pacemaker neuron (e.g., Maynard, 1972) or as a network of neurons (e.g., Wilson & Waldron, 1968).
The pioneering work of von Hoist (1935/1973), an early proponent of central-pattern generators, addressed the problem of the coupling of two or more neural oscillators. This problem arises as soon as the focus of inquiry into locomotion shifts from the rhythmicity of a single limb or body segment to the rhythmicity of the locomotory act in full. Examination of the coupled rhythmic movements of the pectoral and dorsal fins of fish that swim with the main body axis immobile led to the identification of two major classes of mutual influence. One of these influences, termed "superposition," is manifest (primarily) in the amplitude of the rhythmic movements, while the other influence, termed the "magnet effect," is manifest in their frequencies. Treating the generators of individual fin rhythmicity as automatisms, von Hoist (1935/1973) regarded the magnet effect as the tendency of automatisms to attract each other to their respective preferred tempos, von Hoist regarded the magnet effect as general: Not only did it operate in the coupling of individual automatisms but it operated in the coupling of the cells that comprise an individual automatism. Further, he observed that when two or more automatisms converged on a common, stable frequency, they lost nothing of their individuality (see also Arsharvskii, Kots, Orlovskii, Rodionov & Shik, 1965; Shik & Orlovskii, 1965). Individual preference for this or that frequency remained, suggesting that the coordinated rhythmic states exhibited by the collection of rhythm generators comprised continuously competing tendencies among components. Although some of von Hoist's empirical claims have been questioned (e.g., Roberts, 1967) the foregoing observations remain secure (Stein, 1977). In retrospect, they are observations that place locomotion squarely in the class of cooperative phenomena (Haken, 1977). How is this locomotory instance of cooperativity to be understood?

1.2. Hard-Molded and Soft-Molded Rhythmic Movements

Where explanations of rhythmic behavior such as locomotion have been neural in their focus, the tendency has been to regard the behavior in question as hard molded (hard wired, hard geared, hard coupled, hard guided, and hard algorithmed). These terms, borrowed from engineering, refer, in general, to the directing of "signals" along rigidly determined kinematic paths. The commonly proposed neural mechanisms, as noted, are single cells or ensembles of cells specialized for the generation of behavioral rhythmicities. Of the two, the specialized ensemble or network is thought to be the more general mechanism. A central pattern generator works, presumably, by guiding the chemico-electrical field along hard constraints (specific neural pathways linking specific neural elements) to produce periodic tensile states in the associated musculature. Selverston (1980) has argued that understanding how a hard-molded central pattern generator works for any given instance of rhythmicity is equated with identifying all of the ensemble's neural elements, all of the membrane and synaptic properties of those elements, and all of the connections among them. Putting aside doubts about the success of such a program (see Selverston, 1980, and commentaries) there are questions of its propriety. Rhythmic motions of the body can be, and frequently are, soft molded (soft wired, soft geared, soft coupled, soft guided, and soft algorithmed), which is to say, loosely speaking, that a biokinematic system with periodic behavior can be assembled temporarily and for a particular purpose from whatever neural and skeletomuscular elements are available and befitting the task.
Both hard and soft construction of rhythmic movements must follow from principles that govern the cyclic mode of biological organization in general. An account of hard-molded periodic behavior might be pursued without identifying these principles, but a satisfactory account of soft-molded periodic behavior cannot be attempted without them. In their basic format these principles are not likely to be unique to biology. An educated guess is that they are to be numbered among the few universally generalizable principles of physics (Morowitz, 1968, 1978; Yates & Iberall, 1973). Understanding the production of rhythmic movements that are softly molded from biological materials must rest on an understanding of how a specific set of strategies can be realized in distinct morphological settings subject to very general laws (cf. Iberall & Soodak, 1986). A program for understanding soft-molded behavior contrasts with that identified above for hard-molded rhythmic behavior in that it must give priority to physical law.
On at least two counts, it would seem that a law-oriented program is essential to the success of a neural-oriented program, regardless of whether the latter's target is an understanding of hard, or hard and soft, instances of rhythmic behaviors. First, there is the issue of how to constrain rationally the choice of relevant properties to be studied. Ideally one wishes to manipulate those parameters of the central pattern generator that govern its operation. Unfortunately, the parameter set of a neural ensemble contains, by some counts, 46 entries that could be relevant to a neurophysiological explanation (Bullock, 1975). Principles beyond those of neurophysiology are required to guide the selection of parameters. Second, there is the issue of how to explain the characteristic quantities of a rhythmic behavior—for example, its period, amplitude, and energy per cycle. These quantities cannot be rationalized on neural considerations alone.

1.3. The Concept of Motor Program

It is a small step from the concept of central pattern generator to that of motor program. Often the two concepts are used interchangeably. Like the concept of central pattern generator, the motor-program concept is a "centralist" counterpoint to the "peripheralist" treatment of rhythmic movement (as a concatenation of reflexively mediated, afferent-efferent connections). At the core of the centralist view is the recognition that the spatiotemporal details of a cycle of locomotion appear, in very large part, to be anticipated. By the peripheralist account, the successive and adjacent order of the skeletomuscular variables and their magnitudes are determined during the cyclic movement on a moment-to-moment basis. In contrast, the centralist account regards the successive and adjacent order of the skeletomuscular variables and the ballpark magnitudes of these variables as being determined prior to the cyclic movement. There are moment-to-moment influences, but these are reflected mainly in the magnitudes of the variables (as a fine tuning) and minimally in their ordering. Some proponents of the centralist view (e.g., Keele, 1968) have ruled out fed-back influences. But as others have pointed out, this prohibition is unwarranted (e.g., Reed, 1982; Schmidt, 1982) and inconsistent with the concept of program (MacKay, 1980). By definition, a program must receive (negations and affirmations) as well as give (instructions).
An example of a programming formulation of a step cycle in locomotion is provided by MacKay (1980) and reproduced in Figure 1.1. As can be seen, the kinematic and kinetic details are ordered by a sequence of commands and queries. The commands and queries are symbol strings that guide the performance of the step cycle: They function to constrain the continuous dynamical process by which the step cycle is realized. The contrast between rate-independent symbol strings and rate-dependent dynamical processes is said by Pattee (1973, 1977, 1979) to identify a complementarity principle. For Pattee, this particular complementarity is the hallmark of living systems. His argument is that living systems operate in two modes, the symbolic and the dynamic, which are incompatible and irreducible. Consequently, for Pattee, understanding biological phenomena (such as rhythmic movements) rests with the elaboration of this complementarity. By Pattee's view, the motor-program approach is flawed to the extent that it emphasizes the discrete symbolic mode to the neglect of the continuous dynamical mode. The phenomena in question are the result of a mutuality between the two modes.
FIGURE 1.1. A MOTOR PROGRAM PERSPECTIVE ON THE LOCOMOTORY STEP CYCLE (adapted from MacKay, 1980).
FIGURE 1.1. A MOTOR PROGRAM PERSPECTIVE ON THE LOCOMOTORY STEP CYCLE (adapted from MacKay, 1980).
There is, however, an inequality between the discrete symbolic and continuous dynamical modes that has to be appreciated. Nature uses the symbolic mode—nonholonomic, nonintegrable constraints (see Pattee, 1983, 1986; and Appendix A)—sparingly. Dynamics are used to the fullest, wherever and whenever, to achieve characteristic biological effects (see also Gould, 1966; Gould & Lewontin, 1979). Symbol strings are used, now and then, to direct dynamical processes and to limit their complexity—in other words, to trim the dynamical degrees of freedom. In Figure 1.1 the opposite strategy is at work. Very many nonholonomic constraints are exploited to achieve ("to explain") the kinetic and kinematic regularities of a locomotory step cycle. The question of how the dynamics, properly construed for the biological scale, might fashion the phenomenon is ignored. Also ignored is the question of how the symbol strings interface with the dynamics.
Pattee's analysis is an important one (see Carello, Turvey, Kugler, & Shaw, 1984) for the motor-program perspective (given that perspective's emphasis on the symbolic mode) because it suggests that only in the working out of the physics of a regularity can one identify the nature and type of symbol strings (nonholonomic constraints) needed to complete the explanation. Beginning with the symbolic mode, and adhering strictly to it, invites an account (of coordinated movement, for example) that will be plagued by arbitrariness. Beginning with the dynamical mode—that is, taking a law-based approach—and pursuing it earnestly promises an account that will be principled.

1.4. Physical Biology

Broadly construed, a law-oriented program is an attempt to give an account of biological phenomena (such as rhythmic movement) that is continuous with physical methodologies. A physical approach to biology views living systems as ordinary physical systems of great complexity; all biophysical transformations must ...

Indice dei contenuti

  1. Cover
  2. Title
  3. Copyright
  4. Original Title
  5. Original Copyright
  6. Dedication
  7. Contents
  8. Foreword Physics and Biology
  9. Introduction Physical and Neurophysiological Perspectives on Movement
  10. Preface
  11. Acknowledgments
  12. 1. PERSPECTIVES ON RHYTHMIC MOVEMENT
  13. 2. PROBLEMS OF MEASUREMENT AND MODELING
  14. 3. WHY THINGS FLOW: AN OUTLINE OF PHYSICAL THEORY FOR SIMPLE ATOMISMS
  15. 4. WHY THINGS FLOW: AN OUTLINE OF PHYSICAL THEORY FOR COMPLEX ATOMISMS
  16. 5. WHY THINGS "TICK": PHYSICAL PREREQUISITES FOR SELF-SUSTAINED OSCILLATION
  17. 6. AN EXPERIMENTAL METHODOLOGY FOR INVESTIGATING THE SOFT, SELF-ASSEMBLY OF THE PENDULAR, CLOCKING MODE
  18. 7. HAPTIC INFORMATION AS THE ABSTRACTED MORPHOLOGY OF MOVEMENT DYNAMICS
  19. 8. THE SCALING RELATION OF NATURAL PERIOD TO MASS AND LENGTH
  20. 9. MEASURING THE ENERGY FOR COORDINATION
  21. 10. SPACING IN THE PENDULAR CLOCKING MODE: THE THEORY OF CONDITIONAL PERIODICITY AND ADIABATIC INVARIANTS IN OPEN CONSERVATIVE AND NONCONSERVATIVE SYSTEMS
  22. 11. ASSEMBLING AND SUSTAINING ESCAPEMENTS FOR BIOMECHANICAL OSCILLATION: IDENTIFYING THE ENGINE (CHEMICAL-THERMAL-MECHANICAL) PROCESS
  23. 12. THE ADIABATIC HYPOTHESIS AND THE PROPORTIONING OF SPACE TO MASS, LENGTH, AND PERIOD: EXPERIMENTAL EVALUATIONS
  24. 13. INTENTIONALITY AND UNITS OF ACTION
  25. Epilogue
  26. Appendix A: Holonomic and Non-Holonomic Constraints
  27. Appendix B: Collisions and Fracture
  28. Appendix C: Huygens' Derivation of the Center of Oscillation
  29. Appendix D: Physical Laws, Structural Stability, and Dimensional Homogenity
  30. Appendix E: Natural Law and Adjunctive Logic
  31. Author Index
  32. Subject Index
Stili delle citazioni per Information, Natural Law, and the Self-Assembly of Rhythmic Movement

APA 6 Citation

Kugler, P., & Turvey, M. (2015). Information, Natural Law, and the Self-Assembly of Rhythmic Movement (1st ed.). Taylor and Francis. Retrieved from https://www.perlego.com/book/1644059/information-natural-law-and-the-selfassembly-of-rhythmic-movement-pdf (Original work published 2015)

Chicago Citation

Kugler, Peter, and Michael Turvey. (2015) 2015. Information, Natural Law, and the Self-Assembly of Rhythmic Movement. 1st ed. Taylor and Francis. https://www.perlego.com/book/1644059/information-natural-law-and-the-selfassembly-of-rhythmic-movement-pdf.

Harvard Citation

Kugler, P. and Turvey, M. (2015) Information, Natural Law, and the Self-Assembly of Rhythmic Movement. 1st edn. Taylor and Francis. Available at: https://www.perlego.com/book/1644059/information-natural-law-and-the-selfassembly-of-rhythmic-movement-pdf (Accessed: 14 October 2022).

MLA 7 Citation

Kugler, Peter, and Michael Turvey. Information, Natural Law, and the Self-Assembly of Rhythmic Movement. 1st ed. Taylor and Francis, 2015. Web. 14 Oct. 2022.