The Palgrave Handbook of Practical Animal Ethics
eBook - ePub

The Palgrave Handbook of Practical Animal Ethics

Andrew Linzey, Clair Linzey, Andrew Linzey, Clair Linzey

  1. English
  2. ePUB (disponibile sull'app)
  3. Disponibile su iOS e Android
eBook - ePub

The Palgrave Handbook of Practical Animal Ethics

Andrew Linzey, Clair Linzey, Andrew Linzey, Clair Linzey

Dettagli del libro
Anteprima del libro
Indice dei contenuti
Citazioni

Informazioni sul libro

This handbook provides an in-depth examination of the practical and theoretical issues within the emerging field of animal ethics. Leading experts from around the globe offer insights into cutting edge topics as diverse as killing for food, religious slaughter, animal companions, aquariums, genetic manipulation, hunting for sport and bullfighting. Including contributions from Lisa Johnson on the themes of human dominance, Thomas White on the ethics of captivity, Mark Bernstein on the ethics of killing and Kay Peggs on the causation of suffering, this handbook offers an authoritative reference work for contemporary applied animal ethics. Progressive in approach, the authors explore the challenges that animal ethics poses both conceptually and practically to traditional understandings of human–animal relations.

Key Features:

· Structured in four parts to examine the ethics of control, the ethics of captivity, the ethics of killing and the ethics of causing suffering

· Interdisciplinary approach including philosophical, historical, scientific, legal, anthropological, religious, psychological and sociological perspectives

· Focussed treatment of practical issues such as animals in farming, zoos and animal experimentation

The Palgrave Handbook of Practical Animal Ethics is an essential resource for those with an interest in the ethics of modern-day treatment of animals as well as scholars, researchers and advanced students in zoology, philosophy, anthropology, religious studies and sociology.

Domande frequenti

Come faccio ad annullare l'abbonamento?
È semplicissimo: basta accedere alla sezione Account nelle Impostazioni e cliccare su "Annulla abbonamento". Dopo la cancellazione, l'abbonamento rimarrà attivo per il periodo rimanente già pagato. Per maggiori informazioni, clicca qui
È possibile scaricare libri? Se sì, come?
Al momento è possibile scaricare tramite l'app tutti i nostri libri ePub mobile-friendly. Anche la maggior parte dei nostri PDF è scaricabile e stiamo lavorando per rendere disponibile quanto prima il download di tutti gli altri file. Per maggiori informazioni, clicca qui
Che differenza c'è tra i piani?
Entrambi i piani ti danno accesso illimitato alla libreria e a tutte le funzionalità di Perlego. Le uniche differenze sono il prezzo e il periodo di abbonamento: con il piano annuale risparmierai circa il 30% rispetto a 12 rate con quello mensile.
Cos'è Perlego?
Perlego è un servizio di abbonamento a testi accademici, che ti permette di accedere a un'intera libreria online a un prezzo inferiore rispetto a quello che pagheresti per acquistare un singolo libro al mese. Con oltre 1 milione di testi suddivisi in più di 1.000 categorie, troverai sicuramente ciò che fa per te! Per maggiori informazioni, clicca qui.
Perlego supporta la sintesi vocale?
Cerca l'icona Sintesi vocale nel prossimo libro che leggerai per verificare se è possibile riprodurre l'audio. Questo strumento permette di leggere il testo a voce alta, evidenziandolo man mano che la lettura procede. Puoi aumentare o diminuire la velocità della sintesi vocale, oppure sospendere la riproduzione. Per maggiori informazioni, clicca qui.
The Palgrave Handbook of Practical Animal Ethics è disponibile online in formato PDF/ePub?
Sì, puoi accedere a The Palgrave Handbook of Practical Animal Ethics di Andrew Linzey, Clair Linzey, Andrew Linzey, Clair Linzey in formato PDF e/o ePub, così come ad altri libri molto apprezzati nelle sezioni relative a Filosofia e Filosofia etica e morale. Scopri oltre 1 milione di libri disponibili nel nostro catalogo.

Informazioni

Anno
2018
ISBN
9781137366719
© The Author(s) 2018
A. Linzey, C. Linzey (eds.)The Palgrave Handbook of Practical Animal EthicsThe Palgrave Macmillan Animal Ethics Serieshttps://doi.org/10.1057/978-1-137-36671-9_1
Begin Abstract

1. Introduction: The Challenge of Animal Ethics

Andrew Linzey1 and Clair Linzey1
(1)
Oxford Centre for Animal Ethics, Oxford, UK
Andrew Linzey (Corresponding author)
Clair Linzey
End Abstract

I

In Brigid Brophy’s novel Hackenfeller’s Ape, a scientist called Professor Clement Darrelhyde faces a dilemma. He has moral qualms about the treatment of apes in his laboratory, including one ape in particular, called Percy, who is to be used in a rocket experiment. The following dialogue with his colleague—called Post—illustrates Darrelhyde’s concern:
“My dear fellow,” Post began. “I had no idea you took it so seriously. But you must adapt yourself to life. You must accept things.”
“Accept what things?”
Post shrugged. “You should know. The oldest adage in natural history—nature red in tooth and claw.”
Darrelhyde did not answer.
“Correct me if I am wrong,” Post continued, “but isn’t that how Evolution works? The strong exploiting the weak all the way up the line?”
The Professor examined himself. His Evolutionary belief had itself been evolving in these last months. It no longer seemed to him that Evolution proceeded by strengthening the strong: rather it used as its vessel the weak and inadequate, as though they possessed some special felicity that was more fertile than strength.1
That developed evolutionary sense, what might be termed “moral evolution,” is the subject of this handbook. It was indeed unusual in 1953 (when Brophy’s book was first published) for experimental scientists to include animals within their moral purview, even more so to risk a distinguished academic reputation as Darrelhyde did. But since the 1950s, a great deal has changed about the world, not least of all our moral attitudes toward animals. Once a neglected topic on the periphery of moral concern, the “animal movement” (for want of a better term) now has taken root in almost every country in the world.
Brophy knew what she was doing, of course. She was a committed antivivisectionist or, in more modern terms, was opposed in principle to using animals in harmful research. Darrelhyde’s words represent her own thoughts. She was a convinced atheist (a patron of the British Humanist Association), a fellow believer in evolution, and also a patron of the National Anti-Vivisection Society. And her role in the emergence of the modern animal movement was not insignificant.
Her 1965 Sunday Times article titled “The Rights of Animals”2 brought the issue to public prominence after years of neglect. Although there were certainly other important voices, such as Justus George Lawler,3 her fame and skill as a writer made people sit up and take notice. But it was the 1971 book Animals, Men and Morals: An Enquiry into the Maltreatment of Non-Humans,4 edited by three Oxford graduate students, to which she contributed, that really put animals on the intellectual agenda. It was later dubbed by Peter Singer as “a manifesto for an Animal Liberation movement.”5 The book was one result of the so-called Oxford Group, composed largely of students and academics. The term “Oxford Group,”6 coined by Richard D. Ryder, is something of a misnomer since the various individuals never met all together and had no plan, strategy, or program as such. But it was a time of intellectual ferment, and from that rather unlikely collection of people (philosophers, a sociologist, a psychologist, and a theologian) emerged a cluster of pioneering books, including Peter Singer’s Animal Liberation,7 Richard D. Ryder’s Victims of Science,8 Andrew Linzey’s Animal Rights: A Christian Assessment,9 and Stephen R. L. Clark’s The Moral Status of Animals.10
The title of Brophy’s 1965 article, “The Rights of Animals,” became the title of the Royal Society for the Prevention of Cruelty to Animal’s (hereafter “RSPCA”) symposium held at Trinity College in Cambridge in 1977, organized by Linzey (then, with Ryder, a council member of the RSPCA). Both Ryder and Linzey were members of the RSPCA Reform Group that sought to change the society’s policies in a progressive direction and, not least of all, to move the society on from its tacit support for foxhunting. The symposium brought together most of the emerging thinkers and intellectuals concerned with animal protection and provided a catalyst for change. The “Declaration against Speciesism” signed by 150 people at the conclusion of the symposium set the intellectual scene for subsequent decades:
Inasmuch as we believe that there is ample evidence that many other species are capable of feeling, we condemn totally the infliction of suffering upon our brother animals, and the curtailment of their enjoyment, unless it be necessary for their own individual benefit.
We do not accept that a difference of species alone (any more than a difference in race) can justify wanton exploitation or oppression in the name of science or sport, or for food, commercial profit or other human gain.
We believe in the evolutionary and moral kinship of all animals and we declare our belief that all sentient creatures have rights to life, liberty and the quest for happiness.
We call for the protection of these rights.11
Brophy’s contribution to the symposium, interestingly enough, was titled “The Darwinist’s Dilemma.” She explained the origin of her 1965 article by saying she intended to deliberately associate the case for animals with that “clutch of egalitarian or libertarian ideas which have sporadically ... come to the rescue of other oppressed classes, such as slaves, or homosexuals or women.” And she invoked the notion of rights specifically because they are “a matter of respect and justice, which are constant and can be required of you by force of argument; they are not a matter of love, which is capricious and quite involuntary.”12
Then she turned directly to her dilemma or (as she later called it) “conundrum”:
When I feed the pigeons, I shut my cat out of the room. This is a small infringement of his rights, imposed on him by me by main force. I think it justified, in the interest of the pigeons’ rights, because if I didn’t he would surely have one of my plump, peanut-fed pigeons for his lunch.
If I lunched on the pigeon, I should think myself immoral. If you do so, I must in all honesty say I think you immoral. But I don’t think my cat immoral. I think him amoral. The whole dimension of morality doesn’t apply to him, or scarcely applies to him.
Here then is the conundrum. Am I setting up my species as morally superior to the cat species? Have I torn down the old class barrier only to rebuild it in moral terms?13
Brophy here delineates one important feature of animal ethics: it concerns humans’ treatment of animals and not the treatment of animals by other animals. “Do animals really need ethics?” is a usual, if erroneous, comment sometimes made by those who are new to the subject—erroneous because it muddles (as many commentators still do) the realm of nature with the realm of morality. Nature is not a moral textbook either for animals or for humans. We shall return to this point later. But for now, the key thing is to grasp that humans are moral agents in a way that animals cannot be. Even if, as some have claimed, animals have moral sense or are capable of some forms of altruism, they are not moral agents responsible for their actions.14 This means that animal ethics are essentially human ethics, and their remit is human actions, individually or collectively, intentionally or half-intentionally, toward animals. That does not mean, of course, that animal ethicists are indifferent to the sum total of suffering and death in the natural world, and if there are ways to alleviate that death and suffering, caused through human or even sometimes natural agency, then animal ethicists should be in the forefront of championing them. But animal ethicists, whether they be Darwinian or religious, cannot change the natural world as we experience it with its complex biological systems of parasitism and predation. Like Brophy, we have to conclude that although we cannot change the (natural) world, we can change ourselves—and that is the moral point.
It would be a mistake, however, to suppose that sensitivity to animals is a post-1970s phenomenon. There have been ethical voices for animals as far back as the pre-Socratics. However, that sensitivity has been characterized by moments of intellectual advancement and social embodiment. One good example of the latter was the foundation in 1824 of the RSPCA, which pioneered legislation and sought to enforce it through a system of inspectors. And probably the best example of intellectual advancement was the movement from the 1970s.

II

How then should we characterize animal ethics? We collect here some of the essential elements. For clarity, we need to begin with what animal ethics rejects, which can be classified under three headings.15
The first is anthropocentrism. By “moral anthropocentrism,” we mean the assumption that human needs, wants, or desires should have absolute or near absolute priority in our moral calculations. As already noted, there have been thinkers who have challenged moral anthropocentrism in almost every age, but such ideas have often lacked any organizational or institutional backing and have therefore had limited social influence.
Perhaps the most obvious example of moral anthropocentrism stems from the perceived relation between justice and friendship. Aristotle was clear that there could be no friendship between the ruler and the ruled—“for where there is nothing in common to ruler and ruled,” he writes, “there is not friendship either, since there is no justice.”16 Aristotle provides examples of how there is no justice between humans and inanimate (“lifeless”) objects, since “each case is benefited by that which uses it.” He further explains that “neither is there friendship towards a horse or an ox, nor to a slave qua slave.”17 A...

Indice dei contenuti

  1. Cover
  2. Front Matter
  3. 1. Introduction: The Challenge of Animal Ethics
  4. Section I. The Ethics of Control
  5. Section II. The Ethics of Captivity
  6. Section III. The Ethics of Killing
  7. Section IV. The Ethics of Causing Suffering
  8. Back Matter
Stili delle citazioni per The Palgrave Handbook of Practical Animal Ethics

APA 6 Citation

[author missing]. (2018). The Palgrave Handbook of Practical Animal Ethics ([edition unavailable]). Palgrave Macmillan UK. Retrieved from https://www.perlego.com/book/3488067/the-palgrave-handbook-of-practical-animal-ethics-pdf (Original work published 2018)

Chicago Citation

[author missing]. (2018) 2018. The Palgrave Handbook of Practical Animal Ethics. [Edition unavailable]. Palgrave Macmillan UK. https://www.perlego.com/book/3488067/the-palgrave-handbook-of-practical-animal-ethics-pdf.

Harvard Citation

[author missing] (2018) The Palgrave Handbook of Practical Animal Ethics. [edition unavailable]. Palgrave Macmillan UK. Available at: https://www.perlego.com/book/3488067/the-palgrave-handbook-of-practical-animal-ethics-pdf (Accessed: 15 October 2022).

MLA 7 Citation

[author missing]. The Palgrave Handbook of Practical Animal Ethics. [edition unavailable]. Palgrave Macmillan UK, 2018. Web. 15 Oct. 2022.