Vygotsky
eBook - ePub

Vygotsky

Philosophy and Education

  1. English
  2. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  3. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Vygotsky

Philosophy and Education

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

Vygotsky Philosophy and Education reassesses the works of Russian psychologist Lev Vygotsky work by arguing that his central ideas about the nature of rationality and knowledge were informed by the philosophic tradition of Spinoza and Hegel.

  • Presents a reassessment of the works of Lev Vygotsky inlight of the tradition of Spinoza and Hegel informing his work
  • Reveals Vygotsky's connection with the work of contemporary philosophers such as Brandom and McDowell
  • Draws on discussions in contemporary philosophy to revise prominent readings of Vygotskian psychology and revisits educational debates where Vygotsky's ideas were central
  • Reveals the limitations of appropriations of Vygotsky which fail to recognize the Hegelian provenance of his work
  • Shows the relevance of Brandom's inferentialism for contemporary educational theory and practice

Frequently asked questions

Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Yes, you can access Vygotsky by Jan Derry in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Philosophy & Philosophy History & Theory. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Year
2013
ISBN
9781118368756

1

Introduction

This book is a response to the claim that Vygotsky holds abstract rationality as the pinnacle of thought. The claim is based on the belief that Vygotsky subscribed to what is referred to as the ‘Enlightenment project’. The book aims to show that Vygotsky had a far more sophisticated appreciation both of reason and of its remit than this fashionable characterisation implies. Its argument is developed through an exploration of some aspects of the philosophy of Hegel and Spinoza, to both of whom Vygotsky acknowledges a debt. In the dominant, predominantly psychological research literature, the nature of the philosophical underpinnings of Vygotsky’s work tends to receive little attention. Not only is that neglect contested here, but the argument is carried a stage further, claiming that the limitations that critics see in Vygotsky’s work are based on misapprehensions of his understanding of reason. In support of this it is argued that Hegel’s investigation of the presuppositions of claims to knowledge already contains a critique of the frame of reference used by these commentators – commentators who view Vygotsky, in this aspect of his work, as having an ‘old-fashioned’ conception of reason that cannot do justice to diversity.
A recurring theme of this book is Vygotsky’s conception of the nature of abstract reason, but such are the ramifications of this that it is necessary to go well beyond an examination of any particular aspect of Vygotsky’s work. Vygotsky was concerned above all with questions of education. While education may appear to be non-philosophical and certainly to lie outside the range of what most philosophers write about, it has, by virtue of its direct involvement with thought and intellect, a philosophical dimension. As education leads towards philosophy, so philosophy can gain from an engagement with education, precisely because the latter is not only engaged with questions of mind and world but engaged with them in a real and practical sense.
It was Piaget, with his genetic epistemology, who brought the study of the development of faculties into direct contact with philosophy. Vygotsky, Piaget’s contemporary, appreciated that any inquiry on the part of philosophy into the nature of mind and world could not be separated from the study of the mind in its development. Those familiar with Vygotsky’s work will appreciate the extent of his influence within education and also be aware of the debates about pedagogy and knowledge that his work has generated. Accordingly, although this book focuses on the question of abstract reason in Vygotsky, it concludes by illustrating how the philosophical tradition that inspired Vygotsky has significant implications for these debates.
While Vygotsky was explicit about the importance of philosophy for theory, he did not actually spell out the philosophy that informed his argument, yet this omission, if this is how it is to be judged, does not detract from the subtlety and sophistication of his approach. The dualism of the ideal and real, of mind and world, that has underpinned criticism of Vygotsky both in his own time and in the current period has been taken up not only by his follower Evald Ilyenkov, but also by contemporary analytical philosophers. David Bakhurst has written on this directly: in claiming normativity to be a necessary element of the sociogenesis of mind, he has brought to our attention links between the philosophy of John McDowell and Ilyenkov. For modern philosophy the questions requiring careful analysis concern empiricism and knowing. The two contemporary philosophers whose work is most important in this book have both taken a Hegelian approach to make explicit points, which, though unexpressed, are necessarily assumed in the forms of argument that they analyse. In Mind and World McDowell addresses the problem of how a separate mind can connect with a world by working through a number of highly developed arguments about how we come to know. His enquiries lead to the unusual conclusion that, rather than possessing the means of thought solely in one’s head, ‘the dictates of reason are there [in the world] anyway, whether or not one’s eyes are open to them’ (McDowell, 1996, p. 91). Following Wilfrid Sellars, he refers to this sphere as ‘The Space of Reasons’.
For McDowell and also for Robert Brandom, the other contemporary philosopher whose work I shall highlight, this concept plays a crucial role. Simply summarised, the gist of the argument is that in order to make a claim of knowing we are not, as commonly thought, giving a description of an event but placing our claims about it in a space of reasons – that is to say, making claims on the basis of knowing what follows from them and what it is necessary to assume in order to make them in the first place. Where a word is used without the user being aware of its conceptual connections to other concepts, these connections are still present. The implication of Brandom’s argument is that context, not simply conscious intention, imparts reason. This approach, which results from bringing a Kantian argument to bear upon a Humean residue in empiricist conceptions of knowledge, identifies human knowing as fundamentally different from the ‘knowing’ of machines. For example, a human shout of ‘Fire!’ is fundamentally different as far as general awareness is concerned from the differential response of a fire alarm, though both are an alert to the same danger. For Brandom, what is distinctive about human beings is the ability to operate in the light of reasons rather than to respond simply to causes. McDowell refers to this as our second nature, emphasising our being human as something other than pure matter yet still part of nature.
When the distinction between the human and the natural is dualistically drawn as a distinction of mind and world, a clear boundary exists between the conceptual (mind) and the nonconceptual (nature). Such a distinction exists for Kant, but for McDowell, who adopts a Hegelian standpoint in Mind and World and speaks of the ‘unboundedness of the conceptual’, it is fundamentally misconceived. McDowell rejects the separation of mind and world underlying so much philosophy in favour of a frame of thought in which reasons exist in the world that humans have developed. In adopting this frame of thought McDowell takes up a position similar to Vygotsky’s. For both, mind is social and to give an account of mindedness and intellect it is necessary to look beyond the individual and to attend to external mediation in the formation of higher mental functions.
The arguments of McDowell, Brandom, Sellars, Bakhurst and, with them, Vygotsky cast a distinctive light on rationality and reason.1 In their hands these concepts take on quite a different shape from the mainstream of philosophical thought that comes through Descartes, Locke, Hume and Kant down to modern analytical philosophy. To give a bare outline, a once prevailing view in analytical philosophy presents rationality as abstract and decontextualised: it relies on the idea that reason is separated from the world and can be applied to it with greater or lesser degrees of adequacy. When applied to education such a position can lead to the most extreme forms of formalised teaching.
It is beyond the remit of this book to begin to spell out the many practical ­implications of the philosophical issues it considers. However, one topic must be mentioned that confirms that there are such implications and that these are of crucial importance. This is the way ‘abstract’ reason has been made the culprit for the poverty of educational practice in mass schooling. McDowell’s claim that receptivity – our experience of the world through our senses – is already ‘conceptual’ involves a conception of reason quite different from that with which critics such as James Wertsch quite correctly take issue – the extreme of a decontextualised schooled knowledge, presented without regard to its genetic development or any sense that learning involves actualising concepts. This matter of decontextualisation is taken up in Chapter 2, which presents the critique of Vygotsky’s alleged abstract rationalism and considers the theory of situated cognition which has been proposed in its place.
Chapter 3 turns to ‘constructivism’, which plays a central role in much post-Vygotskian thought. Criticism here is directed against what is argued to be the ‘representationalist paradigm’ implicit in conceptions of the active construction of meaning into a bare ‘given’. It is argued that constructivism leads to particular pedagogic strategies that, though not part of a more sophisticated analysis, are influential in the rhetoric of classroom practice, specifically the undermining of the authority of the teacher, of knowledge (in texts) and of the belief that knowledge is a matter of plurality in the sense that no one approach is superior to any other.
Chapter 4 uses the debate between Vygotsky and Piaget on conscious awareness, egocentrism and development to illustrate the differences between their philosophical backgrounds. The purpose of this chapter is to show how the different philosophical presuppositions of each author lead to different theoretical positions.
Chapter 5 turns to elements of Spinoza’s philosophy that influenced Vygotsky. In particular it is concerned with Spinoza’s formulation of knowing in terms of a holism of one substance of which everything is a part, as opposed to a dualism that assumes fundamental separations. Spinoza’s approach leads to a conception of truth not as an attribute but as an actualisation of a process understood as many-sided. From this standpoint, freedom appears quite differently from the Cartesian conception of wilful agency. It is understood as self-determination: to be free is to be the cause of oneself rather than subject to external causes, and this depends upon ‘adequate ideas’.
Chapter 6 turns to Hegel, who follows a similar approach to Spinoza, progressively ‘exorcising’ claims to know to reach a distinctive conception of knowing. This conception, rather than being based on secure foundations, sees new knowledge arising out of a working through of existing claims to knowledge to show that more is implicated than appears initially to be the case.
Chapter 7 considers this anti-foundationalist character of the philosophy of Spinoza, Hegel and Vygotsky in order to argue that the conception of reason ­central to Vygotsky’s work bears no relation to the caricature of abstract rationality criticised by contemporary post-Vygotskian researchers.
This order is not a linear sequence as the criticisms levelled against situated cognition and constructivism in Chapters 2 and 3 presuppose philosophical ideas that are not discussed until Chapters 5 and 6. On the other hand, those philosophical ideas would not make sense in the context of this book without an examination of post-Vygotskian research. Furthermore, it must be stressed that the later chapters are intended only to address those parts of Spinoza and Hegel that are relevant for understanding Vygotsky’s work. The aims of this book are: first, to show that Vygotsky was influenced by a different tradition of philosophy from that which has influenced post-Vygotskian research; and second, to demonstrate that this difference is significant and has implications for educational practice.
Apart from the complexities of the differences between the philosophical traditions, there is the additional difficulty that neither Vygotsky nor post-Vygotskian researchers spell out their philosophical presuppositions in detail. Vygotsky, it is true, acknowledged the philosophic influence on his thinking, and it is often only a matter of following the leads he gave to find his sources. With his commentators, however, things are much less clear and the scope for attributing to them positions they do not hold is necessarily that much greater. But it must be stressed that the criticisms made of various works of commentary on Vygotsky for failure to appreciate the significance of the philosophical traditions in which he was working stop far short of denying the value of the contribution of those traditions to the understanding of the nature of reason.

NOTES

1 Bakhurst’s The Formation of Reason (2011) offers an original defence of a sociohistorical ­account of mind that utilises the work of all the thinkers here mentioned, especially McDowell.

REFERENCES

Bakhurst, D. (2011) The Formation of Reason (Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell).
McDowell, J. (1996) Mind and World (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).

2

Situated Cognition and Contextualism

The interpretation of Vygotsky raises issues at the heart of contemporary debates in educational theory and practice, and nowhere is this more true than in connection with situated cognition and constructivism. The critical question here is how knowledge and understanding are related to immediate context, whether causally or ­constitutively or in some combination of these (Robbins and Aydede, 2009). This chapter and the next consider the division of opinion concerning situated cognition, contextualism and constructivism. But first, and in order to better place these ­matters within the main theme of this book, consideration is given to what has been termed ‘decontextualised rationality’. This will demonstrate the importance of placing Vygotsky’s work in its proper philosophical context and, hence, preventing the foreclosure of areas of investigation by commentators who do not pay it due regard.
‘Decontextualised rationality’ is a term used by Wertsch to characterise a ‘voice’ (in Bakhtin’s sense) or ‘social speech type’ that emerged with the Enlightenment:
The defining characteristic of the voice of decontextualised rationality is that it represents objects and events (i.e. referentially semantic content) in terms of ­formal, logical, and, if possible, quantifiable categories. The categories used in this form of representation are decontextualised in the sense that their meaning can be derived from their position in abstract theories or systems independent of particular speech contexts.1 (Wertsch, 1992, p. 120)
Wertsch goes on to write that ‘the voice of decontextualised rationality contrasts with “contextualised forms of representation” in that the latter represent events and objects in terms of their concrete particularity’ (p. 120). He sees the distinction between decontextualised rationality and contextualised forms of representation as particularly significant in the case of schooling: there, it seems, even when ‘other forms of representing the objects and operations at issue would do equally well or better’ (p. 120), decontextualised modes of discourse are privileged. The focal point of Wertsch’s argument is forms of ‘representation’, and, as we shall see below, the emphasis that he lays upon them has a decisive influence on his account of decontextualised rationality. The question of what precisely decontextualised rationality is and how it is best understood is not clearly worked out, but for Wertsch it has significant ramifications as his references to teaching and learning make clear.2 In the context of schooling the natural sciences and mathematics would ­typically fit Wertsch’s description of decontextualised rationality. For example, the concept electron takes its meaning from its position within a tightly bounded atomic theory. The application of the concept electron does not rely on any specific personal context for its sense. This can be distinguished from what Wertsch describes as ‘contextualised forms of representation … that … represent objects in terms of their concrete particularity’ (p. 120). In schools this might be associated with expressive subjects such as literature or art where the legitimacy of what Wertsch would call a different voice is not only acceptable but required. Wertsch’s concern is with the dominance of ‘the voice of decontextualised rationality’ in schooling. It is important to note that Wertsch’s work is set within a broader context of thought dealing with the nature of rationality. For instance, referring to Habermas’s analysis of instrumental rationality and to Lukács’s examination of reification, Wertsch points beyond formal instructional settings to a wider tendency in modern society to privilege the ‘decontextualised, rational voice’ (p. 121). In an educational context this theme appears in various works concerned with theoretical knowledge – for example, in Donald Schon’s critique of technical rationality (1983) and in Paul Hirst’s rethinking of the character of reason (Hirst, 2008) and its place in education.3 Here we are particularly concerned with Wertsch and his reading of Vygotsky and related literature. To grasp the nature of the issues involved it is necessary to consider the following: decontextualisation, theorising the institutional, historical background, situated cognition, the transfer problem and the question of determination.
The i...

Table of contents

  1. Cover
  2. The Journal of Philosophy of Education Book Series
  3. Title page
  4. Copyright page
  5. Series Editor Preface
  6. Preface
  7. 1 Introduction
  8. 2 Situated Cognition and Contextualism
  9. 3 Constructivism and Schooling
  10. 4 Vygotsky and Piaget
  11. 5 Spinoza and Free Will
  12. 6 Vygotsky, Hegel and the Critique of Abstract Reason
  13. 7 Vygotsky, Hegel and Education
  14. Index