Mathematical Modelling Techniques
eBook - ePub

Mathematical Modelling Techniques

  1. 288 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Mathematical Modelling Techniques

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

"Engaging, elegantly written." ā€” Applied Mathematical Modelling
Mathematical modelling is a highly useful methodology designed to enable mathematicians, physicists and other scientists to formulate equations from a given nonmathematical situation. In this elegantly written volume, a distinguished theoretical chemist and engineer sets down helpful rules not only for setting up models but also for solving the mathematical problems they pose and for evaluating models.
The author begins with a discussion of the term "model, " followed by clearly presented examples of the different types of models (finite, statistical, stochastic, etc.). He then goes on to discuss the formulation of a model and how to manipulate it into its most responsive form. Along the way Dr. Aris develops a delightful list of useful maxims for would-be modellers. In the final chapter he deals not only with the empirical validation of models but also with the comparison of models among themselves, as well as with the extension of a model beyond its original "domain of validity."
Filled with numerous examples, this book includes three appendices offering further examples treated in more detail. These concern longitudinal diffusion in a packed bed, the coated tube chromatograph with Taylor diffusion and the stirred tank reactor. Six journal articles, a useful list of references and subject and name indexes complete this indispensable, well-written guide.
"A most useful, readable-and stimulating-book, to be read both for pleasure and for enlightenment." ā€” Bulletin of the Institute of Mathematics and Its Applications

Frequently asked questions

Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on ā€œCancel Subscriptionā€ - itā€™s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time youā€™ve paid for. Learn more here.
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlegoā€™s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan youā€™ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, weā€™ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Yes, you can access Mathematical Modelling Techniques by Rutherford Aris in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Mathematics & Discrete Mathematics. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Year
2012
ISBN
9780486138893

1

What is a model?

e9780486138893_img_8038.gif
M
e9780486138893_img_941.gif
Ī½Ī±Ī½Ī“ĻĪµ
Īŗ
e9780486138893_img_8049.gif
Ī¹ Ī²
e9780486138893_img_943.gif
Īµ

Ļ€Ć³Ļ„ĪµĻĪæĻ‚
e9780486138893_img_7940.gif
Ļā€™
e9780486138893_img_973.gif
Āµ
e9780486138893_img_8182.gif
Ī½ Ļ€Ć³Ļ„ĪµĻoĪ½
e9780486138893_img_7936.gif
Ļ€ĪµĀµ
e9780486138893_img_617.gif
Āµ
e9780486138893_img_8053.gif
ĻƒĪ±Ļ„o
altr. to Aristophanes of Byzantium
Syrianus in Hermog. (Rabe ij 23)
(0 Menader, o life, which of you has imitated the other?)

1.1 The idea of a mathematical model and its relationship to other uses of of the word.

In these notes the term ā€˜mathematical modelā€™--usually abbreviated to ā€˜modelā€™--will be used for any complete and consistent set of mathematical equations which is thought to correspond to some other entity, its prototype. The prototype may be a physical, biological, social, psychological or conceptual entity, perhaps even another mathematical model, though in detailed examples we shall be concerned with a few physico-chemical systems.
Being derived from ā€˜modusā€™ (a measure) the word ā€˜modelā€™ implies a change of scale in its representation and only later in its history did it acquire the meaning of a type of design, as in Cromwellā€™s New Model Army (1645). still later (1788) came the complacent overtones of the exemplar that Gilbert was to use so effectively for his modern major general, while it is the first years of this century before fashion became so self-conscious as to claim its own models and make possible Kaplanā€™s double entendre (see quotation at head of Ch. 5). In the sense that we are seeking a different scale of thought or mode of understanding we are using the word in its older meaning. However, the word model (without the adjective ā€˜mathematicalā€™) has been and is used in a number of senses both by philosophers and scientists as merely glancing through the titles of the bibliography will suggest. Thus Apostel [7] distinguishes nine motivations underlying the use of models ranging from the replacement of a theory-less domain of facts by another for which a theory is known (e.g., network theory as a model for neurological phenomena) to the use of a model as a bridge between theory and observation. Suppes in the same volume [169] maintains that the logicians concept of a model is the same in the empirical sciences as in mathematics though the use to which they are put is different. The logicianā€™s definition he takes from Tarski [172] as: ā€œa possible realization in which all valid sentences of a theory T are satisfied is called a model of Tā€. This is a non-linguistic entity in which a theory is satisfied and Suppes draws attention to the confusion that can arise when model is used for the set of assumptions underlying a theory, i.e. the linguistic structure which is axiomatized. In our context this suggests that we might usefully distinguish between the prototype (i.e. the physical entity or system being modelled), the precursive assumptions or what the logicians call the theory of the model (i.e. the precise statement of the assumptions of axioms) and the model itself (i.e. the scheme of equations).
The idea of a change of scale which inheres in the notion of a model through its etymology can be variously interpreted. In so far as the prototype is a physical or natural object, the mathematical model represents a change on the scale of abstraction. Certain particularities will have been removed and simplifications made in obtaining the model. For this reason some hard-headed, practical-minded folk seem to regard the model as less ā€œrealā€ than the prototype. However from the logical point of view the prototype is in fact a realization in which the valid sentences of the mathematical model are to some degree satisfied. One could say that the prototype is a model of equations and the two enjoy the happy reciprocality of Menander and life.
The purpose for which a model is constructed should not be taken for granted but, at any rate initially, needs to be made explicit. Apostel (loc. cit.) recognizes this in his formalization of the modelling relationship R(S,P,M,T), which he describes as the subject S taking, in view of a purpose P, the entity M as a model for the prototype T. J. Maynard Smith [165] uses the notion of purpose to distinguish mathematical descriptions of ecological systems made for practical purposes from those whose purpose is theoretical. The former he calls ā€˜simulationsā€™ and points out that their value increases with the amount of particular detail that they incorporate. Thus in trying to predict the population of a pest the peculiarities of its propagation and predilections of its predators would be incorporated in the model with all the specific detail that could be mustered. But ecological theory also seeks to make general statements about the population growth that will discern the broad influence of the several factors that come into play. The mathematical descriptions that serve such theoretical purposes should include as little detail as possible but preserve the broad outline of the problem. These descriptions are called ā€˜modelsā€™ by Smith, who also comments on a remark of Levins [114] that the valuable results from such models are the indications, not of what is common to all species or systems, but of the differences between species of systems.
Hesse [92] in her excellent little monograph ā€œModels and Analogies in Scienceā€ distinguished two basic meanings of the word ā€˜modelā€™ as it is used in physics and Leatherdale in a very comprehensive discussion of ā€œThe Role of Analogy, Model and Metaphor in Scienceā€ has at least four. They stem from the methods of ā€œphysical analogyā€ introduced by Kelvin and Maxwell who used the partial resemblance between the laws of two sciences to make one serve as illustrator of the other. In the hands of 19th century English physicists these often took the form of the mechanical analogues that evoked Duhemā€™s famous passage of Gallic ire and irony. Duhem [56] had in mind that a physical theory should be a purely deductive structure from a small number of rather general hypotheses, but Campbell [41] claimed that this logical consistency was not enough and that links to or analogies with already established laws must be maintained. Leatherdaleā€™s four types are the formal and informal variants of Hesseā€™s two. Her ā€œmodel1ā€ is a copy, albeit imperfect, with certain features that are positively analogous and certain which are neutral but shorn of all features which are known to be negatively analogous, i.e. definitely dissimilar to the prototype. Her ā€œmodel2ā€ is the copy with all its features, good, bad and indifferent. Thus billiard balls in motion, colored and shiny, are a model2 for kinetic theory, whilst billiard balls in motion obeying perfectly the laws of mechanics but bereft of their colour, shine and all other non-molecular properties constitute a model1. It is the natural analogies (i.e. the features as yet of unknown relevance) that are regarded by Campbell as the growing points of a theory. In these terms a mathematical model would presumably be a formal model1.
Brodbeck [35], in the context of the social sciences, stresses the aspect of isomorphism and reciprocality when she defines a model by saying that if the laws of one theory have the same form as the laws of another theory, then one may be said to be a model for the other. There remains, of course, the problem of determining whether the two sets of laws are isomorphic. Brodbeck further distinguishes between two empirical theories as models one of the other and the situation when one theory is an ā€œarithmetical structureā€. She then goes on to describe three meanings of the term mathematical model according as the modelling theory is (a) any quantified empirical theory, (b) an arithmetic structure or (c) a mere formalization in which descriptive terms are given symbols in the attempt to lay bare the axioms or otherwis...

Table of contents

  1. Title Page
  2. Acknowledgments
  3. Copyright Page
  4. Preface
  5. Table of Contents
  6. 1 - What is a model?
  7. 2 - The different types of model
  8. 3 - How to formulate a model
  9. 4 - How should a model be manipulated into its most responsive form?
  10. 5 - How should a model be evaluated?
  11. Appendix A Longitudinal diffusion in a packed bed
  12. Appendix B The coated tube chromatograph and Taylor diffusion
  13. Appendix C The stirred tank reactor
  14. References
  15. Subject index
  16. Name index
  17. Re, k and Ļ€ : a conversation on some aspects of mathematical modelling
  18. THE JAIL OF SHAPE - RUTHERFORD ARIS
  19. THE MERE NOTION OF A MODEL - RUTHERFORD ARIS AND MISCHA PENN
  20. Ut Simulacrum, Poesis - Rutherford Aris
  21. FIFTH P. V. DANCKWERTS MEMORIAL LECTURE PRESENTED AT GLAZIERSā€™ HALL, LONDON, U.K. 16 OCTOBER 1990 - MANNERS MAKYTH MODELLERS
  22. HOW TO GET THE MOST OUT OF AN EQUATION WITHOUT REALLY TRYING*