Moral Education
eBook - ePub

Moral Education

  1. 304 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Moral Education

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

The great French sociologist and philosopher Emile Durkheim is best known for his classic book Suicide (1897), a landmark in social psychology. Among his other major works is this study in the sociology of education, which features 18 lectures by an influential theorist who discusses his ideas on the school as the appropriate setting for moral education. The first element in developing a moral being, he maintains, is instilling a sense of discipline, followed by a willingness to behave in terms of the group's collective interest, and a sense of autonomy. Durkheim also examines discipline and the psychology of the child, discipline of the school and the use of punishment, altruism in the child, the influence of the school environment, and the teaching of science, aesthetics, and history. Perceptive and provocative, this volume abounds in valuable insights for teachers and others involved in education.

Frequently asked questions

Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Yes, you can access Moral Education by Émile Durkheim in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Psychology & Social Psychology. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Year
2012
ISBN
9780486143453

CHAPTER ONE

INTRODUCTION: SECULAR MORALITY

I PROPOSE TO TALK ABOUT MORAL EDUCATION AS AN EDUCATOR; therefore, I ought to give you my conception of education at the very outset. I have previously suggested that we are not dealing with a science.4 A science of education is not impossible; but education itself is not that science. This distinction is necessary lest we judge education by standards applicable only to strictly scientific research. Scientific inquiry must proceed most deliberately; it does not have to meet deadlines. Education is not justified in being patient to the same extent; it must supply answers to vital needs that brook no delay. When a change in the environment demands appropriate action of us, our hand is forced. All that the educator can and should do is to combine as conscientiously as possible all the data that science puts at his disposal, at a given moment, as a guide to action. No one can ask more of him.
However, if education is not a science, neither is it an art. Art, indeed, is made up of habit, practice, and organized skills. Pedagogy is not the art of teaching; it is the savoir faire of the educator, the practical experience of the teacher.
What we have here are two clearly differentiated things: one may be a good teacher, yet not very clever at educational theory. Conversely, the educational theorist may be completely lacking in practical skill. It would have been unwise to entrust a class to Montaigne or to Rousseau; and the repeated failures of Pestalozzi prove that he was not a very good teacher. Education is therefore intermediate between art and science. It is not art, for it is not a system of organized practices but of ideas bearing on these practices. It is a body of theories. By that token it is close to science. However, scientific theory has only one goal—the expression of reality; whereas educational theories have the immediate aim of guiding conduct. While these theories do not constitute action in themselves, they are a preparation for it, and they are very close to it. Their raison d’être is in action. It is this dual nature that I have been trying to express in referring to education as a practical theory. The uses that may be expected of it are determined by this ambivalent nature. It is not action itself and thus cannot replace action. But it can provide insight into action. It is therefore useful to the extent that thought is useful to professional experience.
If educational theory goes beyond its proper limits, if it pretends to supplant experience, to promulgate ready-made formulae that are then applied mechanically, it degenerates into dead matter. If, on the other hand, experience disregards pedagogical thinking, it in turn degenerates into blind routine or else is at the mercy of ill-informed or unsystematic thinking. Educational theory essentially is the most methodical and best-documented thinking available, put at the service of teaching.
These preliminaries over, I can now go on to the problem of moral education. To treat this question methodically, we must look at the conditions under which it is posed today. It is within the framework of our traditional, national educational system that the crisis to which I have alluded before has reached particularly serious proportions. Let us examine it a little more closely.
The question is not only intrinsically interesting, to all teachers. It is especially urgent today. Anything that reduces the effectiveness of moral education, whatever disrupts patterns of relationships, threatens public morality at its very roots. The last twenty years in France have seen a great educational revolution, which was latent and half-realized before then. We decided to give our children in our state-supported schools a purely secular moral education. It is essential to understand that this means an education that is not derived from revealed religion, but that rests exclusively on ideas, sentiments, and practices accountable to reason only—in short, a purely rationalistic education.
Such a change could not take place without disturbing traditional ideas, disrupting old habits, entailing sweeping organizational changes, and without posing, in turn, new problems with which we must come to grips. 5
I know that I am now touching on questions that have the unfortunate effect of arousing passionate argument. But we must broach these questions resolutely. We cannot speak of moral education without being very clear as to the conditions under which we are educating. Otherwise we will bog down in vague and meaningless generalities. In this book, our aim is not to formulate moral education for man in general; but for men of our time in this country.
It is in our public schools that the majority of our children are being formed.6 These schools must be the guardians par excellence of our national character. They are the heart of our general education system. We must, therefore, focus our attention on them, and consequently on moral education as it is understood and practiced in them and as it should be understood and practiced. As a matter of fact, I am quite sure that if we bring to our discussion of these questions just a modicum of the scientific attitude, it will not be hard to treat them without arousing passions and without giving offense to legitimate feelings.
In the first place, a rational moral education is entirely possible; this is implied in the postulate that is at the basis of science. I refer to the rationalist postulate, which may be stated thus: there is nothing in reality that one is justified in considering as fundamentally beyond the scope of human reason. When I call this principle a postulate, I am in fact using a very improper expression. That principle had the character of a postulate when mind first undertook to master reality—if indeed one can say that this intellectual quest ever had a beginning. When science began to organize itself, it necessarily had to postulate that it, itself, was possible and that things could be expressed in scientific language—or, in other words, rational language, for the two terms are synonymous. However, something that, at the time, was only an anticipation of the mind, a tentative conjecture, found itself progressively demonstrated by all the results of science. It proved that facts should be connected with each other in accordance with rational relationships, by discovering the existence of such relationships.
There are of course many things—in fact, an infinity of things—of which we are still ignorant. Nothing guarantees that all of them will ever be discovered, that a moment will come when science will have finished its task and will have expressed adequately the totality of things. Rather, everything leads us to think that scientific progress will never end. But the rationalist principle does not imply that science can in fact exhaust the real. It only denies that one has the right to look at any part of reality or any category of facts as invincibly irreducible to scientific thought—in other words, as irrational in its essence.
Rationalism does not at all suppose that science can ever reach the limits of knowledge. If it is understood in this fashion, we might say that this principle is demonstrated by the history of science itself. The manner in which it has progressed shows that it is impossible to mark a point beyond which scientific explanation will become impossible. All the limits within which people have tried to contain it have only served as challenges for science to surpass them. Whenever people thought that science had reached its ultimate limit, it resumed, after varying periods of time, its forward march and penetrated regions thought to be forbidden to it. Once physics and chemistry were established, it was thought that science had to stop there. The biological world seemed to depend upon mysterious principles, which escaped the grasp of scientific thought. Yet biological sciences presently came into their own. Next, the founding of psychology demonstrated the applicability of reason to mental phenomena. Nothing, then, authorizes us to suppose that it is different with moral phenomena. Such an exception, which would be unique, is contrary to all reasonable inferences. There is no ineluctable reason for supposing that this last barrier, which people still try to oppose to the progress of reason, is more insurmountable than the others. The fact is, we are witnessing the establishing of a science that is still in its beginnings, but that undertakes to treat the phenomena of moral life as natural phenomena—in other words, as rational phenomena. Now, if morality is rational, if it sets in motion only ideas and sentiments deriving from reason, why should it be necessary to implant it in minds and characters by recourse to methods beyond the scope of reason?
Not only does a purely rational education seem logically possible; it seems to be determined by our entire historical development. If our education had suddenly taken on this character several years ago, one might well doubt whether so sudden a transformation were really implied in the nature of things. In reality, however, this transformation is the result of a gradual development, whose origins go back, so to speak, to the very beginnings of history. The secularizing of education has been in process for centuries.
It has been said that primitive peoples had no morality. That was an historical error. There is no people without its morality. However, the morality of undeveloped societies is not ours. What characterizes them is that they are essentially religious. By that, I mean that the most numerous and important duties are not the duties of man toward other men, but of man toward his gods. The principal obligations are not to respect one’s neighbor, to help him, to assist him; but to accomplish meticulously prescribed rites, to give to the Gods what is their due, and even, if need be, to sacrifice one’s self to their glory. Human morality in those circumstances is reduced to a small number of principles, whose violation is repressed less severely. These peoples are only on the threshold of morality. Even in Greece, murder occupied a much lower place in the scale of crimes than serious acts of impiety. Under these conditions, moral education could only be essentially religious, as was morality itself. Only religious notions could serve as the basis for an education that, before everything, had as its chief aim to teach man the manner in which he ought to behave toward religious beings.
But gradually things change. Gradually, human duties are multiplied, become more precise, and pass to the first rank of importance; while others, on the contrary, tend to become attenuated. One might say that Christianity itself has contributed most to the acceleration of this result. An essentially human religion since its God dies for the salvation of humanity, Christianity teaches that the principal duty of man toward God is to love his neighbor. Although there are religious duties—rites addressed only to divinity—the place they occupy and the importance attributed to them continue to diminish.
Essential sin is no longer detached from its human context. True sin now tends to merge with moral transgression. No doubt God continues to play an important part in morality. It is He who assures respect for it and represses its violation. Offenses against it are offenses against Him. But He is now reduced to the role of guardian. Moral discipline wasn’t instituted for his benefit, but for the benefit of men. He only intervenes to make it effective. Thenceforth our duties become independent, in large measure, of the religious notions that guarantee them but do not form their foundation.
With Protestantism, the autonomy of morality is still more accentuated by the fact that ritual itself diminishes. The moral functions of divinity become its sole raison d’être. It is the only argument brought forward to demonstrate its existence. Spiritualistic philosophy continues the work of Protestantism. But among the philosophers who believe today in the necessity of supernatural sanctions, there are none who do not admit that morality could be constructed quite independent of any theological conception. Thus, the bond that originally united and even merged the two systems has become looser and looser. It is, therefore, certain that when we broke that bond definitively we were following in the mainstream of history. If ever a revolution has been a long time in the making, this is it.
If the enterprise is possible and necessary, if sooner or later it had to be undertaken, and even if there were no reason to believe that it was long in the making, it still remains a difficult process. It is well to realize it, for only if we do not delude ourselves concerning these difficulties will it be possible to triumph over them. Gratified as we may be with what has been achieved, we ought to realize that advances would have been more pronounced and coherent had people not begun by believing that everything was going to be all too simple and easy. Above all, the task was conceived as a purely negative operation. It seemed that to secularize education all that was needed was to take out of it every supernatural element. A simple stripping operation was supposed to have the effect of disengaging rational morality from adventitious and parasitical elements that cloaked it and prevented it from realizing itself. It was enough, so they said, to teach the old morality of our fathers, while avoiding recourse to any religious notion. In reality, the task was much more complex. It was not enough to proceed by simple elimination to reach the proposed goal. On the contrary, a profound transformation was necessary.
Of course, if religious symbols were simply overlaid upon moral reality, there would indeed be nothing to do but lift them off, thus finding in a state of purity and isolation a self-sufficient rational morality. But the fact is that these two systems of beliefs and practices have been too inextricably bound together in history; for centuries they have been too interlaced for their connections possibly to be so external and superficial and for the separation to be so easily consummated. We must not forget that only yesterday they were supported on the same keystone: God, the center of religious life, was also the supreme guarantor of moral order. There is nothing surprising in this partial coalescence; the duties of religion and those of morality are both duties, in other words, morally obligatory practices. It is altogether natural that men were induced to see in one and the same being the source of all obligation. One can easily foresee, by reason of this relationship and partial fusion, that some elements of both systems approached each other to the point of merging and forming only one system. Certain moral ideas became united with certain religious ideas to such an extent as to become indistinct from them. The first ended by no longer having or seeming to have any existence or any reality independent of the second. Consequently, if, in rationalizing morality in moral education, one confines himself to withdraw from moral discipline everything that is religious without replacing it, one almost inevitably runs the danger of withdrawing at the same time all elements that are properly moral. Under the name of rational morality, we would be left only with an impoverished and colorless morality. To ward off this danger, therefore, it is imperative not to be satisfied with a superficial separation. We must seek, in the very heart of religious conceptions, those moral realities that are, as it were, lost and dissimulated in it. We must disengage them, find out what they consist of, determine their proper nature, and express them in rational language. In a word, we must discover the rational substitutes for those religious notions that for a long time have served as the vehicle for the most essential moral ideas.
An example will illustrate precisely what I mean: Even without pushing the analysis, everybody readily perceives that in one sense, a very relative sense as a matter of fact, the moral order constitues a sort of autonomous order in the world. There is something about prescriptions of morality that imposes particular respect for them. While all opinions relating to the material world—to the physical or mental organization of either animals or men—are today entitled to free discussion, people do not admit that moral beliefs should be as freely subjected to criticism. Anybody who questions in our presence that the child has duties toward his parents or that human life should be respected provokes us to immediate protest. The response is quite different from that which a scientific heresy might arouse. It resembles at every point the reprobation that the blasphemer arouses in the soul of the believer. There is even stronger reason for the feelings incited by infractions of moral rules being altogether different from those provoked by ordinary infractions of the precepts of practical wisdom or of professional technique. The domain of morality is as if surrounded by a mysterious barrier which keeps violators at arm’s length, just as the religious domain is protected from the reach of the profane. It is a sacred domain. All the things it comprises are as if invested with a particular dignity that raises them above our empirical individuality, and that confers upon them a sort of transcendant reality. Don’t we say, casually, that the human person is sacred, that we must hold it in reverence? As long as religion and morals are intimately united, this sacred character can be explained without difficulty since, in that case, morality as well as religion is conceived as an attribute and emanation of divinity, the source of all that is sacred. Everything coming from it participates in its transcendance and finds itself by that very fact implicated in other things. But if we methodically reject the notion of the sacred without systematically replacing it by another, the quasi-religious character of morality is without foundation, (since we are rejecting the traditional conception that provided that foundation without providing another). One is, then, almost inevitably inclined to deny morality. It is even impossible to feel the reality of it, when, as a matter of fact, it could very well be that it is founded in the nature of things.
It may very well be that there is in moral rules something that deserves to be called by this name and that nevertheless could be justified and explained logically without implying the existence of a transcendant being or specifically religious notions. If the eminent dignity attributed to moral rules has, up to the present time, only been expressed in the form of religious conceptions, it does not follow that it cannot be otherwise expressed; consequently, one must be careful that this dignity does not sink with the ideas conventionally associated with it. From the fact that nations, to explain it to themselves, have made of it a radiation and a reflection of divinity, it does not follow that it cannot be attached to another reality, to a purely empirical reality through which it is explained, and of which the idea of God is indeed perhaps only the symbolic expression. If, then, in rationalizing education, we do not retain this character and make it clear to the child in a rational manner, we will only transmit to him a morality fallen from its natural dignity. At the same time, we will risk drying up the source from which the schoolmaster himself drew a part of his authority and also a part of the warmth necessary to stir the heart and stimulate the mind. The schoolmaster, feeling that he was speaking in the name of a superior reality elevated himself, invested himself with an extra energy. If we do not succeed in preserving this sense of self and mission for him—while providing, meanwhile, a different foundation for it—we risk having nothing more than a moral education without prestige and without life.
Here is a first body of eminently complex and positive problems that compel our attention when we undertake to secularize moral education. It is not enough to cut out; we must replace. We must discover those moral forces that men, down to the present time, have conceived of only under the form of religious allegories. We must disengage them from their symbols, present them in their rational nakedness, so to speak, and find a way to make the child feel their reality without recourse to any mythological intermediary. This is the first order of business: we want moral education to become rational and at the same time to produce all the results that should be expected from it.
These questions are not the only ones we face here. Not only must we see to it that morality, as it becomes rationalized, loses none of its basic elements; but it must; through the very fact of secularization, become enriched with new elements. The first transformation of which I have just spoken bore only on the form of our moral ideas. The foundation itself cannot stand without profound modifications. The causes requiring the institution of a...

Table of contents

  1. DOVER BOOKS ON BIOLOGY, PSYCHOLOGY AND MEDICINE
  2. Title Page
  3. Copyright Page
  4. FOREWORD
  5. PREFACE
  6. Table of Contents
  7. CHAPTER ONE - INTRODUCTION: SECULAR MORALITY
  8. PART I - The Elements of Morality
  9. PART II - How to Develop the Elements of Morality in the Child
  10. INDEX
  11. A CATALOG OF SELECTED DOVER BOOKS IN ALL FIELDS OF INTEREST