A Companion to Rorty
eBook - ePub

A Companion to Rorty

  1. English
  2. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  3. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

A Companion to Rorty

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

A groundbreaking reference work on the revolutionary philosophy and intellectual legacy of Richard Rorty

A provocative and often controversial thinker, Richard Rorty and his ideas have been the subject of renewed interest to philosophers working in epistemology, metaphysics, analytic philosophy, and the history of philosophy. Having called for philosophers to abandonrepresentationalist accounts of knowledge and language, Rorty introduced radical and challenging concepts to modern philosophy, generating divisive debate through the new form of American pragmatism which he advocated and the renunciation of traditional epistemology which he espoused.

However, while Rorty has been one of the most widely-discussed figures in modern philosophy, few volumes have dealt directly with the expansive reach of his thought or its implications for the fields of philosophy in which he worked. The Blackwell Companion to Rorty is a collection of essays by prominent scholars which provide close, and long-overdue, examination of Rorty's groundbreaking work. Divided into five parts, this volumecovers the major intellectual movements of Rorty's career from his early work on consciousness and transcendental arguments, to the lasting impacts of his major writings, to his approach to pragmatism and his controversial appropriations from other philosophers, and finally to his later work in culture, politics, and ethics.

  • Offers a comprehensive, balanced, and insightful account of Rorty's approach to philosophy
  • Provides an assessment of Rorty's more controversial thoughts and his standing as an "anti-philosopher's philosopher"
  • Contains new and original exploration of Rorty's thinking from leading scholars and philosophers
  • Includes new perspectives on topics such as Rorty's influence in Central Europe

Despite the relevance of Rorty's work for the wider community of philosophers and for those working in fields such as international relations, legal and political theory, sociology, and feminist studies, the secondary literature surrounding Rorty's work and legacy is limited. A Companion to Rorty address this absence, providinga comprehensive resource for philosophers and general readers.

Frequently asked questions

Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Yes, you can access A Companion to Rorty by Alan Malachowski, Alan Malachowski in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Philosophy & Philosophy History & Theory. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Year
2020
ISBN
9781118972182

Part I
Early Developments

2
Was Rorty an Eliminative Materialist?

WILLIAM RAMSEY

1 Introduction

Richard Rorty is widely regarded as one of the early developers and proponents of a version of materialism known today as eliminative materialism. This characterization is based primarily on papers wrote in the mid‐1960s, especially his “Mind–Body Identity, Privacy and Categories” (Rorty 1965, from hereon MBIPC). While in his later work, Rorty arguably abandons the view suggested in these papers by rejecting the metaphysical and linguistic assumptions they demand, nearly all commentators treat the earlier Rorty as having helped define and establish the radical thesis that the posits of commonsense psychology, especially sensations like pain, do not actually exist.
I am going to argue here that on a closer reading of MBIPC, this interpretation of Rorty as a proponent of eliminative materialism is actually a mistake. Others have noted inconsistencies and difficulties in Rorty’s position. But here I will argue that the most plausible interpretation of Rorty’s account of mental states is one in which he rejects several central features of contemporary eliminativism. As other writers have suggested, such as Bush (1974), I believe Rorty should instead be viewed as a more conventional sort of materialist who makes a misguided claim about what mind–brain identity entails. While Rorty argues for the eliminability of terms used to pick out mental states, he does not base this claim about language on a clear commitment to the nonexistence of the states or properties that those terms denote. In the end, while his writing lends itself to different interpretations, I believe Rorty should be seen as simply a good‐old‐fashioned reductionist/identity theorist.
To show this, this chapter will have the following organization. First, I am going to spell out eliminative materialism as it is commonly understood today, highlighting key elements that are relevant to the question of whether or not Rorty was himself an eliminativist. Then, I will spend some time going over the claims and arguments that Rorty makes in MBIPC in an effort to capture his picture of the nature of mental states. I will then elaborate on the mismatch between modern eliminativism and Rorty’s account, and argue that Rorty is best viewed not as an eliminative materialist, but rather as a proponent of the very different view that mental states should be regarded as identical (in some sense) to brain states. I will also contrast my interpretation with the interpretations offered by others, in particular, Lycan and Pappas (1972) and Bush (1974), and explain why I think my interpretation is better.

2 Contemporary Eliminative Materialism

Generally, eliminativism about something is the thesis that the targeted entity, process, event, property, or whatever else assumed (at some time) to exist actually does not exist. Thus, we are all eliminativists about some things – ghosts, demons, the crystal spheres that were thought to hold the stars in their fixed position. Eliminativism is thus a form of antirealism regarding something once assumed by some to be real. The term is misleading as the allegedly nonexistent item is not actually eliminated (it can’t be eliminated, since it doesn’t exist). What is proposed is the elimination of the reliance on, or perhaps the positing of or explanatory appeal to, the corresponding notion or concept. So while no one has eliminated demons, as such, we (or most of us) have eliminated the practice of invoking our concept of demons to explain various phenomena. We have eliminated demons from our understanding of the furniture of the world.
Modern eliminative materialism is a form of eliminativism with regard to certain mental states or processes. Thus, modern eliminative materialists typically claim that specific sorts of mental states or mental processes do not actually exist. In recent years, the most popular target of eliminativist writings have been intentional states and, in particular, propositional attitudes, such as beliefs and desires. Thus, eliminative materialists like Paul M. Churchland (1981, 1993) and Patricia Churchland (1986) have claimed that there are no such things as beliefs, in the same sense in which there are no such things as demons. But there have also been those who have endorsed an eliminativistic outlook toward phenomenal states like pain (Dennett 1978; Hardcastle 1999), consciousness (Rey 1983), concepts (Machery 2009), and a variety of other mental states, capacities, and processes.
Most contemporary arguments for various sorts of eliminative materialism typically involve two major steps. The first step involves establishing a set of central properties that the relevant mental state or kind is assumed to possess. Often this is done by claiming that our understanding of that mental state is based on some broader theoretical framework, like our commonsense or “folk” psychology (Churchland 1981). In other words, our conception of the mental state in question is claimed to be rooted in a theory that is used to explain and predict behavior; as an explanatory posit, the state in question is assigned a set of defining characteristics, such as various causal properties. The second step involves arguing that such a thing cannot be identified with – at any level of analysis – anything in our most advanced scientific account of the brain, either now or down the road. Thus, eliminative materialists share with dualists a sort of antireductionist outlook. They agree that a given mental state cannot be identified with anything going on in the brain. Dualists say this is so because mental states exist as nonphysical states, whereas eliminative materialists say this is so because the mental states do not actually exist.
Some further clarification is needed to understand each of these steps. Regarding the first step, a great deal of discussion has been devoted to the question of whether or not our invoking of commonsense mental notions like “belief” or “pain” is the expression or application of some broader theoretical framework. Proponents of the so‐called “theory‐theory” claim that commonsense psychology is a predictive and explanatory theory, albeit a nonscientific one, that we learn while growing up. Many philosophers (and some psychologists) reject the theory‐theory, and claim instead that we make sense of one another through some other process, like simulating their decision making using our own decision‐making machinery (Goldman 2008). However, strictly speaking, eliminative materialism does not really require that our commonsense mental notions are embedded in a theoretical framework used for explaining and predicting. Just about any sort of embedding conceptual framework can be used to support an eliminativistic outlook. In fact, although it is seldom appreciated, the only thing eliminative materialism actually requires is the boring assumption that we have mental concepts (that is, concepts of mental states and processes) and that those concepts assign certain properties to those mental states and processes. That is an extremely weak thesis. Even the most ardent opponent of the theory‐theory will typically grant that we possess concepts about mental states like beliefs and pains, and that those concepts (at least tacitly) assign to their corresponding mental entities a variety of intrinsic, intentional, phenomenal, causal, temporal, and other properties. To deny this would be to deny that we possess distinct concepts of mental states.
Regarding the second step, the immediate and crucial question that comes up is this: Just how mistaken does a given conception of something need to be for us to properly say that it turns out there is no such thing? Because so many eliminative materialists regard our mental notions as part of a folk theoretical framework, this question is often framed as this: Just how wrong does folk psychology need to be for its theoretical posits to fail to correspond with anything that exists? Obviously, wrongness of the theory alone is insufficient for claims of nonexistence. We have been initially wrong about many things invoked by both commonsense frameworks (stars, light, fire) and scientific theories (planets, genes, atoms), and yet we nevertheless regard these things as real, but just different than we initially thought. In response to Rorty’s MBIPC, Steven Savitt (1974) described the relevant difference as one between ontologically conservative (retentive) and ontologically radical (eliminativistic) theory change. But beyond making this helpful distinction, Savitt did not go far in explaining what motivates it. So why do we revise and retain (reduce) ontological posits of some frameworks and abandon the ontological posits of others?
As it turns out, this is not an easy question to answer. There are no clear, fixed, and acknowledged sets of criteria that tell us how much (or what sort of) mismatch is needed between a given concept and the world to motivate and justify a change that is ontologically radical. A survey of the history of science seems to reveal a hodgepodge of different factors influencing different cases. Still, as Savitt notes, one plausible thing we can say is that in many clear cases of retention, the mismatch was relatively minor, whereas in most cases of elimination, the mismatch was quite substantial. For instance, while we were wrong to think that planets orbit the Earth as Ptolemy claimed, we were right that there are spherical bodies in solar systems that orbit so...

Table of contents

  1. Cover
  2. Table of Contents
  3. Blackwell Companions to Philosophy
  4. Preface and Acknowledgments
  5. Contributors
  6. Introduction
  7. Prologue
  8. Part I: Early Developments
  9. Part II: Texts
  10. Part III: Themes
  11. Part IV: Appropriations
  12. Part V: Culture, Politics, and Religion
  13. Part VI: Coda
  14. Internet Resources
  15. Index
  16. End User License Agreement