On Tolerance
eBook - ePub

On Tolerance

A Defence of Moral Independence

  1. 224 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

On Tolerance

A Defence of Moral Independence

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

Outwardly, we live in an era that appears more open-minded, non-judgemental and tolerant than in any time in human history. The very term intolerant invokes moral condemnation. We are constantly reminded to understand the importance of respecting different cultures and diversities. In this pugnacious new book, Frank Furedi argues that despite the democratisation of public life and the expansion of freedom, society is dominated by a culture that not only tolerates but often encourages intolerance. Often the intolerance is directed at people who refuse to accept the conventional wisdom and who are stigmatised as 'deniers'. Frequently intolerance comes into its own in clashes over cultural values and lifestyles. People are condemned for the food they eat, how they parent and for wearing religious symbols in public. This book challenges the 'quiet mood of tolerance' towards morally stigmatised forms of behaviour. The author examines recent forms of 'unacceptable behaviour'. It will tease out the real motives and drivers of intolerance.

Frequently asked questions

Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Yes, you can access On Tolerance by Frank Furedi in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Philosophy & Political Philosophy. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Year
2013
ISBN
9781441119407

1
Introduction: Clarifying the Issues

The idea of tolerance has been subject to significant conceptual confusions. Tolerance is often represented as a form of non-judgemental acceptance of other people’s beliefs; yet, to tolerate a disagreeable opinion requires a prior act of judgement. In a world where acceptance of difference is represented as mandatory, the classical idea of tolerance has become problematic. It has either been rejected as far too negative or reinterpreted as a gesture of non-judgemental respect. Through examining the current reaction to tolerance, this introduction sets the scene for a review of its historical evolution.
Controversies over ‘gays in the military’, the wearing of the burka or the crucifix, or even whether it should be permissible to make offensive comments about someone’s culture, indicate that twenty-first-century Western society has an uneasy relationship with the idea and practice of tolerance. As I write I receive a press release from a British think tank announcing that ‘wearing the veil is a civil right’ and insisting that ‘British tolerance’ means recognizing ‘freedom of religious expression’. In America, too, the age-old question of religious tolerance is the subject of debate. On the eve of 11 September 2010, President Barack Obama felt it necessary to remind the public of the necessity for religious tolerance, after a Florida-based Christian clergyman threatened to burn the Koran in protest against plans to build an Islamic centre two blocks from the site where the World Trade Center stood before its destruction. Some claim that tolerance has gone ‘too far’, and blame the culture of permissiveness in Western societies for a bewildering variety of social and moral problems, from pornography to the disintegration of the traditional family.
This book argues that, despite its frequent rhetorical use, twenty-first-century society does not take the classical liberal ideal of tolerance very seriously. Even its advocates practise their tolerance selectively, often legitimizing attitudes and behaviour that are censorious and unforgiving towards beliefs and views that challenge their assumptions. Matters are made worse by the confusions that surround the meaning of ‘tolerance’: the term finds itself used in ways that would shock the philosophers and thinkers who developed this concept. Here, we aim to clarify and elaborate the meaning of tolerance for the current era.
Tolerance is an important ideal that is indispensable for the working of a genuinely free and democratic society. Yet it is an ideal that we take for granted. Numerous articles and books on the subject treat it as a rather insignificant idea that doesn’t go far enough to secure a just society. Others depict tolerance as a disinclination to judge or to have strong views about the behaviour of others, or deploy ‘tolerance’ as a synonym for ‘permissive’. Increasingly, we are in danger of forgetting that tolerance is an intimate companion of liberty and freedom, and that it constitutes one of the most precious contributions of the Enlightenment imagination to modern life. Without tolerance we cannot be free, we cannot live with one another in relative peace, we cannot follow and act on our conscience, we cannot exercise our moral autonomy nor pursue our own road towards seeking the truth.
In historical terms, tolerance is a very recent cultural and moral ideal. Until the seventeenth century the toleration of different religions, opinions and beliefs was interpreted as a form of moral cowardice, if not a symptom of heresy. Indeed medieval witch-hunters and inquisitors were no less concerned with stigmatizing those who questioned their intolerant practices than they were with hunting down witches and heretics. The fifteenth-century witch-hunters’ manual Malleus Maleficarum claimed that those who denied the existence of witches or questioned the methods of the inquisitors were as guilty of heresy as the active practitioners of witchcraft. In the following century, scepticism was frequently treated as a particularly dangerous form of anti-Christian heresy. As the French historian Paul Hazard notes in his pioneering study The European Mind, until the seventeenth century tolerance ‘had not been a virtue at all, but, on the contrary, a sign of weakness, not to say cowardice’, and ‘duty and charity’ forbade people to be tolerant.1 As late as 1691, the French theologian Jacques-Bénigne Bossuet boasted that Catholicism was the least tolerant of all religions, stating that ‘I have the right to persecute you because I am right and you are wrong’.2 Protestant religious figures more than matched Bossuet’s intolerance. Indeed the Walloon synod of Leyden, mainly composed of Huguenot refugees, condemned religious toleration as a form of heresy.3
It was in the seventeenth century that attitudes towards tolerating competing ideas and religions began to change. In part the rise of secularism and rationality encouraged a more sceptical orientation towards religious dogmatism and intolerance. Although there are some historical exceptions, people are far less likely to impose their beliefs on others when they are not absolutely certain of their convictions. This was also a period when Europe was overwhelmed by bitter religious conflicts that frequently resulted in bloody civil wars. In such circumstances, calls for tolerance were influenced by the pragmatic calculation that without a measure of religious toleration, endemic violence and bloodshed could not be avoided. This was the moment when a significant minority of Europeans recognized that tolerance was a prerequisite for their society’s survival. The American philosopher Michael Walzer emphasizes the significance of this insight when he states that toleration ‘sustains life itself’: we need to remind ourselves that ‘toleration makes difference possible; difference makes toleration necessary’.4 From this perspective toleration is not only a moral or philosophical principle, but also a matter of pragmatic necessity. It is precisely because many differences cannot be resolved philosophically that tolerance becomes the only alternative to conflict and violence.
The aim of seventeenth-century advocates of tolerance, including John Locke, was to protect religious belief from state coercion. Locke’s advocacy of toleration represented a call for restraining political authorities from interfering with the workings of individual conscience and lifestyles. Over the centuries this affirmation of religious tolerance has expanded to allow the free expression of opinions, beliefs and behaviour associated with the exercise of the individual conscience. Tolerance is intimately connected to the assertion of this most basic dimension of freedom, and demands that we accept the right of people to live according to beliefs and opinions that are different, sometimes antithetical, to ours. Tolerance does not invite us to accept or celebrate other people’s sentiments, but requires that we live with them and desist from interfering or forcing others to fall in line with our own views. As Murphy writes, ‘neither conceptually nor historically is toleration affiliated with approval of diversity or with intellectual, religious, or moral pluralism per se’.5
In this book the concept of tolerance is used in two senses. It pertains to the domain of the political/philosophical through its avowal of the principle of non-interference towards the way that people develop and hold beliefs and opinions. Tolerance affirms the freedom of conscience and individual autonomy. As long as an act does not violate a person’s moral autonomy and harm others, tolerance also calls for the absence of constraint on behaviour linked to the exercise of individual autonomy. From this perspective, tolerance can be measured in relation to the extent to which people’s belief and behaviour is not subject to institutional and political interference and restraint. Second, tolerance is a social/cultural accomplishment, and a tolerant society is one where the cultural orientation discourages and restrains social intolerance. This was a concern eloquently pursued by the philosopher J. S. Mill, who warned about the ‘tyranny’ of public opinion and its tendency to stigmatize and silence minority and dissident beliefs. Upholding the disposition to be tolerant is always a challenge, and experience shows that legal safeguards can always come unstuck when confronted by a tidal wave of social intolerance.

What tolerance is not

Anyone perusing policy documents, mission statements, school textbooks and speeches made by politicians and policymakers is likely to be struck by the frequency with which the term ‘tolerance’ is celebrated. It is difficult to encounter any significant acclaim for intolerance. However, on closer inspection it becomes evident that the meaning of this term has radically altered, mutating into a superficial signifier of acceptance and affirmation. In official documents and school texts, tolerance is used as a desirable character trait rather than as a way of managing conflicting beliefs and behaviour. So one can be tolerant without any reference to a set of beliefs or opinions. Moreover, the idea that tolerance means not interfering with, or attempting to suppress, beliefs that contradict one’s own sentiments has given way to the idea that tolerance involves not judging other people and their views. Instead of serving as a way of responding to differences of views, tolerance has become a way of not taking them seriously.
When tolerance is represented as a form of detached indifference or as a polite gesture connoting mechanical acceptance, it becomes a vice rather than a virtue. One reason why tolerance was historically interpreted as a virtue was because it implied a willingness to tolerate disagreeable beliefs and opinions. According to the classical liberal outlook, it involved an act of judgement and discrimination; but judgement did not serve as a prelude to censoring another person’s wrong views, because tolerance demands respect for people’s right to hold beliefs in accordance with their conscience. Indeed, the recognition of the primacy of freedom imposed on the truly tolerant the responsibility to refrain from attempting to coerce religious and political opponents into silence. Voltaire’s frequently repeated statement, ‘I disapprove of what you say, but I will defend to the death your right to say it’, expressed the intimate connection between judgement/disapproval and a commitment to freedom. The capacity to tolerate views of which one disapproves is underpinned by the conviction that this virtue provides an opportunity for testing out ideas and confronting ethical dilemmas. Interference with individual belief and opinion disrupts the creative dynamic of intellectual and moral development of society. From this standpoint, tolerance of disapproved-of beliefs is a very small price to pay for society’s intellectual and moral development.
In contemporary public discussion, the connection between tolerance and judgement is in danger of being lost. Our analysis of the current usage of the word ‘tolerant’ indicates that it is frequently used as a companion term with ‘inclusive’ and ‘non-judgemental’. As a fascinating survey of American political culture concludes, ‘Thou shalt not judge’ has become the eleventh commandment of middle-class Americans. Alan Wolfe, the study’s author, notes that ‘middle-class Americans are reluctant to pass judgement on how other people act and think’.6 While the reluctance to judge other people’s behaviour has its attractive qualities, it is not necessarily a manifestation of social tolerance. All too often this attitude is synonymous with not caring about the fate of others. Yet the precondition for the working of a democratic public sphere is openness to conversation and debate. Reflecting on our differences with others’ points of view, letting them know where we stand and what we find disagreeable in their opinions, is the very stuff of a vibrant democracy. Without it tolerance turns into shallow indifference, an excuse for switching off when others talk.
The confusion of the concept of tolerance with the idea of acceptance and valuation of other people’s beliefs and lifestyles is strikingly illustrated by the United Nations Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organization (UNESCO) Declaration on the Principles of Tolerance, which frames the term thus: ‘tolerance is respect, acceptance and appreciation of the rich diversity of our world’s cultures, our forms of expression and ways of being human’ and it is ‘harmony in difference’.7 For UNESCO toleration becomes an expansive and diffuse sensibility that automatically accepts and offers unconditional appreciation of different views and cultures. This officially sanctioned declaratory rhetoric of tolerance is often used in schools, and children interpret it as an exhortation to be nice to other people. Children are taught that a nice person is a tolerant one, and tolerance is diagnosed as a psychological trait – a variant of other fashionable pedagogic values such as empathy, self-esteem, or valuing yourself.
The reinterpretation of tolerance as a psychological attitude that conveys acceptance, empathy and respect means that in public deliberations it has lost its real meaning. Yet it is precisely the intimate connection between disapproval/disagreement and toleration that endows tolerance with the potential to enhance the quality of public life. The act of toleration demands reflection, restraint and a respect for the right of other people to find their way to their truth. Once tolerance signifies a form of automatic acceptance, it becomes a performance in expected behaviour. As David Heyd writes, the shift in meaning, ‘which rests on easy acceptance of the heterogeneity of values and ways of life’, pushes ‘the concept of tolerance dangerously close to that of indifference’. The ‘scope of indifference is growing in the field of value judgments, and … liberalism today means less the toleration of other ways of life than the cool acceptance of the very plurality and heterogeneity of lifestyles’.8 So inadvertently well-meaning exhortations to tolerate discourage people from developing their moral capacity to understand, judge and discrimin...

Table of contents

  1. Cover
  2. Title Page
  3. Contents
  4. Preface
  5. 1 Introduction: Clarifying the Issues
  6. 2 Tolerance as a Precious Resource
  7. 3 The Fossilization of Identity
  8. 4 Tolerance Confused with Recognition
  9. 5 The Expansion of the Meaning of Harm
  10. 6 The Loss of Respect for Moral Independence
  11. 7 The Cultivation of Intolerant Identities and the Infantilizing of Offence
  12. 8 Twenty-First-Century Heresy
  13. 9 Conclusion: Why Tolerance Matters
  14. Bibliography
  15. eCopyright