Retribution
eBook - ePub

Retribution

  1. 452 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub
Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

Retribution is perhaps the most popular contemporary theory about punishment and has enjoyed enduring appeal as the oldest, even most venerable, penal theory with its strong ancient roots. Retribution is understood in many different ways, but the standard view of retribution is that punishment is justified where it is deserved and an offender should be punished in proportion to his desert. In this volume, retributivism is examined from various critical perspectives, including its diversity, relation with desert, the link between desert and proportionality, retributivist emotions and the idea of mercy. The theory of retribution has been the subject of a revival of interest in recent years and the essays selected for this volume are the leading works on retribution from the dominant international figures in the field.

Frequently asked questions

Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on ā€œCancel Subscriptionā€ - itā€™s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time youā€™ve paid for. Learn more here.
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlegoā€™s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan youā€™ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, weā€™ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Yes, you can access Retribution by Thom Brooks, Thom Brooks in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Law & Jurisprudence. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Publisher
Routledge
Year
2019
ISBN
9781351903493
Edition
1
Topic
Law
Index
Law

Part I

Retributions

[1]

VARIETIES OF RETRIBUTION

BY JOHN COTTINGHAM

One of the functions of philosophy is to combat ambiguity and muddle. Yet in discussions of the justification of punishment, philosophers persist in talking of ā€˜retributionā€™ and ā€˜retributive theoryā€™ as if these labels stood for something relatively simple and straightforward. The fact is that the term ā€˜retributiveā€™ as used in philosophy has become so imprecise and multivocal that it is doubtful whether it any longer serves a useful purpose. In this paper I shall attempt to separate out no less than nine distinct approaches to punishmentā€”I shall call them ā€œtheoriesā€, but the term will be qualified laterā€”which are or have been labelled retributive. The first object of the exercise will be clarification for its own sake; but along the way I shall allow myself some brief observations on the logical adequacy of various strategies for justifying punishment.

(1) REPAYMENT THEORY

Most dictionaries give the first meaning of ā€˜retributionā€™ as repayment. The etymology of the term is clear: re+tribuo, Latin, to pay back. I am inclined to suggest that this notion encapsulates the basic or fundamental sense of ā€˜retributionā€™. Etymology, of course, is no arbiter in philosophy. But there is a perfectly ordinary (pre-philosophical) way of talking about punishment which exactly fits this original sense of ā€˜retributionā€™. Newspapers and public speakers often hold forth about the need for the criminal to repay his debt to society. And the argot of criminals (or at least the criminal of fiction) is full of expressions like ā€˜Iā€™ve paid the priceā€™:
Iā€™m going straight, I am, straight as an arrer,
Iā€™ve paid the price and done me time;
Iā€™m going straight, and I donā€™t mean the straight and narrer,
ā€™Cos Iā€™m going straight back to crime!
On our standard theory of retribution, then, punishment is inflicted in order to make the offender pay for his offence. Exactly how or why suffering something unpleasant (e.g., ā€œdoing timeā€ for six months) should count as payment for an offence is left unexplained; but it has to be admitted that the notion is both ancient and widely held. In the Pauline doctrine of the atonement, the passion (suffering) of Christ is supposed to ā€œpay forā€ the offences of mankind. (Note: this is merely an example of the belief that suffering pays for wrong; I do not mean to suggest that the repayment version of retributivism is really an atonement theory. There could not be an atonement theory of punishment; atonement is something voluntarily undertaken, punishment something exacted.)

(2) DESERT THEORY

A recent textbook defines ā€˜retributive punishmentā€™ as ā€˜punishment meted out because it is deservedā€™.1 Similarly, Ted Honderich in his book Punishment asserts quite bluntly that to give as a reason for the rightness of punishment that it is deserved by offenders is retributivism.2 Unlike our first theory, which is grounded in the original meaning of ā€˜retributionā€™, these accounts are initially puzzling. No doubt it may be true that many who call themselves retributivists have held that desert is a sufficient condition for just punishment; but to say, tout court, that this is what makes them retributivists leaves the rationale for the label compressed to the point of unintelligibility. Suppose I say: ā€œIā€™m a retributivist: I believe that where punishment is deserved this is sufficient to justify itā€. I think the initial reaction of that ubiquitous figure the ā€œintelligent laymanā€ would be: ā€œWell, go on, explain! Where does the retribution come in?ā€. To put the point more precisely, if someone claims that a sufficient condition for the justification of university scholarships is that they are deserved, does this mean that he has a retributive theory of scholarship-awarding? Perhaps it does; but only in a rather old-fashioned sense of the term ā€˜retributionā€™, meaning any kind of reward or recompense (ā€œnever did a charitable act go away without the retribution of a blessingā€3). If we are allowed to unpack and amplify the desert theory in this way, the claim becomes that punishment is justified because it is a deserved requital or reward for wrong-doing. Viewed as an exercise in justification, this account shares the curiously jejune quality of theory (1); and its detractors have made the complaintā€”not without forceā€”that it reduces to the bald assertion that it is simply just that the offender should be punished.
Is there a logical connection between the desert account (2), and our basic account (1)? Thesis (2) is certainly compatible withā€”perhaps even entailed byā€”thesis (1). For it may be that to claim that punishment is a just retribution (repayment) implies that the offender deserves to pay. The converse entailment, however, does not seem to hold. For it seems that one could be a ā€œretributivistā€ in the unexpanded Honderichian sense (punishment is justified because deserved) without subscribing to the idea that punishment is some kind of repayment of a debt. This alone is enough to warrant keeping theories (1) and (2) distinct.

(3) PENALTY THEORY

Kant, universally regarded as a retributivist, asserts that the reason why punishment is imposed must always be because the individual on whom it is inflicted has committed a crime.4 A possible, though unlikely, interpretation of this remark is that the breaking of a law is, in itself, a sufficient condition for just punishment. This latter proposition was put forward, half a century ago, in a highly influential paper by John Mabbott. In connection with his own experiences in dealing with defaulters who had broken college rules, Mabbott wrote: ā€œthey had broken a rule and they knew it and I knew it; nothing more was necessary to make punishment properā€.5 Mabbottā€™s theory seems to construe punishment as a kind of automatic penalty, whose appropriateness is ensured simply by the knowing commission of an offence.
It is not clear that this theory, as it stands, will serve as an account of the justification of punishment (and the author later made substantial modifications in his position to deal with this point). However, Mabbottā€™s original unmodified theory deserves inclusion in our list for historical reasons. Many of those influenced by Mabbott took him to be putting forward not a moral thesis but a logical one. They took him to be claiming, as a necessary truth, that there is an essential ā€œretrospectiveā€ feature to punishment; punishment, that is, must logically look backward to the past commission of an offence.6 Because Mabbott adopted the label ā€˜retributiveā€™ to describe his theory (though he warned that he was not an ā€œorthodox retributivistā€), subsequent writers who wished to support this logical thesis tended to characterize their position asā€”at least partlyā€”retributivist. To be aware of this background is a vital prerequisite for following the argument of section (4) below.
Whatever the truth of the purely logical claim that proper punishment must necessarily involve reference to a past offence, it seems both arbitrary and inappropriate to signal this claim by using the label ā€˜retributiveā€™. There are many terms in the language of obligation whose correct understanding involves a necessary reference to a past act. ā€˜Promiseā€™ is one of them. To understand why promises should be kept, it is, it seems to me, crucial to understand thatā€”whatever the future benefits of keeping promises may beā€”the obligatoriness relates to a past act: the giving of a promise. But in saying this have I advanced a ā€œretributive theory of promisingā€? Hardly! A retrospective or backward-looking element in a theory is never normally characterized as ā€œretributiveā€; it is only in the literature on punishment that these two notions are muddled (so that, in some discussions, ā€˜retributiveā€™ becomes virtually an antonym of ā€˜teleologicalā€™).

(4) MINIMALISM

ā€œMost contemporary retributivistsā€, asserts Martin Golding in his book Philosophy of Law, ā€œmaintain a minimalist position. This holds that no one should be punished unless he is guilty of a crime and culpableā€.7 Similarly, Anthony Quinton claims ā€œthe fundamental thesis [of retributivists] must be that only the guilty are to be punishedā€.8 Thesis (4), then, asserts that guilt is a necessary condition of just punishment.
As with our definition (2), some initial puzzlement is in order here. What on earth is supposed to be distinctly retributivist about thesis (4)? The most likely explanation for the classification of (4) as a kind of retributivism seems to be the historical one sketched in the previous section: even though Mabbottā€™s thesis was principally about the logically sufficient, as opposed to necessary, conditions for just punishment, his adoption of the label ā€˜retributivistā€™ paved the way for any theory asserting a logical connection between proper punishment and past offence to be classified as retributivist.
But whatever its historical genesis, the labelling of thesis (4) as a kind of retributive theory has sowed nothing but confusion. For it is clearly possible to hold thesis (4) as a principle of natural justice, or as a utilitarian secondary rule, without having any truck with the notion of retribution in the standard senses outlined under (1) and (2) above. A good example of the awkwardness that can arise in this connection is an otherwise exemplarily clear paper by H. L. A. Hart. Hart mounts a staunch and well constructed defence of thesis (4), but then proceeds to insist on labelling it the principle of ā€œretribution-in-distributionā€. This in spite of the fact that the route taken by Hart to defend (4) has, as he himself admits, nothing to do with retribution in its ordinary sense, but is concerned instead with principles of simple justice, and in particular the need to guarantee ā€œa method of social control which maximizes individual freedomā€.9
A further unfortunate consequence of calling thesis (4) ā€œretributivistā€, or mislabelling it the principle of ā€œretribution-in-distributionā€, has been the widespread view (hinted at by Hart) that some kind of compromise is possible between utilitarian and retributive accounts of punishment. The supposed compromise runs: utilitarian considerations provide the answer to the general question ā€˜why punish at all?ā€™, while ā€˜retributionā€™ provides the answer to the more specific question ā€˜whom shall we punish?ā€™ (answer: ā€˜only the guiltyā€™).10 To put the matter this way can be highly misleading, since, once again, if thesis (4) is held as a utilitarian secondary rule or as a liberty-maximizing principle, then of course no concession at all has necessarily been made to the strict notion of retributionā€”i.e., to the notion that punishment is due as repayment for a crime.

(5) SATISFACTION THEORY

ā€œA man is rightly punished because his punishment brings satisfaction to others.ā€ This thesis, which I label the satisfaction theory, has been described as a view which ā€œhas given force to retributivismā€.11 The idea behind the claim seems to be that there should be some kind of reciprocity between the sense of grievance felt by the victim of an offence and the satisfaction he gets from the suffering of the offender. What connection, if any, does this theory have with our ā€œbasicā€ sense of retribution? The answer, I think, hinges on which of two possible interpretations is given to the theory.
(5a) On the first interpretation, the claim put forward is that it is intrinsically desirable or appropriate that grievances of victims should be matched by suffering of offenders. There is a close link here with retribution as repayment. If child A hits child B causing him pain and a sense of grievance, child B will frequently be heard to say, ā€œIā€™ll make you pay for that!ā€. The payment is felt to have been exacted once B has inflicted a similar hurt on A. (Such beliefs are by no means confined to children, but children tend to make them more explicit.) Unfortunately for this version of the satisfaction theory, it is far from clear how the indubitable psychological facts just cited are capable of providing a satisfactory moral justification for the practice of punishment (unless we fall into the error commonly attributed to Mill and argue that what is desired is therefore desirable).
(5b) A second, and more sophisticated, version of the satisfaction theory is put forward by Justice Steven: ā€œthe criminal law regulates sanctions and provides a satisfaction for the passion of revengeā€.12 If the underlying idea here is that the penal system provides a substitute for private revenge, then it turns out that the focus of justification does not centre on the notion of retribution at all. Rather, we seem to be dealing with a utilitarian approach, where the penal system is justified as a mechanism for the prevention of vendettas, which furthers the goal of social stabilityā€”making society better ordered and more secure.

(6) FAIR PLAY THEORY

ā€œFailure to punish is unfair to those who practise self-restraint and respect the rights of others.ā€13 ā€œ[Retributivism proposes that] a manā€™s punishment is justified or obligatory because ā€¦ unlike non-offenders he has gained satisfactions attendant on the commission of an offence.ā€14 These quotations are strongly reminiscent of John Rawlsā€™ ā€œjustice-as-fairnessā€ defence of political obligation. The citizen, according to Rawls, has a duty to obey laws of which he disapproves because it is unfair to his fellow citizens if he voluntarily accepts the benefits of the social system without being prepared to shoulder his share of its burdens.15 The parallel suggestion, in the sphere of punishment, seems to be that the state is justified in punishing the offender on behalf of the good because otherwise he would be gaining an unfair advantage: he would be profiting from his own selfish refusal to play fair and respect the rights of his fellow citizens.
Is it correct to describe the fair-play theory as ā€œretributiveā€ in our basic sense? Only, I think, indirectly. The object of punishment, on theory (6), is the preservation of justice and the maintenance of fair play. The immediate focus of justification thus centres not on the offender but on the law-abiding citizen and the duties owed to him. It is not that punishing the offender is intrinsically appropriate, b...

Table of contents

  1. Cover
  2. Half Title
  3. Title Page
  4. Copyright Page
  5. Table of Contents
  6. Acknowledgements
  7. Series Preface
  8. Introduction
  9. PART I RETRIBUTIONS
  10. PART II RETRIBUTION AND DESERT
  11. PART III PROPORTIONALITY
  12. PART IV RETRIBUTIVIST EMOTIONS
  13. PART V RETRIBUTION AND MERCY
  14. Name Index