Women Philosophers on Autonomy
eBook - ePub

Women Philosophers on Autonomy

Historical and Contemporary Perspectives

  1. 232 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Women Philosophers on Autonomy

Historical and Contemporary Perspectives

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

We encounter autonomy in virtually every area of philosophy: in its relation with rationality, personality, self-identity, authenticity, freedom, moral values and motivations, and forms of government, legal, and social institutions. At the same time, the notion of autonomy has been the subject of significant criticism. Some argue that autonomy outweighs or even endangers interpersonal or collective values, while others believe it alienates subjects who don't possess a strong form of autonomy. These marginalized subjects and communities include persons with physical or psychological disabilities, those in dire economic conditions, LGBTI persons, ethnic and religious minorities, and women in traditional communities or households.

This volume illuminates possible patterns in these criticisms of autonomy by bringing to light and critically assessing the contribution of women throughout the history of philosophy on this important subject. The essays in this collection cover a wide range of historical periods and influential female philosophers and thinkers, from medieval philosophy through to contemporary debates. Important authors whose work is considered, among many others, include Hildegard of Bingen, Margaret Cavendish, Anne Conway, Mary Wollstonecraft, Susan Moller Okin, HĂ©lĂšne Cixous, Iris Marion Young, and Judith Jarvis Thomson. Women Philosophers on Autonomy will enlighten and inform contemporary debates on autonomy by bringing into the conversation previously neglected female perspectives from throughout history.

Frequently asked questions

Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Yes, you can access Women Philosophers on Autonomy by Sandrine Berges, Alberto L. Siani, Sandrine Berges, Alberto L. Siani in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Philosophy & Philosophy History & Theory. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Publisher
Routledge
Year
2018
ISBN
9781351733809

1 Introduction

Sandrine BergĂšs and Alberto L. Siani
We encounter the notion of autonomy in virtually every area of philosophy. Its principal aspects are: autonomy in its relation with rationality, personality, self-identity, authenticity (personal autonomy), autonomy in its relation with freedom, moral values, moral motivations (moral autonomy), and autonomy in its relation with forms of government, state sovereignty, and legal and social structures and institutions (political autonomy). The three aspects are clearly interrelated, yet not reducible to one another. The omnipresence of the concept of autonomy in philosophical debates is reflected in traditional accounts of the history of Western philosophy, as autonomy constitutes an essential component of rationality, from Plato’s and Aristotle’s rational self-determination up to the political autonomy and perfectionism debate in contemporary liberal philosophy, passing through the Stoic notion of self-sufficiency, Spinoza’s notion of adequate ideas, and Kant’s moral autonomy as rooted in practical reason. When we include women philosophers in that narrative, as this volume does, the list becomes longer. And were we to make the list more diverse, including non-Western philosophers, there is no doubt that it would become even longer. This is perhaps because issues related to autonomy inform not only philosophical practice, but also everyday life. Hardly a single dimension of life can escape evaluations in terms of autonomy: psychological autonomy, economic autonomy, legal autonomy, physical autonomy, autonomy of taste, etc. Matters of autonomy may have a different resonance depending on gender, race, sexuality, and social class, but all of us struggle with them to some extent.
Nonetheless, part of the efforts to diversify philosophy has resulted in the notion of autonomy becoming subject to significant criticism. In particular, there are two major threads of dissent. The first is the thought that autonomy outweighs or even endangers interpersonal or collective values (equality, solidarity, care, etc.). The second sees autonomy as alienating or marginalizing individual or collective subjects who do not, for different reasons, benefit from a strong form of autonomy. People with physical or psychological disabilities or in dire economic conditions, single parents, women in traditional communities or households, LGBTI persons, ethnic and religious minorities, and even whole states may find the requirement that they should aim for autonomy disconcerting or even demeaning. The quest for autonomy requires an institutional, moral, and social framework that is partly or wholly denied to a significant portion of the population, and without which autonomy is meaningless.
These criticisms have led to a widespread dissatisfaction, if not out-right skepticism, toward traditional conceptions of autonomy, beginning with the one that is perhaps most influential, namely the Kantian one. Autonomy, understood as the agent’s capacity for self-legislation, is at the core of Kant’s conception of practical reason. In fact, for Kant, no subject can be said to be free and morally-politically responsible unless it is based on such-conceived autonomy. Criticisms to Kant’s thick version of autonomy, however, remain mostly on the margin of philosophy, in that they are often voiced by those concerned with the shortcomings of existing accounts and so belong to the realms of feminist philosophy, or applied philosophy, rather than mainstream discussion. At the same time, the mainstream discussion relies on a limited canon and rarely includes contributions from those philosophers who might have reason to question autonomy. Since, despite all criticism, autonomy seems to remain a fundamental and possibly non-dispensable concept, formulating a more sophisticated and non-exclusive version of it is a major task whose importance goes far beyond the borders of the academic debate.
There is, therefore, a strong case to be made for revisiting the concept of autonomy from a wider angle, which includes the perspectives of people who have reason to be suspicious of it. In the case of this volume, we have chosen to put forward the perspective of women philosophers. This is not meant to redress, by itself, the imbalance that can be found in the philosophical debate autonomy, but to make a start by highlighting some of the ways in which the questions of autonomy can appear different from outside the mainstream perspective. This is also an occasion to build on recent work that has been done on recovering the works of women philosophers of the past and show how their arguments fit into a debate that reaches to the 21st century in a way that nourishes and enriches the ideas presented by contemporary and past philosophers alike.
In some cases, some biographical details are necessary, both because the philosopher in question and her period or her cultural environment are not generally known, and because, in other cases, the “lived” philosophy of the author casts light on what they wrote. But the focus of this volume is primarily to engage with a specific philosophical topic these philosophers are debating from different angles, namely autonomy and the way in which philosophical discussions on this topic are or could be informed by this debate, spanning over several periods of the history of philosophy. The volume will therefore contribute both to our knowledge of women philosophers and to the inquiry on the notion of autonomy. The essays collected here aim at illuminating possible patterns of this reformulation by bringing to light and critically assessing the contribution by women philosophers throughout the history of philosophy starting with the Medieval author Hildegard of Bingen and finishing with contemporary philosophers such as Susan Moller Okin and Martha Nussbaum. In this sense, moreover, the volume presents both historical research and contemporary perspectives (both in the “analytic” and the “continental” traditions).
As is clear, our ambition is to bridge several gaps: between women’s philosophical reflection in history and the notion of autonomy in its contemporary relevance, between past and contemporary perspectives, and between different cultural understandings, based on the diverse geographical and institutional rooting of the contributors to this volume.
One might object that there would be no need to bridge gaps in this way if the project had been more focused in the first place—if the essays had focused on questions of autonomy and equality, say, or education. But in fact, the concept of autonomy resists this sort of narrowing, especially when seen from the perspective of women philosophers. Instead of a single, universal, and eternal concept of autonomy, we see rather a concept that is always changing, a protean dynamical product of a constant effort, and not a static feature that may, by way of a binary opposition, be attributed to certain subjects (individuals or collective) and not to others. This is not meant to blur the concept of autonomy into an undistinguished mix of feelings and thoughts belonging to every subject and to no subject at all. Rather, we should emphasize the complex, multi-layered character of autonomy as something that is always on the verge of escaping our grasp. In fact, a philosophical approach to autonomy discloses from the very beginning aspects that seem to contradict not only the common-sense view of autonomy as absence of dependence on the will of other subjects, but also one another.
The aspects of autonomy that women philosophers in this volume focus on to bring out this varied multi-layered concept are numerous, but we may highlight three of them here. First of all, there is the matter of education: None of us is born an autonomous individual; rather, a long and complex process of education at the hands of other people is needed to get us there. Secondly, one may think of familial and social relationships and the role they play in developing our sense of autonomy, not only in the negative sense of an emancipation, but also in the positive sense of developing our personality, our system of preferences and needs, our life plans, etc.: in short, the various pieces of what constitutes each of us as an autonomous subject. Last, there are the institutions: Could we really be autonomous subjects if not in the framework of social and political institutions that not only guarantee our rights, but also enforce our duties?
Even the hasty naming of these three aspects complicates the view of autonomy as absence of dependence. If, among others, education, relations, and institutions play an essential role in the development of autonomy, how could we conceive of this latter in purely negative terms as a lack of ties and dependences, as a situation in which my free will is all that counts? But, on the other hand, does it make sense (and what sense?) to speak of autonomy in a way that necessarily involves a dependence on other subjects, both individual and collective? Furthermore, we often use freedom and independence as almost equivalent with autonomy, but clearly, even though they are cognate concepts, they are not the same, and a clarification of the apparent contradictions of autonomy has to go through a clarification of its proximity and difference from those cognate concepts.
It would be unfair to expect from the essays contained in this volume a univocal, precise answer as to what autonomy should look like once we recover the women philosophers’ voice. What on the contrary they manage to do, in our opinion, is to let this multi-layered character of autonomy emerge with its whole philosophical strength. They show that autonomy, both as a central philosophical concept and as a central dimension of real life, is not the result of a process of isolation and distillation, through which we create a space that is clear and separated from everything else. As a dimension of real life it is, rather, the product of a delicate balance of several, not necessarily compliant factors. As a philosophical concept, autonomy is at the meeting point of different ideas and even areas, which do not allow clear-cut responses. The reformulation our volume proposes by putting women perspectives on the proscenium is hence more precisely a series of reformulations, though not in the sense of mutually exclusive, unrelated proposals. Our hope is rather that each of the essays be considered as a possible face of autonomy and as a piece of a vivid, pluralistic discourse on it. The reader will find, in the perspectives of the philosophers here examined and in the approach of the authors of the papers, views ranging from enthusiastic re-appropriations of autonomy as a powerful emancipatory idea essential to the flourishing of women and men, to critical and skeptical evaluations of the concept, seen as yet another ideological tool or distortion aimed at keeping women and non-dominant groups in a condition of minority. We welcomed this broad theoretical span as yet another piece of evidence of the fertility and gap-bridging potential of the Recovery Project, and as a way of remapping the debate on autonomy by providing it with new, stimulating coordinates and orientations.
This collection proposes discussions of autonomy in and by women philosophers ranging from the Middle Ages to the 21st century. The fact that we do start in the 12th century, with Hildegard of Bingen, and then go through the 16th century, with Oliva Sabuco, the 17th century, with Madeleine de Scudery, Anne Conway, Margaret Cavendish, and the 18th century with Olympe de Gouges, Macaulay, and Wollstonecraft is evidence that we looked for conceptions of autonomy different from, though not necessarily incompatible with, the Kantian “invention” of morality as autonomy (see Schneewind 1998, 3). This does not mean that we reject Kantian autonomy as self-legislation of the subject under the moral law. However, as we suggested in the first half of this introduction, autonomy can mean many different things in different philosophical contexts, and looking for it beyond Kant, before and after, is a way of depicting the richness of that concept.
By beginning in Chapter 2 with Hildegard of Bingen in the 12th century, we do not mean to imply that autonomy as a concept did not exist until then. Indeed, autonomy played an important role in Plato’s moral and political thought (Cohen 1993). Unfortunately, it is harder to find texts by women philosophers of that period—this is the reason for our medieval start. In her contribution on Hildegard of Bingen, Lerius exposes the philosopher’s surprisingly modern thought, arguing that autonomy for Hildegard of Bingen means not only being responsible for oneself morally, but also entails a form of inter-dependence, which requires humans to regard not only their own well-being as their personal responsibility, but also that of others, and of the environment.
Olivia Sabuco was a 16th-century Spanish metaphysician whose work is only now beginning to come to light thanks to Mary Ellen Waithe’s scholarship. In Chapter 3, Waithe presents Sabuco as arguing for political and religious autonomy under the watchful eye of the Spanish Inquisition through a rejection of a number of Aristotelian precepts about human nature. Waithe’s discussion of Sabuco on autonomy takes us through different layers of that concept, which, for Sabuco, are interdependent. Personal and political autonomy is inferred from the emphasis she places on women’s mental and physical health and from her account of a well-functioning republic. Sabuco argues for collectivist limits on personal autonomy when its exercise threatens the personal freedoms or welfare of others. The resulting discussion is rich philosophically but also gives us a fascinating glimpse into the life and personality of this hitherto unknown philosopher.
Andreas Blank, in Chapter 4, discusses the works of three 17th-century philosophers: Madeleine de ScudĂ©ry, Jeanne-Michelle de Pringy, and Françoise d’AubignĂ©, Marquise de Maintenon, arguing that their work on “complaisance,” the inclination to please socially, is in many ways a discussion of autonomy. The philosophical question which is central to all three women’s discussion of complaisance is to what extent the social qualities which make (courtly) life pleasant or bearable are essentially in conflict with honesty, or with morality in general. Can one be socially acceptable and at the same time regain some sort of control on the morality of one’s actions? The three philosophers Blank discusses come up with different answers to this question, each bringing out the complexity of making autonomy fit within a social context.
Margaret Cavendish lived at a time when claiming political autonomy could and did amount to revolution and regicide. Like Hobbes, she was inclined to limit the very real damages of a civil war by strengthening the power of the monarch and lessening the autonomy of the subjects. BergĂšs, in Chapter 5, argues that there is more to this picture, however, and that Cavendish, reflecting on the condition of women, reached different conclusions from Hobbes as to the nature of freedom. Observing that for women autonomy was prevented as much by internal as by external obstacles, led her to the conclusion that autonomy depended partly on internal growth through education.
A contemporary of Cavendish, Anne Conway, was less interested in political philosophy than metaphysics and theology. Her complex system of substances can be read, Fiona Tomkinson tells us in Chapter 6, as a discussion of different kinds and levels of autonomy. For Conway, God, or the First Substance, is autonomous in the sense of being independent, but lacks the power to change in any way. Christ, the Second Substance, can change for the better, but not the worse, whilst the Third Substance, consisting of “creatures,” including human beings, is fully autonomous in the sense of being capable of changing themselves in either direction, but not in the sense of being independent. Tomkinson then discusses contemporary eco-feminist scholarship on Conway and suggests how it may be enriched by a consideration of the questions of self-perfection and autonomy.
In Chapter 7, Alan Coffee argues that at least some women republican writers of the 18th century had developed a relational concept of personal and social freedom that anticipates and prefigures subsequent feminist critiques of individuated accounts of autonomy. Catharine Macaulay and, subsequently, Mary Wollstonecraft showed how human beings are inevitably embedded in an intricate set of social institutions, practices, and expectations that shaped their capacity to act. While everyone is influenced by their surroundings, it is women who suffer most given their subordinate social position. Using a modified form of what we would now refer to as freedom as non-domination, these writers maintained that unless the social background reflected women’s as well as men’s input and perspectives, women could not act autonomously.
In Chapter 8, Martina Reuter, whose focus is also Wollstonecraft, discusses how Schneewind’s interpretation of the invention of autonomy would look different had it included a discussion of Wollstonecraft’s moral philosophy. Reuter takes into account in particular the gender dimension of Wollstonecraft’s discussion and how Wollstonecraft’s combination of egalitarian and perfectionist tendencies challenges the opposition Schneewind posits between these two aspects of moral philosophy. She looks in particular at the place of education in the development of autonomy, a topic that is largely overlooked by Schneewind. Reuter notes that the most significant elements of Wollstonecraft’s conception of autonomy focus on questions of knowledge and education, so that, in an important sense, Wollstonecraft’s outlook is not unlike Kant’s. Reuter concludes that had she engaged with Kant’s work, Wollstonecraft would have almost certainly argued for his arguments to be extended to women.
Chapter 9 continues in the 18th century, but with an opening onto the 20th. Alberto Siani contrasts two feminist accounts of justice: that of revolutionary philosopher Olympe de Gouges and Susan Moller Okin’s. Focusing on Gouges’s Declaration of the Rights of Woman and on Okin’s critique of Rawls, Siani suggests that Gouges and Okin are both reacting to a similar problem: the exclusion of the feminine perspective from philosophical (and political) debates about justice and rights. Gouges, he notes, attempts to solve this problem by replacing considerations of autonomy with those of social cohesion. Okin, Siani argues, achieves the same desired result while maintaining autonomy as a central goal for justice. His contribution offers a discussion of the contrast between these two responses.
Chapter 10 takes us into the 19th century, with Patrick Fessenbecker’s discussion of how the novelist Mary Ward embraced the philosophy of British Idealist Thomas Hill Green, but also questioned his views about the necessary conditions for personal autonomy. This contribution reminds us of the importance of not limiting the genre of philosophical texts: Not only did much philosophy get written in the form of novels or plays in the 17th, 18th and 19th century (Voltaire wrote plays, Rousseau novels and even an opera), but this was in particular the case for women philosophers, for whom it was harder to find acceptance as “purely intellectual” writers (ScudĂ©ry, Cavendish, and Gouges are prime examples of philosophers who made use of literary genres).
With Chapter 11 we move definitely into the 20th century. Hatice Karaman looks at the works of HĂ©lĂšne Cixous and attempts do derive a philosophy of autonomy from Cixous’s theory of â€œĂ©criture fĂ©minine,” which argues that women must create their own autonomy by writing about themselves. This contribution is also a comment on the tendency of philosophy to dismiss some of its women members by calling them “feminist theorists” rather than philosophers. Karaman challenges this tendency, as well as other canonical boundaries of philosophy, by reading the exchange between Cixous and Jacques Derrida not only in the light of the postmodernist topos of intertextuality, but also in that of Cixous’s distinctive idea of intersextuality.
Chapter 12 brings us into the domain of applied ethics and discusses the role played by personal autonomy as self-determination in Judith Jarvis Thomson’s defense of abortion. Daniela Ringkamp, in this contribution, argues that Thomson fails to give a sufficient response to the “responsibility” objection that argues that if a pregnancy is the (unintended) result of an autonomous act then the pregnant person has a responsibility to see through the pregnancy. On the other hand, Ringkamp shows that Thomson’s violinist analogy points out imp...

Table of contents

  1. Cover
  2. Title
  3. Copyright
  4. Contents
  5. Preface
  6. 1 Introduction
  7. 2 Hildegard von Bingen on Autonomy
  8. 3 Freedom’s Just Another Word for Nothin’ Left to Lose: Oliva Sabuco’s Philosophy and Life
  9. 4 Complaisance and the Question of Autonomy in the French Women Moralists, 1650–1710
  10. 5 Margaret Cavendish on Women’s Autonomy, Political Skepticism, and Republican Values
  11. 6 Three Types of Infinite Autonomy: The Philosophy of Anne Conway
  12. 7 Independence as Relational Freedom: A Republican Account Derived From Mary Wollstonecraft
  13. 8 Mary Wollstonecraft’s Contribution to the “Invention of Autonomy”
  14. 9 No Justice Without Autonomy! Olympe de Gouges and Susan Moller Okin
  15. 10 Autonomy, Divinity, and the Common Good: Selflessness as a Source of Freedom in Thomas Hill Green and Mary Augusta Ward
  16. 11 Intersextuality: Derrida and Cixous
  17. 12 Responsibility and Involvement: Judith Jarvis Thomson’s Justification of Abortion
  18. 13 “Living in Contradiction”: Iris Marion Young’s Contribution to the Philosophy of Sports
  19. 14 Autonomy, Emotional Vulnerability, and the Dynamics of Power
  20. Contributors
  21. Index