Music, Experiment and Mathematics in England, 1653–1705
eBook - ePub

Music, Experiment and Mathematics in England, 1653–1705

  1. 222 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Music, Experiment and Mathematics in England, 1653–1705

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

How, in 1705, was Thomas Salmon, a parson from Bedfordshire, able to persuade the Royal Society that a musical performance could constitute a scientific experiment? Or that the judgement of a musical audience could provide evidence for a mathematically precise theory of musical tuning? This book presents answers to these questions. It constitutes a general history of quantitative music theory in the late seventeenth century as well as a detailed study of one part of that history: namely the applications of mathematical and mechanical methods of understanding to music that were produced in England between 1653 and 1705, beginning with the responses to Descartes's 1650 Compendium music and ending with the Philosophical Transactions' account of the appearance of Thomas Salmon at the Royal Society in 1705. The book is organized around four key questions. Do musical pitches form a small set or a continuous spectrum? Is there a single faculty of hearing which can account for musical sensation, or is more than one faculty at work? What is the role of harmony in the mechanical world, and where can its effects be found? And what is the relationship between musical theory and musical practice? These are questions which are raised and discussed in the sources themselves, and they have wide significance for early modern theories of knowledge and sensation more generally, as well as providing a fascinating side light onto the world of the scientific revolution.

Frequently asked questions

Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Yes, you can access Music, Experiment and Mathematics in England, 1653–1705 by Benjamin Wardhaugh in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Media & Performing Arts & Music. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Publisher
Routledge
Year
2017
ISBN
9781351557078
Edition
1
Subtopic
Music

Chapter 1
From Pythagoras to Kircher

Imagine a scholar living and working in Restoration England, with an interest in the mathematical theory of music. Such scholars existed; they included the mathematicians John Wallis and John Pell, the President of the Royal Society William Brouncker, Isaac Newton, and the English exponent of atomism Walter Charleton, to name only a few. What sources were available to such a scholar, to widen or deepen one’s knowledge of mathematical music theory? How, indeed, would one find out that such a subject existed at all?
A great deal of relevant material could have been at the disposal of such a scholar. The mathematical study of music had a history stretching from ancient Greece to seventeenth-century France and Italy, and had left a correspondingly plentiful written account of itself. But certain parts of that account loomed very much larger on the seventeenth-century horizon than others: notably the classical texts which had been edited and published over the preceding 150 years, and the early seventeenth-century works of René Descartes, Marin Mersenne and Athanasius Kircher. What remained unread were the medieval sources, which with a bare handful of exceptions remained in almost total obscurity in manuscripts, and more surprisingly, the numerous sixteenth-century Italian publications whose ideas, on the whole, seem to have reached England by indirect routes.
The earlier history of mathematical theories of music was one of increasingly complex elaborations upon a roughly stable basic idea – though that is not to say that ancient Greek ideas about the subject were simple. Their history in late seventeenth-century England was one of fruitful reinvention, as writers tried to incorporate into an existing discipline the new ideas of the scientific revolution: a task which proved productive of unexpected novelties, and which was to take the mathematics of music in directions previously unsuspected.

Ancient Sources

Aristoxenians and Pythagoreans

Two major classical Greek sources on mathematical music theory have survived, both from roughly the late fourth century BC: the Harmonics of the peripatetic philosopher aristoxenus, and the Sectio canonis attributed, still somewhat controversially, to the geometer Euclid. Music theory texts from the first to the fourth centuries AD have survived in slightly greater numbers, and that of ptolemy – from the second century AD – is perhaps the most important for this book.1
There were two distinct traditions in the mathematical study of music in classical greece. For aristoxenus:
harmonics is a science whose data and explanatory principles are independent of those in any other domain of enquiry. its subject is music as we hear it, the perceptual data offered to the discerning musical ear. Its task is to exhibit the order that lies within the perceived phenomena; to analyse the systematic patterns into which it is organised; to show how the requirement that notes must fall into certain patterns of organisation, if they are to be grasped as melodic, explains why some possible sequences of pitches form a melody while others do not; and ultimately to display all the rules governing melodic form as flowing from a coordinated group of principles that describe a single, determinate essence, that of ‘the melodic’ or ‘the well-attuned’ itself.
The predecessors of aristoxenus in this approach to music were ‘“empiricists” of a cruder sort’. later writers who were – and are – called ‘aristoxenians’ tended to be academic systematisers, with less interest than aristoxenus himself in actual musical experience.2 These included the writers of what are now known as the ‘Aristoxenian handbooks’ of the second and third centuries AD: musical compilations and catechisms by cleonides, gaudentius, Bacchius and others.3
In contrast with the aristoxenian stood the ‘Pythagorean’ or, more generally, ‘mathematical’ approach to music theory. these pythagoreans:
were not typically interested in the study of music for its own sake …. The order found in music is a mathematical order; the principles of the coherence of a coordinated harmonic system are mathematical principles. and since these are principles that generate a perceptibly beautiful and satisfying system of organisation, perhaps it is these same mathematical relations, or some extension of them, that underlie the admirable order of the cosmos, and the order to which the human soul can aspire.4
‘Pythagorean’ writers identified musical intervals with the ratios of lengths of strings, and discussed intervals by discussing those ratios. two otherwise identical strings whose lengths formed the ratio 2:1 would produce pitches one octave apart. The octave could therefore be identified with the ratio 2:1, and its specifically musical nature rapidly eclipsed by wholly mathematical or numerological theorising. this tradition is represented mainly by somewhat fragmentary evidence, but a mathematising approach shorn of numerological speculation was at work in the Euclidean Sectio canonis.
An essential difference between the aristoxenian and pythagorean approaches to music theory was the roles which they assigned to sense and to reason, and the relationship which they supposed to exist between them. the aristoxenian approach privileged the actual experience of hearing musical sounds, and tended to discount such results of pure reason as were not clearly descriptive of those experiences. The Pythagorean approach took the opposite line, privileging the results of reason applied to abstractions, and tending to disregard any objections the senses might raise to those results. the relationship between sense and reason in music would remain problematic, and would present increasingly complex difficulties, nearly a millennium and a half later.5
Our most important source from later in the Greek tradition discusses both the pythagorean and aristoxenian approaches to music theory: namely the Harmonics of ptolemy, written in the second century ad. ptolemy directed strong refutations at the Aristoxenians, but although, like the Pythagoreans, he identified musical intervals with the ratios of string lengths, he also took enormous care to provide experimental checks for his reasoned results about musical tuning.6

Classical Editions

The recovery of the ancient Greek musical sources began around the tenth century in Byzantium, and by the fifteenth century, manuscripts were being transmitted to Venice. This work of recovery of ancient music as a literary discipline rather than a repertoire may ultimately have contributed to the separation between theory and practice which we will meet in the seventeenth century.7 But our scholar in seventeenth-century England would not have had to consult rare and difficult manuscripts in order to have access to the Greek musical writings: indeed, not even the ability to read Greek would have been necessary. By the middle of the century, nearly all of the major texts had appeared in print, and many had been translated into latin.8
Henry Savile’s 1609 donation of manuscripts to the Bodleian Library included a copy of Ptolemy’s Harmonics, as well as another ancient Greek music treatise, that of Aristides Quintilianus. The Savilian professorships which he founded in 1619 were intended to promote all of the mathematical arts – including ‘harmonics’ or ‘canonics’, the mathematical study of music – and the Savilian professors were encouraged to prepare editions of relevant classical texts as well as lecturing. in 1627, Peter Turner, the Savilian professor of geometry, was employed by John Selden to ‘translate and collate’ Greek musical manuscripts including those of gaudentius and alypius, although that project did not result in a published edition. Later, the musician and scholar Edmund Chilmead worked on Oxford’s Greek musical manuscripts, and he began to prepare an edition of gaudentius which, in the event, was abandoned when it was superseded by the appearance of Marcus Meibom’s edition in amsterdam in 1652.9 Later still, in the 1680s and 1690s, another Savilian professor of geometry, John Wallis, published editions of the musical writings of Ptolemy, Porphyry and Bryennius.
The first Greek authors to be edited, around the beginning of the sixteenth century, were two who are now relatively obscure: Cleonides – an Aristoxenian – and Theon, both from the second century AD.10 Theon’s book on the mathematics required to read plato included a good deal of musical material and transmitted many fragments from other musical authors. after these, and an edition of the Euclidean Sectio canonis in 1557, the major editions introducing new texts were gogava’s of aristoxenus, ptolemy and aristotle in 1562, and johannes van Meurs’ of Nicomachus (from the first half of the second century AD) and Alypius (from the fourth or fifth century AD) in 1616. Fédéric Morel edited Bacchius (fourth century AD or later) in 1623. The sixteenth-century editions were strikingly concentrated in paris.
What may be called a second wave of publications began in 1644 with a new paris edition of theon. the remainder of the texts that had so far been published received new editions either from Marcus Meibom in 1652 or from john Wallis in 1682 and 1699; Meibom also provided the first editions of Gaudentius and aristides Quintilianus (both from the third–fourth century ad), and athanasius Kircher edited the surviving fragments of the writings of Archytas (fourth century Bc) in his Musurgia universalis of 1650.
Many of these editions were parallel Greek–Latin texts. Vernacular translations were much more unusual, and by 1700, only two texts had received them. these were cleonides’ Eisagoge harmonice (attributed at the time to Euclid), which was published in French in 1566, and capella’s late, encyclopaedic De nuptiis philologiae et mercurii, which contained a long section on music.
The overall result was that by 1600, most of the major texts, including those of Euclid, Aristoxenus and Ptolemy, had been published; by 1652, most of the Greek musical writings which are now known had been published, and the major texts existed in recent and fairly authoritative editions – with the sole exception of ptolemy’s Harmonics, a gap filled by Wallis in 1682.
We will see in the later chapters of this book how some of the particular issues present in the Greek sources were revisited in the seventeenth century. The roles of sense and reason and the implications of quantifying musical pitch using ratios would provide crucial questions for the reworking of mathematical music that took place in Restoration England.

Boethius and the Pythagorean Scale

Despite the richness of the Greek music theory tradition, theorists in the Middle ages were heavily reliant on a single second-hand description for their information about that tradition. that description was the De institutione musica of A.M.S. Boethius, written early in the sixth century AD. Boethius (c. 480–524) transmitted to the medieval universities the structure of the curriculum comprising seven liberal arts, one of which was ‘harmonics’; his De institutione musica became the standard source for the content of that subject. it was based closely on the lost work of Nicomachus, who wrote in the second century AD.11
Among his four mathematical arts – arithmetic, geometry, harmonics and astronomy – Boethius distinguished arithmetic from geometry on the basis of their subject matter: arithmetic was concerned with multitudes (‘HOW many?’), geometry with magnitudes (‘HOW much?’). similarly, astronomy was the study of magnitudes in relation to the heavens, and harmonics the study of multitudes, of numbers, in relation to sounds: in fact, in relation to pitch. harmonics in this sense corresponded only to a part of the Greek study of music, which had also been concerned with rhythm and metre. (Rhythm was discussed in augustine’s (354– 430) De musica libri sex, but this never became an important teaching text.)12
Among much else, in his discussion of pitch Boethius described the ‘Pythagorean’ scale, whose construction was surely more concerned with mathematical neatness than with actual musical practice. It was formed by taking fifths and fourths as corresponding to the ratios 3:2 and 4:3 respectively – that is, they were produced by pairs of strings whose lengths formed those ratios – and the whole tone as the difference between them, with the ratio 9:8. the major third was taken as two tones, that is 81:64, and was not a consonance. The semitone was the difference between a major third and a fourth: 256:243. Minor thirds, and both major and minor sixths, were described by similarly complex ratios (see Figure 1.1).
Images
Figure 1.1 The Pythagorean scale
Since its thirds and sixths were impure, it is improbable that the pythagorean scale was much used in practice after those intervals became widespread as consonances, that is after perhaps 1300 – if indeed it was ever used at all. But this scale acquired a legitimacy among theorists which was quite independent of its tenuous relationship with musical practice: its appearance in Boethius became a certificate of its sanction by the ancients, and it was proposed and re-proposed as the ideal model for musical tuning until the seventeenth century and beyond. in Chapter 5, we will examine the writings of john Birchensha, a practical musician active in the 1660s and 1670s who insisted unflaggingly on the theoretical importance of the pythagorean scale, which he cannot have used in ...

Table of contents

  1. Cover Page
  2. Half title
  3. Dedication
  4. Title
  5. Copyright
  6. Contents
  7. List of Figures
  8. Acknowledgements
  9. List of Abbreviations
  10. Introduction
  11. 1 From Pythagoras to Kircher
  12. 2 Musical Pitch: Discrete or Continuous?
  13. 3 Faculties of Hearing
  14. 4 Harmony in the Mechanical World
  15. 5 Theories and Practices
  16. Conclusion
  17. Select Bibliography
  18. Index