Subjects of Analysis
eBook - ePub

Subjects of Analysis

  1. 241 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Subjects of Analysis

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

This book offers a way of understanding and making use of a critical dimension of the analytic experience that is rarely spoken about by psychotherapists and analysts: the ordinary, moment-to-moment experience of the analyst in the analytic setting.

Frequently asked questions

Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Yes, you can access Subjects of Analysis by Thomas Ogden in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Psicología & Historia y teoría en psicología. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Publisher
Routledge
Year
2018
ISBN
9780429919510

1
On Becoming a Subject

It is too late to turn back. Having read the opening words of this book you have already begun to enter into the unsettling experience of finding yourself becoming a subject whom you have not yet met, but nonetheless recognize. The reader of this book must create a voice with which to speak (think) the words (thoughts) comprising it. Reading is not simply a matter of considering, weighing, or even of trying out the ideas and experiences that are presented by the writer. Reading involves a far more intimate form of encounter. You, the reader, must allow me to occupy you, your thoughts, your mind, since I have no voice with which to speak other than yours. If you are to read this book, you must allow yourself to think my thoughts while I must allow myself to become your thoughts and in that moment neither of us will be able to lay claim to the thought as our own exclusive creation.
The conjunction of my words and your mental voice does not represent a form of ventriloquism. A more complex and interesting human event is involved. A third subject is created in the experience of reading that is not reducible to either writer or reader. The creation of a third subject (that exists in tension with the writer and the reader as separate subjects) is the essence of the experience of reading, and, as will be explored in this volume, is also at the core of the psychoanalytic experience.
In writing these sentences, I choose each word and phrase and speak to myself through the voice of the reader whom I have created in my own mind. It is the otherness of the reader (whom I imagine and anticipate in my own internal division of myself into writer and reader, subject and object) that allows me to hear myself in preparation for your reading. In your reading, you generate a voice from my words that will create me in a broader sense than I am able to create myself. In that process you and I shall have created one another as a subject who has not existed to this point.
The reader and writer do not create one another ahistorically. The present in which the third subject comes into being is not simply the current moment, but "the present moment of the past" (Eliot 1919), which (past) speaks through us as much as we speak through one another. Laius's, and later, Oedipus's attempts to create an ahistorical present set in motion the cascade of events leading to the deafening roar of the insistence of history and of mortality. We must recognize ourselves in Laius's and Oedipus's efforts to escape history, since each of us resists experiencing ourselves as spoken as well as speaking. Art, literature, history, philosophy, and psychoanalysis all teach us, despite our protestations, that we are indeed spoken, not only by the historical Other, but by the unconscious Other and the intersubjective Other.
You, the reader, will oppose me, deny me, perhaps humor me, but never entirely give way to me. This book will not be "understood" by you; you will not simply receive it, incorporate it, digest it, or the like. To the degree that you will have anything at all to do with it, you will transform it. (The word transform is too tepid a word to describe what you will do to it.) You will destroy it, and out of that destruction (in that destruction) will come a sound that you will not fully recognize. The sound will be a voice, but it will not be one of yours that you have heard before, for you have not previously destroyed me as you will encounter me in your reading of this book. The sound that you will hear is certainly not my voice since the words on this page are silent, composed as much by the white shapes around the black markings as by the markings themselves.
What I am describing is at the same time one of the most mysterious of human experiences and one of the most commonplace — it is the experience of doing battle with one's static self-identity through the recognition of a subjectivity (a human I-ness) that is other to oneself. The confrontation with alterity will not let us rest; that perception of the other I-ness once perceived will not allow us to remain who we were and we cannot rest until we have somehow come to terms with its assault on who we had been prior to being interrupted by it. This book is a disturbance, a disruption to you. You may decide to put the book down, but that would only be a postponement of something that has already been set in motion. This book has already become "an eternal curse on the reader of these pages" (Puig 1980).
If you decide not to postpone the confrontation posed by this book, you will know something of the experience of the analyst as he begins the first meeting (and every subsequent meeting) with an analysand. The analyst must be prepared to destroy and be destroyed by the otherness of the subjectivity of the analysand and to listen for a sound emerging from that collision of subjectivities that is familiar, but different from anything that he has previously heard. This listening must be done "without memory or desire" (Bion 1963), but at the same time the listener must be rooted in the history that has created (spoken) him if he is to be able to discern the sound of which I am speaking. The destruction of analyst by analysand and of analysand by analyst (as separate subjects) in the collision of subjectivities must not be complete or else the pair has fallen into the abyss of psychosis or autism. Instead, the analyst must listen to (through) the roar of the destruction from its edge, not ever being certain where that edge lies.
The subjects of analysis that will be the focus of this volume bear a dialectical relationship to one another. From the elements of the dialectic of subject and object, a new whole begins to emerge that almost immediately reveals itself to be a new source of dialectical tension. The analytic process, which creates analyst and analysand, is one in which the analysand is not simply the subject of analytic inquiry; the analysand at the same time must be the subject in that inquiry (that is, creating that inquiry) since his self-reflection is fundamental to the enterprise of psychoanalysis. Similarly, the analyst cannot simply be the observing subject of this endeavor since his subjective experience in this endeavor is the only possible avenue through which he gains knowledge of the relationship he is attempting to understand.
Having said something of the interdependence of analyst and analysand (as subjects creating and created, destroying and destroyed by one another), we must introduce a third term, for without it we will not have adequately described the psychoanalytic process in which the analyst and analysand as subjects of analysis create one another. The nature of the third term is that which defines the nature of psychoanalytic experience and differentiates it from all other intersubjective human events. (There exist innumerable forms of human intersubjectivity, but none involves the form of intersubjectivity that is distinctive to psychoanalysis.)
In the same moment that analyst and analysand are created, a third subject is generated that I shall refer to in this volume as the analytic third, since it is a middle term sustaining and sustained by the analyst and analysand as two separate subjects. More accurately, analyst and analysand come into being in the process of the creation of the analytic subject. The analytic third, although created jointly by (what is becoming) the analyst and analysand, is not experienced identically by analyst and analysand since each remains a separate subject in dialectical tension with the other. Moreover, although the analytic third is constituted in the process of the mutual negation/recognition of analyst and analysand, it does not reflect each of its creators in the same way any more than the third created in the experience of reading reflects the reader and writer in the same way. In other words, the transference and countertransference reflect one another, but are not mirror images of one another.
The analytic third is not only a form of experience participated in by analyst and analysand, it is at the same time a form of experiencing I-ness (a form of subjectivity) in which (through which) analyst and analysand become other than who they had been to that point. The analyst gives voice to and participates in the creation of experience that is the living past of the analysand and in this way not only hears about the analysand's experience, but experiences his own creation of it. The analyst does not experience the past of the analysand; rather, the analyst experiences his own creation of the past of the analysand as generated in his experience of the analytic third
At the same time, the analysand experiences his own living past as created intersubjectively in the third. The analysand does not reexperience his past; the analysand experiences his past as it is being created for the first time in the process of its being lived in and through the analytic third. (It is therefore a past that could be created only by this particular analytic pair through this particular analytic third.) As an experience lived in (and through) the analytic third, onr is never completely alone with oneself (and one's past experience), since one's experience is being created with another person. This feature of the analytic situation creates the conditions for a fundamental recontextualization of formerly unintegrable, split off, unutilizable experience of the analysand.
To conclude (or better, to begin), psychoanalysis can be thought of as an effort to experience, understand, and describe the shifting nature of the dialectic generated by the creation and negation of the analyst by the analysand and of the analysand by the analyst within the context of the roles constituting the analytic set-up. The dialectical tension generated by this creative negation and recognition does not present a question to be answered, a riddle to be solved. It is fitting that the riddle of the Sphinx (taken as the paradigm of the analytic mystery of subjectivities confronting one another) does not have an answer. In the myth of Oedipus, there is momentary victory for Oedipus (and for us as audience in identification with Oedipus) in Oedipus's capacity to answer the riddle of the Sphinx and thereby overcome the power of the Sphinx to block entry to Thebes. But the answer to the riddle (more accurately, the very fact that an answer was offered and was accepted) quickly comes to strike us as a disappointing trivialization of the question (just as Oedipus's victory over the Sphinx is ultimately revealed in the narrative to be still another reflection of Oedipus's subjugation to the Other).
The question posed by the Sphinx in the form of a riddle concerning a creature that walks on four legs in the morning, two at midday and three in the evening, is a question about the nature of the human condition in its multiform possibilities (represented by fourness that becomes twoness that becomes threeness). The answer to the riddle of the Sphinx must include all possible answers to the question of what it is to be human in a community of historically rooted human beings. We must attempt not to allow the fundamental psychoanalytic questions about the nature of human experience generated in the confrontation of subjectivities in the analytic situation to be trivialized with answers that pretend to offer more than an effort to describe a moment in time that is disappearing and becoming something different as we are attempting to recognize what it is.
Each of the chapters of this volume attempts in different ways to explore a conception of psychoanalysis as a unique form of dialectical interplay of the individual subjectivities of analyst and analysand leading to the creation of a new subject (more accurately, a myriad of new subjects: the subjects of analysis).
This introductory chapter is followed by a discussion of the foundations of a psychoanalytic conception of the subject. For Freud, the subject is neither coincident with the conscious, thinking, speaking, self nor is the subject located "behind the repression barrier" in "the unconscious mind." Instead, Freud's conception of subjectivity, in my view, is fundamentally dialectical in nature and is rooted in the idea that the subject is created, maintained, and simultaneously decentered from itself through the dialectical interplay of consciousness and unconsciousness. The principle of presence-in-absence and absence-in-presence subtends the Freudian conception of this dialectical movement.
In Chapters 3 and 4, I discuss the paths by which an intersubjective conception of the subject is developed in the work of Klein and Winnicott (often in ways that they were not aware of). For Klein, the subject is constituted through the dialectical interplay of fundamentally different modes of attributing meaning to experience (the "positions") leading to the creation of a subject decentered in psychic space and in analytic time.
I view Klein's concept of projective identification (particulary as elaborated by Bion, Heimann, and H. Rosenfeld) as a monumental step in the expansion of the analytic understanding of the nature and forms of dialectical tension underlying the creation of the subject. While Freud viewed the subject as dialectically constituted in the interplay of the "qualities* of consciousness and unconsciousness, the concept of projective identification introduces a conception of the subject constituted in the context of a complex system of psychological-interpersonal forces. With the introduction of the concept of projective identification, the idea of the interdependence of subject and object became fundamental to the analytic understanding of the creation and development of subjectivity. From that point on, analytic theory of technique has undergone radical change and has become increasingly devoted over the past fifty years to the study of the interdependence of subject and object, of transference and countertransference, in human development and in the analytic process.
In the work of Winnicott, the subject is seen as coming into being in the (potential) space between mother and infant (and in the analytic space between analyst and analysand). The Winnicottian subject is generated in the context of a series of paradoxes involving forms of dialectical tension between experiences of at-one-ment and separateness, me and not-me, I and me, I and Thou. In the course of the exploration of the contributions of Klein and Winnicott to an analytic conception of the subject, I begin a discussion of the notion of a third subject created intersubjectively by the analytic pair.
In Chapter 5, the concept of the analytic third is more fully elaborated and clinically illustrated. This chapter is grounded in a detailed examination of portions of two analyses. This clinical material is provided in an effort to describe the analyst's use of his moment-to-moment experience in and of the newly created subject of analysis (the analytic third) generated jointly (but experienced differently) by the analyst and the analysand. In the first of these clinical accounts, I describe how the intersubjective experience created by the analytic pair becomes accessible to the analyst through his experience of his own "reveries" (Bion 1962a), forms of psychological activity that at first appear to be nothing more than his own distractedness, narcissistic ruminations, daydreaming, self-absorption, and the like. In the second clinical vignette, I discuss an instance in which the analyst's somatic delusion in conjunction with the analysand's sensory experiences and body-related fantasies constituted a significant medium through which the analyst came to understand the leading transference-countertransference anxieties of the phase of analysis in which these phenomena occurred.
In Chapter 6, I discuss the phenomenon of projective identification as a specific form of analytic thirdness in which the interplay of mutual subjugation and mutual recognition is fundamental to its elaboration and "analytic resolution." Projective identification is understood as a psychological-interpersonal process in which there is a partial collapse of the dialectic of subjectivity and intersubjectivity. The form of intersubjective third that is generated in projective identification is one in which the individual subjectivities of analyst and analysand (to a degree and for a time) are subsumed in (subjugated by) the newly created analytic third. A successful analytic process requires a superseding of the subjugating third and a reappropriation of the subjectivities of analyst and analysand as separate and yet interdependent individuals.
In Chapters 7 and 8, the understanding of the analytic process being discussed in this volume provides the theoretical framework for contributions to the development of two different aspects of clinical theory and analytic technique. In Chapter 7, the concept of interpretive action is explored. Interpretive action is viewed as an important, and yet little recognized, form of interpretation of the transference-countertransference. This type of interpretation (interpretation in the form of action) is understood as the analyst's use of action (other than verbally symbolic speech) to convey to the analysand specific aspects of his understanding of the transference countertransference, which understanding cannot at that juncture in the analysis be conveyed by the semantic content of words alone. An interpretation-in-action accrues its specificity of meaning from the experiential context of the analytic intersubjectivity in which it is generated.
The development in clinical theory and technique that is addressed in Chapter 8 is the analysis of the matrix of the transference-countertransference. Here, I demonstrate the central importance of the understanding and interpretation of the matrix (or background experiential state) within which the transference-countertransference is generated. The matrix of the transference-countertransference is conceived of as the intersubjective correlate (created in the analytic setting) of the psychic space in which the patient lives. In the clinical illustrations that are presented, there is a focus on the ways in which the analyst's interpretations must often be directed at the contextual level, or matrix, of transference-countertransference (for example, the significance of the way in which the analysand is speaking, thinking, behaving, experiencing sensation, and so on, as opposed to the content of what he is saying).
Chapter 9 addresses the phenomenon of personal isolation. Pathological autism is viewed as a form of breakdown of the dialectic of subjectivity and intersubjectivity in the early mother-infant relationship. Under such circumstances, there is a failure of the mother-infant dyad to create a fluid form of intersubjectivity in which there is a balance between being in the mother-as-environment and withdrawal into autosensuality. While in healthy development there are temporary disconnections from the mother (both as object and as environment), pathological autism is conceived of as representing the complete breakdown of the intersubjectivity of mother and infant and the creation of an experience of impenetrable, uninterrupted, nonbeing.
In Chapter 10, a wide range of issues of psychoanalytic theory and practice are discussed, ranging from the timing of interpretations of the transference-countertransference in the initial analytic meeting to a discussion of contrasting conceptions of the relationship of sexuality and object relations held by different schools of analytic thought. The leitmotif of the discussion in the concluding chapter (and in the book as a whole) is a fascination with the myriad forms of interplay of individual experience and shared experience that one encounters at every level of analytic practice, from the dynamic interplay of subjectivity and intersubjectivity in the analytic hour to the relationship of the analyst (in the "present moment of the past") to the history of the development of analytic ideas

Table of contents

  1. Cover
  2. Half Title
  3. Title
  4. Copyright
  5. Dedication
  6. Contents
  7. 1 On Becoming a Subject
  8. 2 The Freudian Subject
  9. 3 Toward an Intersubjective Conception of the Subject: The Kleinian Contribution
  10. 4 Winnicott's Intersubjective Subject
  11. 5 The Analytic Third: Working with Intersubjective Clinical Facts
  12. 6 Projective Identification and the Subjugating Third
  13. 7 The Concept of Interpretive Action
  14. 8 Analyzing the Matrix of the Transference-Countertransference
  15. 9 Personal Isolation: The Breakdown of Subjectivity and Intersubjectivity
  16. 10 Questions of Analytic Theory and Practice
  17. References
  18. Index