Anxiety Sensitivity
eBook - ePub

Anxiety Sensitivity

theory, Research, and Treatment of the Fear of Anxiety

  1. 384 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Anxiety Sensitivity

theory, Research, and Treatment of the Fear of Anxiety

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

Anxiety sensitivity (AS) is the fear of anxiety sensations which arises from beliefs that these sensations have harmful somatic, social, or psychological consequences. Over the past decade, AS has attracted a great deal of attention from researchers and clinicians with more than 100 peer-reviewed journal articles published. In addition, AS has been the subject of numerous symposia, papers, and posters at professional conventions. Why this growing interest?
Theory and research suggest that AS plays an important role in the etiology and maintenance of many forms of psychopathology, including anxiety disorders, depression, chronic pain, and substance abuse. Bringing together experts from a variety of different areas, this volume offers the first comprehensive state-of-the-art review of AS--its conceptual foundations, assessment, causes, consequences, and treatment--and points new directions for future work. It will prove to be an invaluable resource for clinicians, researchers, students, and trainees in all mental health professions.

Frequently asked questions

Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Yes, you can access Anxiety Sensitivity by Steven Taylor in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Psychology & Abnormal Psychology. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Publisher
Routledge
Year
2014
ISBN
9781135706388
Edition
1
I
CONCEPTUAL FOUNDATIONS
1
Theoretical Approaches to the Fear of Anxiety
Richard J. McNally
Harvard University
Pathological fears have often been defined by their eliciting stimuli. Nosologists, for example, have traditionally defined acrophobia as fear of heights, claustrophobia as fear of enclosed spaces, and agoraphobia as fear of open, public places. This tradition is notable for its neglect of the intentionality of fear, Intentionality does not mean deliberateness as in someone doing something intentionally. It refers to the aboutness of something (Brentano, 1889/1984). Rather than specify why an agoraphobic person fears shopping malls, subways, and so forth, traditional approaches to nosology merely identify the range of external cues that evoke excessive fear. Yet specifying the intentional object of fear (i.e., what the fear is about), and not merely its eliciting stimuli, has important nosological implications. For example, people with agoraphobia and people with specific flight phobia both nominally fear the same stimuli, yet the motivation for avoidance is entirely different. The intentional object for agoraphobics is panicking while aloft, whereas the intentional object for flight phobics is crashing (McNally & Louro, 1992).
In their landmark article on the reanalysis of agoraphobia, Goldstein and Chambless (1978) departed from the traditional perspective in important ways. Instead of viewing agoraphobia as a fear of stimuli embodied in public places, they emphasized the intentional object of agoraphobic fear—namely, panic and its presumed consequences. They also revived the notion that one’s own fear responses could constitute the focus of dread, popularizing the idea that agoraphobia is best conceptualized as a fear of fear itself.
The idea that fear can itself be the intentional object of anxiety had been previously expressed by a diverse range of authors. In his essay entitled Of Fear, Montaigne (1573/1948) said, “The thing I fear most is fear” (p. 53). He did not elaborate further, and this one sentence paragraph appears somewhat out of the blue. Nearly 400 years later, during the Great Depression, Roosevelt (1933/1965) famously proclaimed in his first Inaugural Address: “So first of all let me assert my firm belief that the only thing we have to fear is fear itself—nameless, unreasoning, unjustified terror which paralyzes needed efforts to convert retreat into advance” (p. 274).
Commentators on the fear of anxiety have not been confined to French essayists of the 16th century or to American politicians of the 20th century. Psychoanalytic theorists have also discussed the concept. Freud’s (1895/1962) personal experience with panic attacks may have led him to remark that, “in the case of agoraphobia, etc., we often find the recollection of an anxiety attack; and what the patient actually fears is the occurrence of such an attack under the special conditions in which he believes he cannot escape it” (p. 81, italics in original). Likewise, Otto Fenichel (cited in S. Reiss, 1987) proposed that:
In the first stages, the neurosis may be complicated by a secondary traumatic neurosis, induced by the first anxiety spell which is experienced as a trauma. Many anxiety hysterias develop out of such an experience, a fear of anxiety, and simultaneously a readiness to become frightened very easily, which may create a vicious circle. (p. 586)
Psychoanalyst Rosenberg (1949) conceptualized the capacity to tolerate anxiety as an individual difference variable rather than solely as a feature of agoraphobia. But veering off on a weird theoretical tangent, she then traced the fear of anxiety to its presumptive roots in unconscious aggressive and sexual impulses.
In his comprehensive historical review, Reiss (1987) observed that theorists of nearly every school of clinical psychology have addressed the fear of anxiety. The chief difference among them concerned whether they viewed it mainly as a facet of agoraphobia or whether they believed it relevant to a wide range of neurotic disturbances. Thus, Freud (1895/1962) held the former view, whereas Ellis (1978) expressed the latter view in his theory of discomfort anxiety. Reiss (1987) defended a hybrid perspective, noting that the fear of anxiety has implications for psychopathology in general, but acknowledging its special relevance for understanding agoraphobia.
Concluding his article with a call for more research, Reiss (1987) sketched an agenda for the study of the fear of anxiety. During the next 10 years, investigators have tackled many of the topics he mentioned. Much of this work concerned the relationship between the fear of anxiety and panic disorder (and agoraphobia; see, e.g., chaps. 6 and 10, this volume). However, recent studies have addressed topics unforeseen by Reiss (1987), such as the connection between anxiety sensitivity and essential hypertension (Pagotto, Fallo, Fava, Boscaro, & Sonino, 1992), asthma (Carr, Lehrer, Rausch, & Hochron, 1994), and chronic pain (Asmundson & Norton, 1995; see chap. 12, this volume).
The purpose of this introductory chapter is to provide a comparative analysis of the three main approaches to the fear of anxiety: (a) Pavlovian interoceptive conditioning, (b) catastrophic misinterpretation of bodily sensations, and (c) anxiety sensitivity. Because of its historical importance, panic disorder figures prominently in the discussion.
PAVLOVIAN INTEROCEPTIVE CONDITIONING
Goldstein and Chambless (1978) persuasively argued that agoraphobia is best conceptualized as a fear of fear and not as a fear of public places. They also suggested that such fear might develop through processes akin to Pavlovian interoceptive conditioning:
Having suffered one or more panic attacks, these people become hyperalert to their sensations and interpret feelings of mild to moderate anxiety as signs of oncoming panic attacks and react with such anxiety that the dreaded episode is almost invariably induced. This is analogous to the phenomenon described by Razran (1961) as interoceptive conditioning in which the conditioned stimuli are internal bodily sensations. In the case of fear of anxiety, a client’s own physiological arousal becomes the conditioned stimuli for the powerful conditioned response of a panic attack. (p. 55)
Accordingly, just as an external cue (e.g., tone) can be established as a conditioned stimulus (CS) if it predicts an aversive unconditioned stimulus (US), so might an internal cue (e.g., dyspnea) be established as a CS if it predicts panic.
Although many theorists agree that interoceptive conditioning may figure in the genesis of panic disorder (e.g., Barlow, 1988; Seligman, 1988; Wolpe & Rowan, 1988), others have been skeptical (e.g., Clark, 1988; McNally, 1990; Reiss, 1988). Critics have noted that, although Razran’s (1961) widely cited article described many Pavlovian interoceptive conditioning preparations (see e.g., McNally, 1990), none involved aversive learning that might provide a plausible model for panic attacks. Moreover, the conceptual clarity of the laboratory preparations is lost once one attempts to map interoceptive conditioning concepts onto the phenomenon of panic. For example, Goldstein and Chambless (1978) suggested that bodily sensations function as CSs that elicit the conditioned response (CR) of panic. Yet because these sensations are partly constitutive of panic itself, it is unclear which ones count as the CS and which ones count as the CR. Does a “dizziness CS” elicit a “palpitation CR” or vice versa? Distinctions become vague if one defines the CS and CR as two points on a continuum of arousal (i.e., CS = a little arousal, CR = a lot of arousal). That is, the phenomenon assigned the conceptual role of CS (e.g., an increase in heart rate) is the same as that assigned the conceptual role of CR (e.g., a further increase in heart rate).
Identifying the US and unconditioned response (UR) also presents problems. Because certain bodily perturbations are classified as CSs, they must, by definition, have been established as such via their association with a US. But what is the US and what UR does it evoke? The individual’s first panic is often viewed as the US. Unfortunately, the bodily sensations associated with panic have already been identified with both the CS and CR. Some theorists maintain that panic is the UR (e.g., Wolpe & Rowan, 1988), but this would imply that an event (i.e., panic as US) causes its own occurrence (i.e., panic as UR). Moreover, the interoceptive conditioning account of panic is based on a contiguity model whereby stimuli present during an attack become established as CSs. But the contiguity model has long been abandoned in favor of information-processing models of Pavlovian conditioning, which describe how organisms learn predictive relations among events (Reiss, 1980).
There was more to the Goldstein and Chambless (1978) theory than just the postulate about Pavlovian interoceptive conditioning (Chambless & Goldstein, 1988). They also emphasized that people with agoraphobia held beliefs about the catastrophic consequences of feared bodily sensations in addition to exhibiting Pavlovian CRs to these sensations. To measure these aspects of the syndrome, Chambless and her colleagues developed the Body Sensations Questionnaire (BSQ) and the Agoraphobic Cognitions Questionnaire (ACQ; Chambless, Caputo, Bright, & Gallagher, 1984).
CATASTROPHIC MISINTERPRETATION OF BODILY SENSATIONS
Purely biological approaches to panic disorder had become increasingly dominant until the publication of Clark’s (1986) influential article, “A Cognitive Approach to Panic.” In this article, Clark showed how his model could account for findings adduced in support of various biological theories. The core idea was that panic attacks “result from the catastrophic misinterpretation of certain bodily sensations” (p. 461). Accordingly, an individual might misinterpret dizziness as an impending faint, derealization as impending insanity, or palpitations as an impending heart attack. Initiating a positive feedback loop, these misinterpretations worsen anxiety and intensify bodily sensations until fullblown panic results. Although the misinterpreted bodily sensations may arise from anxiety, they may be associated with other emotional (e.g., anger) or nonemotional (e.g., caffeine ingestion) states as well. Regardless of their source, bodily sensations will not lead to panic unless they are misinterpreted as harbingers of imminent danger.
Reviewing Clark and Beck’s theories, Alford and Beck (1997) noted an “identity of conceptualization, even though different words are used” (p. 123). Clark’s model was foreshadowed by Beck, Emery, and Greenberg (1985), who stated that “her [the person experiencing a panic] interpretation of sudden uncontrollable symptoms as signs of impending physical or mental disaster then accelerates the process until a full-blown panic occurs” (p. 136). Theoretical resemblances notwithstanding, Clark’s (1986) version of the cognitive approach to panic was remarkably influential. Indeed, Clark’s article was the second most frequently cited one in the entire field of psychology among the more than 50,000 articles published during the years 1986 through 1990 (Garfield, 1992).
Clark’s theory stimulated a series of critiques and rejoinders (for a review, see McNally, 1994). A few are discussed next. One issue concerned whether catastrophic interpretations are causally implicated in the genesis of panic or whether they are merely epiphenomenal correlates of an unfolding, autonomous biological process. For example, Wolpe and Rowan (1988) noted that their patients reported experiencing catastrophic thoughts after their panic attacks were well underway.
Another issue concerned whether catastrophic misinterpretations are necessary for panic to occur. Several studies suggest that full-blown panics may occur in the apparent absence of antecedent catastrophizing (e.g., Aronson, Whitaker-Azmitia, & Caraseti, 1989; Rachman, Lopatka, & Levitt, 1988), and as Teasdale (1988) pointed out, just because some attacks are preceded by catastrophic misinterpretation of bodily sensations, one cannot conclude that all panics are so initiated.
The occurrence of panic attacks that erupt during nondreaming sleep pose another challenge to Clark’s central hypothesis. In addressing this anomaly, Clark (1988) suggested that panic patients might nevertheless monitor, detect, and catastro...

Table of contents

  1. Cover
  2. Half Title
  3. Title Page
  4. Copyright Page
  5. Table of Contents
  6. Preface
  7. PART I: CONCEPTUAL FOUNDATIONS
  8. PART II: PSYCHOMETRIC FOUNDATIONS
  9. PART III: NEW RESEARCH ON BASIC MECHANISMS: CAUSES AND CONSEQUENCES OF ANXIETY SENSITIVITY
  10. PART IV: NEW DIRECTIONS IN ANXIETY SENSITIVITY RESEARCH
  11. PART: CONCLUSIONS
  12. Author Index
  13. Subject Index