Genetic Ethics
eBook - ePub

Genetic Ethics

An Introduction

  1. English
  2. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  3. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Genetic Ethics

An Introduction

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

Colin Farrelly contemplates the various ethical and social quandaries raised by the genetic revolution. Recent biomedical advances such as genetic screening, gene therapy and genome editing might be used to promote equality of opportunity, reproductive freedom, healthy aging, and the prevention and treatment of disease. But these technologies also raise a host of ethical questions: Is the idea of "genetically engineering" humans a morally objectionable form of eugenics? Should parents undergoing IVF be permitted to screen embryos for the sex of their offspring? Would it be ethical to alter the rate at which humans age, greatly increasing longevity at a time when the human population is already at potentially unsustainable levels? Farrelly applies an original virtue ethics framework to assess these and other challenges posed by the genetic revolution. Chapters discuss virtue ethics in relation to eugenics, infectious and chronic disease, evolutionary biology, epigenetics, happiness, reproductive freedom and longevity. This fresh approach creates a roadmap for thinking ethically about technological progress that will be of practical use to ethicists and scientists for years to come. Accessible in tone and compellingly argued, this book is an ideal introduction for students of bioethics, applied ethics, biomedical sciences, and related courses in philosophy and life sciences.

Frequently asked questions

Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Yes, you can access Genetic Ethics by Colin Farrelly in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Sciences biologiques & Génétique et génomique. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Publisher
Polity
Year
2018
ISBN
9780745695075

1
Eugenics: Inherently Immoral?

I What is “eugenics”?

One major reason why critics oppose the prospect of human genetic technologies – whether it be screening technologies, such as pre-implantation genetic diagnosis (or PGD) for parents undergoing IVF, or genetic therapy or genome editing – is that they fear this will take humanity down the same path we visited in the past with unjust eugenics policies. The late nineteenth and first half of the twentieth century witnessed a number of unjust policies (e.g. sterilization of the “unfit”) and measures being pursued in the name of “improving the stock” of heredity. This dark episode of our history is what commonly comes to mind when one mentions the word “eugenics.”
“Francis Galton, a cousin of Darwin, invented the term [eugenics] and launched a movement to improve the human race, or at least to halt its perceived decline, through selective breeding” (Wikler 1999: 183). Eugenic-like concepts can be found in the ideas of the ancient Greeks. Plato, Aristotle’s mentor and teacher, proposed an ideal society that would pursue genetic engineering through selective breeding. The “just” Platonic society was one ruled by philosophers, who possessed knowledge and wisdom and who would govern for the common good. The rest of society, divided into the classes of soldiers and workers, would do the work for which they were best suited. Through censorship (e.g. of poetry) and education of the “guardian class,” as well as selective breeding among these class members, the best candidates for the philosopher class could be cultivated and perpetuated. Harmony between the classes could be maintained, argued Plato, if a noble lie was disseminated that some people were made of gold (the philosophers), others of silver and most of bronze. That way people would accept the position in society to which they were best suited.
Most elements of Plato’s ideal society will strike us as obviously misguided and authoritarian. Justice, for Plato, meant “doing what you are best suited to do.” This ancient construal of the moral virtue of justice was predicated upon the foundational premise that people are unequal. Plato’s noble lie that people were made from one of the three different elements of gold, silver or bronze clearly shows that his political theory contravened the idea of the moral equality of all persons.
A contemporary interpretation of the virtues of benevolence and justice must be compatible with the basic moral premise that all persons are moral equals and, as such, deserve to be treated, in the language of John Rawls (1971), as “separate persons” – persons worthy of respect, equal treatment and the protection of basic rights and opportunities.
How should we define “eugenics”? And what was morally wrong with the eugenic aspirations of Plato and the social movements of the late nineteenth and early twentieth century? Must everything considered “eugenic” necessarily be immoral? These are the questions we consider in this chapter. Virtue ethics is a useful moral framework for helping us understand why the eugenic movements of the past were wrong – namely, they epitomized moral and epistemic vice. But, perhaps just as importantly, virtue ethics can help illustrate why eugenics is not inherently immoral. Indeed, justly pursuing eugenic aspirations might actually be required by the virtues of beneficence, justice and the epistemic virtue of adaptability of intellect.
Some have argued that, while “eugenics talk” per se is not wrong, there is something wrong with using its emotive power as a means of circumventing people’s critical–rational faculties (Wilkinson 2008). I agree with this point, and the analysis developed in this chapter is one I hope will help reduce emotive reactions to the word “eugenics” and instead bring to the fore the moral and empirical sensibilities needed to determine whether a specific eugenic proposal or aspiration is just or unjust.
Many have defined eugenics in different ways. To help align our moral analysis of eugenics with the social application of virtue ethics developed in this book, I think the most useful way of defining eugenics is one which emphasizes it as a social movement. Bertrand Russell (1929: 254) provides the following definition of eugenics, one that defines it as a social movement: “The attempt to improve the biological character of a breed by deliberate methods adopted to that end.”
Humans have, since the domestication of animals and agriculture, sought to control and improve the breed of plants and animals they consume and rely upon for labour, sport and leisure. The case of “plant eugenics” is an easy example that satisfies Russell’s definition. Humans purposively intervene in the reproduction of plants, for example. Desired phenotypes, such as a beautiful flower or heatresistant crop, can be achieved through selective breeding or genetic engineering – “a process by which humans introduce or change DNA, RNA, or proteins in an organism to express a new trait or change the expression of an existing trait” (NASEM 2016: 5). The aim of such interventions is to improve the biological character of the plant, to improve its aesthetics, or to aid in feeding the world’s growing human population as well as livestock. And a variety of methods are available. These methods are not without controversy. Many critics of genetically modified crops oppose these technologies, either because they believe (contrary to evidence) eating such foods can be unsafe or because they fear they might cause significant harm to the environment.
Russell’s definition of eugenics is helpful because it draws attention to two distinct issues, each of which warrants closer consideration: (1) an end (i.e. improving the biological character of a breed) and (2) the means (“deliberate methods”) to achieve (1). Without more details, such as what the specific ends and means are, I believe eugenics is a morally neutral aspiration. Some ends are immoral and unjust, whereas other ends are morally laudable. Some means are immoral (even if the ends are morally laudable), and other means are reasonable and defensible. As I have said many times before, the devil really is in the details! I will illustrate this by considering some current public health practices that I believe could be considered “eugenic” but also morally obligatory. And then we will consider the historical eugenic policies that were clearly unjust.

II Folic acid, vaccinations and water fluoridation: eugenics?

Consider, for example, the Centers for Disease Control’s recommendation1 that woman of childbearing age (ages fifteen to forty-five) in the United States should consume 0.4mg of folic acid daily. It is recommended that all women in this age group, not only those planning to get pregnant, take folic acid supplements because nearly half of the pregnancies in the United States are unplanned (Finer and Zolna 2016). The goal of having folic acid be taken en masse is to prevent two common and serious birth defects – spina bifida and anencephaly. Is this recommendation by a public health agency an example of “eugenics”?
If eugenics is understood as an attempt to “improve the biological character of a breed” by “deliberate methods,” then the answer appears to be “yes.” It certainly is an interesting case to debate, and it is not obvious the answer is clearly “no” – that prescribing folic acid isn’t a case of eugenics. But the important point worth noting is that, even if the recommendation that women take folic acid is “eugenic,” it does not mean it is immoral or unjust. In fact, one might take the view, as many public health agencies do, that it is morally obligatory that this recommendation be made. Why? Because it could help prevent serious birth defects. This is beneficial to the prospective parents and their potential offspring. The virtue of benevolence prescribes that a virtuous polity aspire to prevent harm and disadvantage.
Why is the case of recommending folic acid not (at least obviously) morally problematic? I believe there are a few important factors worth emphasizing that are linked to moral and intellectual virtue. Firstly, the CDC simply recommends women take folic acid. It is not something that is legally obligatory. Women of childbearing age in the United States are not compelled, under threat of a fine or imprisonment or public shaming, to take folic acid. To go that far would be to contravene the virtue of justice as it would impose unfair burdens on women. Reducing birth defects is important, but it should not be pursued by placing unfair burdens on women of childbearing age.
Secondly, there is a sound empirical basis for thinking that taking folic acid is linked to the desired objective – namely, reducing serious birth defects. And as such the measure is an example of epistemic virtue rather than vice. The recommended dosage, along with its effectiveness and any potential adverse side-effects, has been extensively studied and the case for prescribing folic acid found to be supported. The CDC does not make the recommendation it does simply on “a hunch” or because it wants to increase the monetary revenue of the pharmaceutical companies producing folic acid.
Thirdly, the desired goal in this case is a morally laudable one – reducing the prevalence of serious birth defects. Such an aspiration is compatible with the virtue of benevolence, which instructs us to prevent harm and disadvantage when possible and reasonable to do so. So invoking moral and epistemic virtues can help us understand why the CDC’s recommendation is not objectionable. Indeed, a strong case can be made for arguing that it is morally obligatory. It simply encourages women of childbearing age to undertake the minor burden of the daily consumption of a pharmaceutical that could promote the health of her offspring, whether it was a planned or unplanned pregnancy. But what about the unjust eugenic policies of the past? They exemplified, I shall argue shortly, both moral and epistemic vice (not virtue).
Before turning to past eugenic policies, let us consider a second contemporary public health example – vaccinations. Children in developed countries are protected from many infectious diseases that kill children in less developed countries because the government can afford, and actively pursues, nationwide initiatives of vaccines to reduce the odds of an outbreak of vaccine-preventable diseases such as pertussis, mumps and measles. Such an aspiration certainly seems to fit Russell’s first condition for something to count as “eugenics” – it seeks to improve our biological character by making us less susceptible to infectious disease.
And deliberate methods are adopted to try to realize this aim. For example, in the United States there are state laws that require vaccinations for schoolchildren and children in day-care facilities. So healthy children are required to receive a medical intervention that is neither 100 percent effective nor 100 percent safe.2 Vaccinations have some risks of harm, and side-effects may include mild problems such as a low-grade fever or more serious complications (these are very rare). However, the overall risks are very small compared with the risks all children would face without vaccinations. And this is why vaccinations are such an important part of public health initiatives. The benefits of “herd immunity” – achieved when a sizeable portion of the population is immunized, protecting most of its members from the disease – far outweigh the costs and risks associated with vaccinations.
Are state-sponsored vaccination initiatives such as those pursued in the United States “eugenics”? Again, I think one could persuasively argue, “yeah, they are!” Critics often make precisely this point to try to weaken support for vaccination programs. But just because it is eugenics does not mean it is morally objectionable. Such programs seek to improve the biological character of children by enhancing their immune system so they are less vulnerable to infectious disease. We do not take the view that the biology humans have inherited from the process of evolution by natural selection is “good enough,” and that we should just tolerate higher rates of infant and child mortality rather than tamper with our “natural” biology. Instead, we pursue the goal of improving the health of the population by mandating that healthy individuals be subjected to medical interventions that may not be 100 percent safe or 100 percent effective. But, just because vaccination programs are “eugenic,” that does not mean they are immoral or unjust. In fact, the provision and (reasonable) enforcement of vaccinations can be considered morally obligatory (not simply morally permissible). Labelling something “eugenics” does not tell us much about the moral character of the practice in question. More details are required – namely, whether the eugenic policy is one that violates moral and epistemic virtue.
One last contemporary public health measure which seeks to “improve the bi...

Table of contents

  1. Cover
  2. Dedication
  3. Copyright
  4. Introduction
  5. 1 Eugenics: Inherently Immoral?
  6. 2 The Genetic Revolution: A Snapshot
  7. 3 Disease
  8. 4 Epigenetics
  9. 5 Reproductive Freedom
  10. 6 Aging Research and Longevity
  11. 7 Happiness, Memory and Behaviour
  12. Conclusion
  13. References
  14. Index
  15. End User License Agreement