Critique of Rights
eBook - ePub

Critique of Rights

  1. English
  2. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  3. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub
Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

Modern political revolutions since the 18th century have swept away traditional systems of domination by declaring that 'all men are created equal'. This declaration of equal rights is a fundamental political act – it is the political act in which the political community creates itself in relation to traditional systems of domination. But because it was generally assumed that the subject of these rights is the individual human being, the political community was subordinated to the individual. Marx discerned, rightly, that this was the paradox at the heart of the declaration of the rights of man. But while Marx was right to highlight this paradox, his proposed solution does not provide us with a sound basis for overcoming it. In this major new work, Christoph Menke adopts a different approach: he argues that we can address and overcome this paradox only by embarking on a fundamental inquiry into the nature of rights. Rights are a specific configuration of normativity: to have a right is to have a justified and binding claim. But with the equal rights declared by modern revolutions, rights assumed a particular form: the normative claim to equality was combined with an assumption about the factual conditions of social life. In this conception, society is the realm of private individuals pursuing their interests, and private interests are therefore seen as the natural basis for politics – what Menke calls 'the naturalization of the social'. By laying bare this conception which lies at the basis of political literalism and modern law, Menke is able to criticize and move beyond it, opening up a new way of understanding rights that no longer involves the disempowering of the political community. This radical critique of rights and of modern law is a major contribution to critical theory and legal theory and it will be of great interest to students and scholars in social and political theory, philosophy and law.

Frequently asked questions

Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Yes, you can access Critique of Rights by Christoph Menke, Christopher Turner in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Philosophy & Political Philosophy. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Publisher
Polity
Year
2020
ISBN
9781509520428

Part I
History: The Legalization of the Natural

Here we find ourselves in the “Copernican” moment of the history of the science of law, at the boundary between two worlds. A new social order is born, whose nucleus will become an individual right that is developed entirely from the concept of potestas, elevated to the dignity of a right.1
Modern legal theory and philosophy of law were the first to speak of rights that belong to the individual and which the individual can exercise for his or her own ends. For this reason, rights here are also first characterized as a person’s property, endowment, or capacity. It is only at this point that talk of “subjective” or “individual” rights could flourish. At the same time, rights are an essential way of formally defining private or civil law. Rights are primarily defined as claims that enable one person to impose an obligation on another person. The form of rights is therefore as old as the institution of civil law: they have existed ever since there were contractually regulated exchange relations. Both of these observations must be borne in mind at the same time. Together, they define the historicity of rights: rights are a form that can only be understood in historical terms.
We are concerned with the modern form of rights. This modern form cannot be understood by merely considering the continual formulations expressed by civil law regarding the normativity of exchange relationships that, beyond mere family arrangements, pervade all societies: the modern form of rights alters social exchange relationships so fundamentally that no concept of their normative regulation – obligation, freedom, equality, authority [Herrschaft] – is able to retain its traditional meaning. Nor can the modern form of rights be understood by attempting to derive it directly from the basic concept of modernity’s normative order, from the concept of the self-determining, autonomous subject: the modern form of rights does not exist because there are autonomous subjects, but autonomous subjects exist because the modern form of rights does. The modern form of rights results from a radical transformation of law. This transformation is radical because it concerns the meaning of law. With the modern form of rights, the concept of law, indeed the concept of normativity, acquires a new, fundamentally different meaning. The transformation in the conception of rights, which were traditionally expressed in terms of private law, thus does not remain restricted to this domain: “law” as such thereby comes to mean something else, and hence rights in their modern form only exist beyond private law.
A radical transformation of law takes place in the modern form of rights. The de-moralization [Entsittlichung] of law expresses this in negative terms: traditionally, law is the moral or rational order of the fair share in which each receives his or her own – his or her right. The modern administration of rights, however, must be defined in positive terms. It consists in the reconfiguration of the basic relation between the legal and the pre- or extra-legal, between norm and nature. In the modern form of rights, law becomes the process of juridification: rights are the mechanisms of an incessant legalization of the natural.

Notes

  1. 1. Michel Villey, La formation de la pensée juridique moderne, ed. by Stéphane Rials (Paris: Quadrige/PUF, 2006), 267.

1
A PHILOSOPHICAL HISTORY OF RIGHT’S FORM

Historians debate who should be regarded as the first author responsible for formulating the new – contemporary or modern – way of talking about a right as a person’s “power” [Macht]. In a series of influential essays, the legal historian Michel Villey maintains that William of Ockham was the first to have systematically understood a right in this manner. Ockham thus claims that:
a right of using is a licit power [potestas licita] of using an external thing of which one ought not be deprived against one’s will, without one’s own fault and without reasonable cause, and if one has been deprived, one can call the depriver into court.1
Lordship [dominium] is a principal human power of laying claim to and defending some temporal thing in a human court. “Human power” separates this lordship from the divine lordship.2
Villey’s critics have cast doubt on whether these formulations by Ockham already amount to a break with tradition – something which is only supposed to have occurred with later authors.3 At the same time, these critics have pointed out that similar formulations can already be found in “men who rediscovered the Digest and created the medieval science of Roman law.”4 However we date this break, though, it is undeniable that a distinction was established in the ideologically formative phase of modernity, between medieval nominalism, late scholasticism, and rational natural law. Indeed, Thomas Hobbes already invokes this terminological distinction as a frequently overlooked and yet obvious conceptual fact. Reviewing its history two hundred years later, Friedrich Carl von Savigny again cites it as a common, self-evident insight.
This distinction involves two different meanings of the term “right” [Recht]: the difference between right [Recht] as a justified or prevalent regime of laws and a right [Recht] as a person’s claim. In explaining the title of his The Rights of War and Peace, Hugo Grotius formulates this distinction as follows:
For Right in this Place signifies meerly that which is just, and that too rather in a negative than a positive Sense
. There is another signification of the word right, different from this, but yet arising from it, which relates directly to the person. In which sense, right is a moral quality annexed to the person, justly entitling him to possess some particular privilege, or to perform some particular act [C.M. - qualitas moralis personae competens ad aliquid juste habendum vel agendum]. This right is annexed to the person.5
Francisco Suárez explains the two “different meanings of the term ‘right’” in a similar way:
Sometimes “right” means an ethical claim [C.M. – moralem facultatem] to a thing or the right to a thing, whether we are dealing with an actual right of ownership or merely with the right to share in something. Right, in this sense, is the proper object of justice
. But “right” also characterizes law, which is a norm for ethically good action and which establishes a certain consistency in things. In this sense 
, “right” coincides with “law.” To put this concisely, we can call the first meaning “useful right” [ius utile] and the other meaning “ethical right” [ius honestum], or the first meaning could be called “real right” [reale] and the second meaning “lawful right” or “legal norm” [legale].6
Hobbes draws on a terminological distinction between law and right to capture the same conceptual difference7 – a distinction that Hobbes introduces as a translation of the Roman distinction of lex and ius, getting to the heart of the decisive contrast, for him, between right as binding law and a right as freedom:
For though they that speak of this subject use to confound Jus and Lex, Right and Law, yet they ought to be distinguished, because RIGHT consiste...

Table of contents

  1. Cover
  2. Front Matter
  3. Marx’s Puzzle
  4. Part I History: The Legalization of the Natural
  5. Part II Ontology: The Materialism of Form
  6. Part III Critique: The Authorization of One’s Own
  7. Part IV Revolution: The Dialectic of Judgment
  8. Law and Violence
  9. Index
  10. End User License Agreement