The Economy as a System of Power
eBook - ePub

The Economy as a System of Power

Corporate Powers

  1. 287 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

The Economy as a System of Power

Corporate Powers

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

This collection brings together important materials concerning the study of the economy as a system of power, offering a sample of positions taken by contributors to the Journal of Economic Issues in response to the perceived problems of the social control of corporate power.

Frequently asked questions

Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Yes, you can access The Economy as a System of Power by Warren Samuels in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Business & Business General. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Publisher
Routledge
Year
2017
ISBN
9781351483278
Edition
1
Part 1
The Economy as a System of Power
Introduction
The materials in this section examine capitalism as a system of power, the role of power in the allocation of resources and social valuation, the operation of power through institutions (including the market), and the role of power in the choice of technology.
The article by Philip Klein establishes certain fundamental themes. The economy not only allocates resources but also is a mode of valuation. The meaning of political economy must be rendered in terms of problems of valuation. Markets allocate resources within and give effect to institutions. Institutions and institutional forces shape values, priorities, and wants. The economy includes both market and institutions such that values are endogenously generated in the economy, in part through institutions, in part through the market mechanism. The economy thus broadly considered shapes and channels human choice and aggregate individual values, which are themselves socially formed. Conflict, process, and change, not equilibrium, characterize institutional evolution and the valuation process. Income distribution, inseparable from the resource allocation to which it gives rise, is one facet of political economy and one means through which choice and power are exercised. In sum, the economic valuation process includes the market and the processes—institutions, power—through which is determined whose private and social values count. For this an analytical political economy is necessary.
James Street’s article considers certain contributions to the theory of economic development. He focuses on the process of development as being, first, a product of the interaction of power structure and orientations of economic and social policy and, second, the pressure of technology against the inertia of traditional modes of organized behavior.1 Whether articulated in terms of education being functional and technical versus ornamental, or technology as requiring and generating new modes of social organization and distinctive ways of thinking and acting, economic development connotes revolutionary transformations in patterns of life and the relative power of groups and interests. The actual course of development is thus a partial function of political and cultural mechanisms of socioeconomic decision making, or power.
Thomas R. De Gregori analyzes how the operation of markets is a function of normative inputs into the market, including the power structure. Problems given definition by narrow market economics thus are limited (perhaps by design) in the analysis and policies which may be applied to or derived from them. Policy in the real world is limited by the power structure and ideas rationalizing market solutions, at the same time that market economics and the status quo system constrain and channel the substance of needs and wants.
Benjamin Ward finds several distinctive features of contemporary capitalism, among them: the changing pattern of dependence of the individual upon the behavior, choices, and approval of others; a changing pattern of power, deliberative manipulation, awareness of manipulation, and deliberative decision making; and greater international political and economic interdependence. This means a changing pattern of individual autonomy and exposure to others in a dynamic and kaleidoscopic system of power. Ward finds great similarities, some differences, and great diversity among the capitalist economies. For example, he sees different patterns of risk assumption and socialization, and different degrees of deep individual involvement with large bureaucracies as important descriptive and normative variables.
Seymour Melman presents the subtle argument that society is powerfully affected by technology, but man and society are not merely its creatures. Technology is man-made and changeable; especially, technology is given varying characteristics by machine builders and designers. It is influenced by design criteria, and these reflect the structure of power, and by social structure and the working rules of those who decide on technology. Social relations are imprinted upon technology or, more properly, on choice of technology, and these reflect the structure of power. Technology, according to Melman, is an array of alternatives, and it is on the basis of power that one alternative is chosen as optimal rather than another. Melman takes as an example the U.S. automotive industry and argues that technology in automobile design, in the physical means of production, and in the organization and integration of work and decision making all reflect the structure of power in that industry. Technology, in short, is a function of choice, which depends upon the criteria adopted, which is a function of power structure. Once again, whose interests count depends upon the power structure.
In the final article in this section, Kenneth Parsons explores the emergence of the market economy as a function of complex and deep institutional transformation. The institutional order, he argues, is fundamental to the organization and performance of the market economy, and the modem economic system rests upon the evolving foundations of social, political, and public order. In particular, the evolution of the property system has been a matter of continuing compromise of interests, tentatively erected into working rules, subject to alteration, governing whose interests are to count. In the process, the legal system has changed from a bastion of centralized absolute prerogative to an arena and mode of conflict resolution, socioeconomic change, and alteration of the working rules governing the weighting of interests. These are aspects of the joint evolution of the elements of the system of order, in general the evolution of power and of checks upon power, and the historical development of the meaning of the differentiation between private and public. Parsons underscores the energizing role of private property, characterizes the meaning of modernization, and applies his analysis to the problems of agricultural development.
Economics:
Allocation or Valuation?
Philip A. Klein
“Whether or not it continues to be a science of price, economics must be a science of value.”
Clarence E. Ayres
Theory of Economic Progress
Among the social sciences, economics long has suffered from a superiority complex. The economist’s view of his field has been of a discipline that was rigorous and precise, with an advanced and pragmatic methodology leading to a highly developed theoretical structure. All this left far behind the imprecise and murky theoretical strivings of political scientists, sociologists, anthropologists, and historians.
The promised land which economic analysis made possible was known as equilibrium.1 What sociologist or political scientist or anthropologist could offer any piece of analytical apparatus which for sheer beauty, precision, and logic could equal it? True, psychologists kept insisting that the behavioral assumptions of conventional economic theory—maximizing behavior, hedonism, rationality—all the characteristics of “Economic Man” which economics always has relied on for convenience, were fatally oversimplified. But economists mostly have ignored the complaints of psychologists (who after all had problems of their own). Moreover, the psychologists were only too willing to follow the economist down the quantitative primrose path. Both disciplines once worried about their ancient roots in philosophy and could never quite rid themselves of the nagging suspicion that questions of subjective valuation could not be eliminated entirely so as to render each a 100 percent pure science. Both embraced mathematics as the true methodological Messiah come at last.2 Together economists and psychologists measured all visibly quantifiable variables, developed models for all problems, and achieved intellectual orgasm through the contemplation of the possibilities of the electronic computer. By enshrining quantification, they believed they had set a standard of scientific excellence sufficiently ahead of their laggardly sister social sciences to enable them to continue virtually indefinitely to play the role of superego to the lowly id of sociology or history.
Without in any way demeaning the very real accomplishments of quantitative procedures in advancing knowledge in critical areas, I should like to suggest that at least in the case of economics, schizophrenia always has been latent in the discipline and has been kept that way only by sweeping under the rug important problems which increasingly have crept out to disturb the neat world of economist and econometrician alike. We can cope with any number of variables in ever more elaborate models, but we cannot cope with underlying questions of direction and meaning, of goals and objectives for the system. The excessive preoccupation with tools with which to cope with problems at best comprising a small corner of economics, and the obsessive need to believe these tools coped with the heart of economics, long has characterized the discipline. Facing up to this obsession involves the fundamental question of whether economics is a science of allocation or a science of valuation. For most of its existence economics has managed to equate the two, and there is a long and bloody literary road devoted to establishing that economics as a “science of price” thereby was coping with all the value problems with which it need legitimately concern itself.
Economics as a Science of Allocation
The central core of economic theory—at least microeconomic theory—was spelled out by Adam Smith and elaborated upon by the well-known nineteenth-century mainstream economists. The culmination was its restatement by Alfred Marshall, who not insignificantly changed the name of the descipline from political economy to economics. The profound changes of the past eighty years have left remarkably untouched much of the field which Marshall defined as “a study of mankind in the ordinary business of life; it examines that part of individual and social action which is most closely connected with the attainment and with the use of the material requisites of wellbeing.”3 Marshall added that economics “concerns itself chiefly with those motives which affect most powerfully and most steadily man’s conduct in the business part of his life.”4 The latter is a far narrower perspective and considerably closer to what in fact Marshall’s Principles dealt with. It was a critical reinforcement to the continued confusion between economics as allocation and economics as valuation.
Marshall’s emphasis on materialism subsequently was questioned, for example, by Lionel Robbins, who wondered how a science concerned exclusively with the material could determine the wage rates for opera stars or orchestra conductors whose productivity is not quite so easily viewed as the more concretely material output of ditchdiggers, carpenters, and others among the myriad toilers in the economic vineyards. Robbins concluded that Marshall’s materialism was a “pseudo-materialism”5 and that what was really at the heart of economics was not materialism but allocation. Robbins then defined the field in the way which is customarily utilized to this day: “Economics is the science which studies human behaviour as a relationship between ends and scarce means which have alternative uses.”6 Such a formulation extricated economists from the materialism quagmire; by adding to this the deceptively simple assumption that the allocation process as carried out through the use of prices in the market disposed of all the ends and scarce means that the proper study of economics need embrace, economists thought they were home free.7 The pricing process was assumed to be the vehicle by which the economic system expressed all the allocating priorities of concern to the economist. Thus price became, if it had not always been, the only measure of value with which economics had to concern itself.
Robbins himself reached this conclusion unequivocably by saying that the significance of economic science lay in the fact that “when we are faced with a choice between ultimates, it enables us to choose with a full awareness of the implications of what we are choosing.” But he was very careful to add that “it is incapable of deciding between the desirability of different ends. It is fundamentally distinct from Ethics.”8 But even if the distinction between economics and ethics were accepted, the discipline must provide (if it is to permit us to choose with the “full awareness of the implications of our choice”) mechanisms by which such “full awareness” choice can be made. The market alone cannot fill that bill in a modern industrial economy. Allocation and valuation are indeed different, and a discipline concerned only with the former can never permit “fully aware” choices to be made.
Those who view economics as a science of allocation customarily have argued that all participants in the economic process get their “values” from wherever they get them, that in fact societal values are of no concern to the economist. Thus all the economist need do is pontificate: “If an individual chooses to allocate his income in Direction A he must forego Direction B.” “To achieve certain objectives, here is the most efficient way for society to achieve them, and here is what must be foregone in the process.” Consequently, generations of economics students were taught that economics is not concerned with questions of “ought” but only with questions of “is.” Economics as a science was not normative but positive.9 Thus economics was viewed as the administrator of social options, in charge of calculating costs and predicting results, but without any normative participation in the process. The economist qua economist occupied a role in which normative judgments definitionally had no place. Only the economist qua citizen was permitted to be filled with the minimal requisite quantities of passion, prejudice, and “subjective valuation” that reside in the breast of other mere mortals.
This view of economics had some convenient side effects. For one, it enabled economic theory to blind itself to the implicit subjective valuations (previously alluded to) of what it did in the guise of pursuit of the scientific method, rigor, and precision. It therefore enabled economics to emulate the physical sciences and thus led to the coronation of equilibrium as normatively “good” in economics because in physics, from whence it came, it was “natural.” If Keynes’s notion of underemployment equilibrium represented a severe jolt to this notion, in microeconomics it survived because equilibrium prices led to market clearing, which was definitionally good. Finally, equilibrium could be viewed as an end in itself because the continued assumption that Adam Smith’s Invisible Hand (developed for atomistic competition) could be appropriately if only approximately attached to emergent prices in actual markets rationalized away any lurking doubts about how economics disposed of the value problem. Individual selfishness was transmogrified into a process optimizing social welfare, and emergent prices did indeed express the values of society in the only way that need concern the economist.
Economics as a Science of Valuation
The simple world of the classical economist, familiar to all economists, was orderly and attractive, but unrelated to much of the economic reality even of its own time. The history of economics has shown...

Table of contents

  1. Cover
  2. Half Title
  3. Title Page
  4. Copyright Page
  5. Table of Contents
  6. Foreword
  7. Introduction
  8. Part 1. The Economy as a System of Power
  9. Part 2. The Corporate System
  10. Part 3. Power and the Interrelations Between Legal and Economic Processes