Methodology Of Frontal And Executive Function
eBook - ePub

Methodology Of Frontal And Executive Function

  1. 256 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Methodology Of Frontal And Executive Function

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

This volume reflects the pressure to develop useful models and methodologies to study executive behaviour - the ability to update information in working memory in order to control selective attention to formulate plans of action and to monitor their efficient execution. Many models are based on the concept of a single "central executive" that manges these functions; others propose a number of independent "working memory systems" that each serve one task or activity but not others.; This book is a collection of essays by active researchers who discuss their own work on the definition of "executive" or "controlled" behaviours, and on the relation of these behaviours to specific areas of the frontal cortex. The papers are particularly concerned with logical difficulties that arise in defining these functions that lead, in turn, to methodological difficulties in studying them. In particular, they discuss such problems as the low test-re-test reliability of tasks that have been used to define and explore "executive" behaviours, the limited validity of these tasks in predicting performance deficits, the poor localization of the changes observed with respect to underlying brain function, and the relation of performance on these tasks to individual difference in performance on measures of "global" or "general" intellectual ability such as Spearman's 1927 gf.; The authors discuss their own research on the relations between cognitive function and neuropsychology, on changes in executive competence in conditions such as closed head injuries or dementias that may diffusely affect the whole brain, and on changes in executive function in normal old age.

Frequently asked questions

Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Yes, you can access Methodology Of Frontal And Executive Function by Patrick Rabbitt in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Psychology & History & Theory in Psychology. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Publisher
Routledge
Year
2004
ISBN
9781135472023
Edition
1

CHAPTER ONE
Introduction: Methodologies and Models in the
Study of Executive Function

Patrick Rabbitt Age and Cognitive Performance Research Centre,
University of Manchester, U.K.


A common theme of all contributors to this book is that, because tests of executive function have low test-retest reliability and uncertain validity, it has been hard to draw clear empirical distinctions between “executive” and “non-executive” tasks. It has also proved difficult to relate particular behaviours which have become regarded as being paradigmatic exemplars of “executive” function to specific neuroanatomical areas or neurophysiological systems. We argue that some of these difficulties occur because executive behaviour has been discussed, simultaneously, at more than one level of description. Accounts of purposeful and conscious behaviour, in the language of everyday subjective experience, map uneasily onto clinical taxonomies of the modes of dysexecutive function observed in brain-damaged patients. Performance indices empirically measured in laboratory tasks are often treated as being directly equivalent to the hypothetical system performance characteristics specified in functional models of working memory and selective attention. As a result, it has passed unrecognised that hypothetical components of “executive behaviour,” such as “inhibition,” “planning,” “monitoring” and “control” which are, in fact, simply descriptions of task demands, may have very poor construct validity because although these demands appear logically different they can be met by identical production system architectures. Confusions have also arisen because both task performance indices and system performance characteristics have been treated as equivalent to statistical constructs, derived to explain individual differ ences in performance on intelligence tests, such as Spearman’s (1927) index gf (see review by Rabbitt, 1996).
Individually and collectively, the contributions to this book show why it is unsurprising that all empirical psychologists find it very difficult and some philosophers (Fodor, 1983) think it impossible to give a satisfactory functional account of the central executive system (CE). Classical descriptions of executive impairment associated with prefrontal lesions have immediacy and richness, and are strikingly similar to definitions of “willed” “purposeful” or “voluntary” behaviour that have preoccupied philosophers and theologians for more than two millennia. For example, contemporary catalogues of the functions of the hypothetical “central executive” are strikingly similar to the formal criteria for commission of mortal sin given by Roman Catholic theologians: Beasts are soulless automata, and so always blameless. Humans also do not transgress while performing even very complex vile acts, provided that they do so involuntarily and automatically without conscious awareness of themselves as perpetrating agents. The minimal functional processes involved in the commission of a mortal sin are awareness of the self as the intending perpetrator of the act; recognition of the unpleasant implications of the act for others by possession of a theory of mind; recognition of its moral repulsiveness by possession of a theory of the mind of God; an ability simultaneously to represent alternative acts and their possible outcomes in working memory in order efficiently to choose between them; conscious formulation of a well-articulated plan to perform the act successfully; self-initiation and execution of sequences of appropriate actions to consummate this plan during which recognition of personal culpability is maintained by continuous monitoring; recognition of attainment of the vile goal state and an intention to use what has been learned in its pursuit to perform it again if opportunity occurs.
Clearly only the central executive (CE) can sin. Do we yet have functional models that improve on this already comprehensive theological description?
Both theologians and neuropsychologists seem to be describing the same ghost, and it is natural that a class of investigators whom Burgess (this book) labels “ultra-cognitive neuropsychologists” should try to deduce its properties from the results of selective damage to the machine that it haunts. An impressive, but unlikely, discovery would be that whenever a particular, functionally circumscribed, brain system is damaged the patient becomes capable only of brutish automaticity. An even more interesting finding would be that different lesions disable one, but not others, of a set of logically distinct and tightly specifiable functions such as “planning,” “sequence initiation,” “monitoring” or “inhibition of alternative responses.” This would reveal the “double disassociations” of effects prized by “ultra-cognitivists.” Unfortunately all the chapters in this collection, and a voluminous background literature excellently reviewed by Fuster (1989), Reitan & Wolfson (1994) and others, point out that attempts to relate any of the capabilities that are agreed to be most characteristic of “executive” behaviour to particular brain systems or even to diffuse changes in volume of brain tissue have been unsuccessful (see especially Foster et al. this book). Failures to offer convincing neurophysiological descriptions of the bases of most complex cognitive skills may, as Burgess (this book) clearly anticipates, sap our faith in the methodology of “ultra-cognitive neuropsychology.” It has been suggested that some of these difficulties may be avoided if the problem is restructured as a search for empirical distinctions between “executive” and “dysexecutive” behaviours and the question of where, or what, their neurophysiological bases may be is deliberately, and indefinitely, postponed (e.g. Baddeley & Wilson, 1988). While this ploy frees us to carry out behavioural experiments without worrying about how their results bear on what we know about the brain, it also deprives us of an important source of evidence against which to check the plausibility of our models. In the difficult task of understanding executive function we need all the help that neuropsychology can offer.
Nevertheless, attempts to distinguish behaviourally between “executive” (E) and “non-executive” (NE) functions at least force us to move beyond the richly allusive language of everyday subjective experience and try to develop a functional taxonomy distinguishing performances, skills, or behaviours that are characteristic of executive function from those that are not. Collectively, our contributors generate an exhaustive list:
First, executive control is necessary to deal with novel tasks that require us to formulate a goal, to plan, and to choose between alternative sequences of behaviour to reach this goal, to compare these plans in respect of their relative probabilities of success and their relative efficiency in attaining the chosen goal, to initiate the plan selected and to carry it through, amending it as necessary, until it is successful or until impending failure is recognised. It is crucial to note that this prospectus does not merely boil down to a statement that executively controlled behaviour is much more complex than NE behaviour. Even choices between very complex behaviour sequences (aka plans) can be carried out “automatically” under NE control. Examples of this might be skilled drivers negotiating complex traffic while carrying on non-trivial conversations, or chess grand masters rapidly selecting among extremely difficult lines of play by recognising generically familiar positions during “lightning chess” tournaments. The key distinction seems to be between situations in which a person must, for the first time, recognise, evaluate, and choose among a variety of alternative options and those in which a single effective behaviour sequence, which has been previously identified, and instantiated by practice, is run off without the need to propose and evaluate alternatives.
In contrast to E behaviour, NE behaviour tends to be initiated by, and to continue automatically in response to, changes in environmental input. A possible way to envisage this is that even very complex NE behaviours are externally driven and controlled by sequences of environmental events or by previously learned “plans” or “programs” held in long-term memory. In contrast, E behaviours can be initiated and controlled independently of environmental input, and can retain the adaptive flexibility to rescue plans even when the environment does not behave as anticipated and no guidance is available from previous experience.
It follows that, should the rules suddenly change, as in the Wisconsin Card-sorting Task or its variants, “executive” function will be necessary to appreciate from feedback that a change has occurred and to formulate and test new plans or rules until successful. Some authors stress that part of this process is the “inhibition” or “suppression” of previously used and so habitual rules in order to project, select, and use alternatives.
Second, a study reported by Burgess (this book) shows that deliberate retrieval of structured information from memory in order to answer a question or to elaborate a partial description may involve the conscious, and reportable, formation and prosecution of well-articulated memory “search plans.” Burgess points out that CE control is not only necessary to manage transactions with the external world but also with the “internal information environment” of long-term memory. Thus CE control extends beyond the current internal or external information environment to restructure interpretation of the past as well as to attempt active control of the future. Burgess’s excellent insight is timely because it allows us to distinguish between NE retrieval of information from memory in response to learned associations and environmental cues and active, “strategic” or “planned” memory search carried out under voluntary control. Closely related suggestions by Phillips (this book) are that individuals with inefficient executive function apparently generate categories of words by simple associations between successive items, or by empirically inscrutable random processes, while the better performance of individuals with intact executive function may be partly attributable to their discovery and use of memory search strategies. These suggestions of a strong link between CE control and efficiency of organised recall of material from memory are particularly interesting in view of Mayes’ and Daum’s (this book) neat demonstrations that lesions in prefrontal areas that are often associated with losses of executive function also impair learning, recall, and recognition. They raise the further question whether prefrontal lesions may impair strategic control of recall and recognition to a greater extent than do the lesions of the mediotemporal lobes and of the hippocampus and limbic system that are more usually associated with the “classic” amnesic syndrome. In this case lesions might disassociate strategic control of memory from memory efficiency.
Third, E functions are necessary to initiate new sequences of behaviour and also to interrupt other ongoing sequences of responses in order to do so. A logically related property is that they can suppress, or inhibit and replace, automatic and habitual responses with task-appropriate responses. E functions can also check involuntary perseveration by appropriately “switching” attention to new sources of information. In this sense “inhibition” of habitual responses in order to make other responses, or “switching” between one sequence of responses or one aspect of the environment and another, appear to be logically, and operationally, very similar concepts (see Lowe & Rabbit this volume, and Baddeley, Maylor, & Godden, in press). Whether by strategically switching attention from one source to another over time, or by simultaneously and strategically allocating attentional resources to more than one input, E processes control the allocation of attention, particularly in complex tasks in which a variety of different demands must be met simultaneously.
Fourth, E functions are necessary to prevent responses that are inappropriate in context. This rather poorly articulated aspect of dysexecutive function must be logically distinguished from the suppression of habitual or unnecessary responses. It seems first to have been documented by clinical observations of inappropriate social behaviour following frontal lesions. Such lapses of social judgment may perhaps have logical analogues in empirical findings, such as the increases in numbers of bizarre responses that patients with frontal lesions make to questions in the Shallice Cognitive Estimates Test (Shallice & Evans, 1978) and in reports, such as that by Parkin (this book) that older, and so potentially more “executively challenged,” individuals make markedly more false-positives in recognition memory experiments than do younger adults. It is hard to suggest any single, comprehensive description of the cause of these and similar lapses but “responding without taking all of the available information into consideration,” “responding without considering alternatives,” “responding on the basis of insufficient information” or “failing to monitor for plausibility” may all capture something that they have in common. It is also difficult to disassociate these ideas from findings such as Parkin’s of an increase in false-positives that may, generically, also be described as “loss of strategic control of memory.” Note also that these problems of response production can also be logically, if not functionally, distinguished from failures to monitor responses in order to detect whether they are “correct” or “wrong” in the sense that they have or have not succeeded in achieving a particular intention. They seem, rather, to be failures to judge when an intention, as well as the response in which it results, is implausible or unacceptable in a particular context.
Fifth, dual-task performance has become a test bed for exploration of functions of planning and control because the simultaneous performance of two tasks may require strategic allocation of attention and synchronisation of responses in order to service both. This may be achieved by rapidly switching from one task to the other and back again as their relative demands fluctuate over time, or by other forms of resource management such as are envisaged in models of “M space” (Case, 1992; Case & Sandieson, 1992) or quantified in terms of the index mu (see Baddeley, della Salla et al. this book). Simultaneous performance of two E tasks is seen as being especially demanding because, in effect, it may involve coping with all of the demands intrinsic to task 1 and task 2 and also, in addition, with the demand of strategically controlling allocation of attention between tasks. As many elegant experiments by Baddeley (1986) have shown, mutual interference between simultaneous tasks is particularly severe if they make simultaneous demands on the same sensory modality or representation system. In contrast, when two tasks are both under NE control, even if both are complex they may be simultaneously performed with less mutual interference and with less need for strategic scheduling of their conflicting demands. However, as recent work by Bourke, Duncan, and Nimmo-Smith (1993) suggests, there may always be some loss of efficiency in dual-task performance.
Sixth, while carrying out plans to cope with novel demands, E functions are necessary to monitor performance in order to detect and correct errors, to alter plans when it becomes clear that they are becoming unlikely to succeed, or to recognise opportunities for new and more desirable goals and to formulate, select among, initiate, and execute new plans to attain them. Even complex sequences of NE behaviours do not seem to be monitored at this level. This distinction requires elaboration because it has long been known that error correction in simple tasks such as serial choice reaction time is very fast and “automatic” (Rabbitt, 1968), so that continuous monitoring for discrepancies between intentions and acts does occur, but at speeds (e.g. < 40ms) which are much too fast to be attributable to “conscious”, or “executive” intervention. In contrast, E monitoring is envisaged as a higher level activity that not only detects when actions have not been completed as planned, but can also predict when failure is imminent, or an even more attractive goal may be missed, unless a plan, which is currently being carried out precisely as intended, can be rapidly changed.
Seventh, Manly and Robertson (this book) suggest that another characteristic of E control is that it can enable attention to be sustained continuously over long periods. Among other benefits, this allows prediction of outcomes of long, complex sequences of events. This property seems to have first been suggested by Wilkins and Shallice (1987). Perhaps an example of this property of E behaviour is Duncan’s (1995) clever demonstration that dysexecutive individuals show “goal neglect” in a novel task in which they are, at random intervals, signalled either to “switch” from one pattern of responding to another or to “stick” with the response pattern in which they are currently engaged. Another example might be the “lift” or “elevator” monitoring task, designed by Robertson and his associates, in which participants watch a changing display which signals a series of upward and downward movements of a hypothetical conveyor. By monitoring these changes patients have to identify the floor that the conveyor has currently reached. We have already discussed how E control is necessary to formulate plans. Manly and Robertson’s observations suggest that we should add to this the ability to hold intended sequences of actions in mind over long periods of time so as to carry them out as soon as appropriate circumstances occur. Another general description of such activities might be “r...

Table of contents

  1. COVER PAGE
  2. TITLE PAGE
  3. COPYRIGHT PAGE
  4. LIST OF CONTRIBUTORS
  5. CHAPTER ONE: INTRODUCTION: METHODOLOGIES AND MODELS IN THE STUDY OF EXECUTIVE FUNCTION
  6. CHAPTER TWO: COGNITIVE MODELS OF AGEING AND FRONTAL LOBE DEFICITS
  7. CHAPTER THREE: TESTING CENTRAL EXECUTIVE FUNCTIONING WITH A PENCIL-AND-PAPER TEST
  8. CHAPTER FOUR: THEORY AND METHODOLOGY IN EXECUTIVE FUNCTION RESEARCH
  9. CHAPTER FIVE: AGEING AND EXECUTIVE FUNCTIONS: A NEUROIMAGING PERSPECTIVE
  10. CHAPTER SIX: SUSTAINED ATTENTION AND THE FRONTAL LOBES
  11. CHAPTER SEVEN: HOW SPECIFIC ARE THE MEMORY AND OTHER COGNITIVE DEFICITS CAUSED BY FRONTAL LOBE LESIONS?
  12. CHAPTER EIGHT: NORMAL AGE-RELATED MEMORY LOSS AND ITS RELATION TO FRONTAL LOBE DYSFUNCTION
  13. CHAPTER NINE: DO “FRONTAL TESTS” MEASURE EXECUTIVE FUNCTION? ISSUES OF ASSESSMENT AND EVIDENCE FROM FLUENCY TESTS
  14. CHAPTER TEN: A NEURAL SYSTEMS APPROACH TO THE COGNITIVE PSYCHOLOGY OF AGEING USING THE CANTAB BATTERY
  15. CHAPTER ELEVEN: BEHAVIOURAL ASSESSMENT OF THE DYSEXECUTIVE SYNDROME