Piaget's Theory
eBook - ePub

Piaget's Theory

  1. 208 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub
Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

This book was first published in 1979. The authors' examinePiaget's Theory starting by considering and commenting on the kinds of question one must ask of a scientific theory. None of the questions demands an absolute answer. Theories are judged in some respects with reference to competing theories. In other respects they are judged against our sense of scientific progress. In subsequent chapters the authors' look at Piaget's theory in detail with such issues in mind. They also endeavour to locate Piaget's theory in the context of other views of intellectual development. In that section we focus on the issue we first nominated, that is the problem of making choices about the kinds of question to ask and the kinds of data to select.

Frequently asked questions

Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on ā€œCancel Subscriptionā€ - itā€™s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time youā€™ve paid for. Learn more here.
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlegoā€™s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan youā€™ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, weā€™ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Yes, you can access Piaget's Theory by Geoffrey Brown,Charles Desforges in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Psychology & History & Theory in Psychology. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Publisher
Routledge
Year
2013
ISBN
9781135661274
Edition
1

Chapter 1
Piaget and theories of development

As a prelude to evaluating Piaget's theory we raise some general issues about the problems of accounting for cognitive development, and contrast Piaget's stance on these issues with those adopted by other authorities.
Many of the differences between a newborn infant and a two-year-old child are obvious. The elder child is bigger, more mobile, less dependent, has a wide repertoire of physical skills, can communicate many of his needs, has tastes, opinions, attitudes, favourite people, remembers a range of facts, names, times and promises and responds in elaborate ways to approaches made to him by others. Despite his achievements, however, he is a social, emotional and intellectual novice when compared with a four-year-old. The theorist working in developmental psychology seeks to explain these dramatic, age related changes.
In this undertaking a number of perennial issues are met. If some account is to be given of the changes as development proceeds then it is necessary to have detailed and accurate descriptions of the achievements at certain reference points. This in turn entails making choices about which part of the child's extensive behavioural repertoire to describe since it is unlikely that any exhaustive description could be possible. Given these necessarily selective descriptions of developmental attainments the theorist then has to consider how development proceeds. Will the acquisition be seen as gradual accumulations of experience or as abruptly appearing achievements, and, as a related issue, are the attainments of the four-year-old qualitatively different from those of the two-year-old or are they simply quantitatively different? Is the four-year-old's language, for example, more of the same kind of language that the two-year-old exhibits or is the elder child in possession of a radically different mode of communication? A fourth problem in accounting for development requires that the theorist explain the differential role of innate and experiential factors and of their possible interactions. How far is the child's mode and level of intellectual functioning biologically determined at conception? How do particular life experiences interact with biological factors to enhance or limit the production of behaviours?
These problems of describing and accounting for developmental change are inter-related in complex ways. The selections made will not be random. The theorist will observe those specific behaviours which are felt to be most related to the problem he has in mind, and the conception of the problem will be informed by his stance on the nature/nurture debate, or on whether he conceives development to be a gradual and continuous accumulation of behavioural elements or a discontinuous, stepwise process of emergent functions. Of course the reverse process of influence is also true. Not only does our conception of development inform the kinds of data we select to solve problems of theory, the subsequent descriptions of behaviour in turn constrain our view of how development proceeds.
Put bluntly, the conception of a problem necessarily informs the selection of the data chosen as pertinent to the problem and selective and limited data necessarily constrain the subsequent view of the problem. In what follows, this point will be illustrated again and again. Whether, in the process of building theories of development, the above describes a vicious circle of self confirmation or a growing spiral of understanding, we set aside for the moment.

The nature of theory

In common usage, the term 'theory' has a number of more or less vague connotations. It may imply a hunch, 'my theory is the butler did it' means that the story so far leads me to believe that the butler is the most likely culprit of some crime. Speculations less directly linked to facts are often termed 'theories'. We see a friend getting fatter and 'theorise' or 'speculate' or 'suspect' that they are anxious, because we know from past experience that this friend eats a lot when snowed under with work and we take this excess eating to be a consequence of anxiety. This dual role of summarising and accounting for facts is entailed in the word 'theory' both in its common sense and formal-scientific usage. Equally, common sense distinguishes between good and bad theory or speculation. Good speculation is, quite simply, speculation which 'comes true'. Scientific theory is similarly demanding. Good theory is theory from which accurate predictions and adequate explanations can be made. One final distinction made in common usage is between promising theory and unpromising theory. There are lines of argument or procedures for making predictions about winning on a fruit machine or betting on horses which, whilst in the short term are not producing satisfying outcomes, none the less look sufficiently worthwhile to polish, amend slightly or persevere with. That is, there are theories which, for more or less vague reasons, we go along with because we believe they can be improved. Scientists also recognise that new theories may be temporarily unsatisfactory in terms of predictive and explanatory capacity but if, for other reasons, the theory looks promising, then it may be subjected to rigorous procedures of amendment.
A scientific theory is a conceptual tool used to describe and predict efficiently, and explain adequately, a given set of phenomena. The set of phenomena may be extremely limited or highly complex. We can contrast, for example, the problem of describing the increase in children's height with age against that of describing the increase in intellectual competence with age. Height is readily conceptualised and can be represented by a single quantity on a single scale. But what constitutes 'intellectual competence' and how is it to be represented?
If describing a set of phenomena is daunting, the question of 'adequately explaining' the set is even more so since theorists must offer not only a definition and representation of the phenomena but also make those statements that allow the description to be tested as an explanation. In science such tests tend to require empirical work. Thus a scientific theory takes the form of a proposition or set of propositions from which empirically testable hypotheses can be deduced.

Some problems in building and evaluating scientific theories

A necessary preliminary to appraising a theory critically is the identification of a set of criteria by which theories may be judged. Building and evaluating theories entail much the same kind of issue and procedure. A good theory is a growing theory; it has an ever extending range of application. Theories rest on data and data are generated by research. Thus a theory must be a rich source of hypotheses. These hypotheses must not be vague or indicate ambiguous outcomes; they must be empirically testable, i.e. potentially falsifiable. A good theory is usable, therefore it must be as parsimonious in terminology as is consistent with the power to explain. Testability entails that a good theory be internally consistent. For example, the definition of each term or relationship must not be a contradiction of the definition of any other term or relationship. These criteria, breadth of application, testability, parsimony, internal consistency and richness as a source of hypotheses, are each complex in themselves and related to each other. Below we expand on some of them.
The matter of judging the quality and progress of scientific theory is complex. Our discussion is necessarily brief and points only to the kinds of ideas which have guided our thinking on Piaget's theory. For more extensive discussions see Keat and Urry, 1975; Koch, 1959, 1974; Kuhn, 1970; and Lakatos and Musgrave, 1970.

Breadth of application

A theory may apply to a very limited set of data or it may be more general. Skinner's account of operant conditioning applied in the first instance to the behaviour of pigeons in specially constructed boxes but has since been used to give accounts of wide ranges of animals and human behaviour including the acquisition of language. This growth in the breadth of application of a theory is a manifestation of the generality of the concepts identified as fundamental. The concept of reinforcement, for example, has been shown by Skinner and his colleagues to be of quite general application. The generality of concepts cannot be judged in advance of their use. As a consequence, the more a theoretical proposition is applied and the more it seems to be sustained as useful, the more we assign it general significance.
There are no yardsticks for judging 'breadth of application.

Testability

We have noted that we demand of a scientific theory that it can be used to generate predictions. Our degree of confidence in the validity of the theory is proportional to the degree to which these predictions are testable, i.e. informative. There is no point in generating predictions which are untestable. It is less than ideal to have predictions which are not potentially falsifiable. If a theory can be used to predict all possible outcomes of a situation then we are no better for having the theory than not. Such predictions carry no information value. A theory should be able to predict the presence of some outcomes and the absence of others. In this view a useful hypothesis is one which is, in principle, falsifiable.
The notion that science makes progress via theoretically based conjectures and empirically based refutations is not without problems and not without its critics. Suppose a hypothesis generated from the theory proves to be false. Do we reject the whole theory? Do we question those concepts used to generate the hypothesis? Do we treat it as measurement error? In testing any hypothesis there are probably many other hypotheses implicit in our measuring instruments or data analysis procedures. Could it be that one of these has been falsified? Clearly it is very difficult to know what to make of particular acts of falsification. This is not to say that falsification is an irrelevant criterion, rather that it is a very difficult notion with which to work.
There is the view however (Feyerabend, 1970) that progress via a process of conjecture and refutation is unnecessarily slow. In this view the essence of progress is industry. Sheer quantity of empirical work generates data which can be scrutinised for generality.

Parsimony

If we have a set of data or phenomena which we seek to describe and comprehend it seems self evident that the more rendered down the description is the more easily it can be accommodated intellectually. Of course this rendering down must not result in a loss of complexity or accuracy. By representing all forms of matter in terms of atoms the physicist has a very parsimonious way of describing a wide range of properties of matter and related phenomena such as magnetism and electricity. Additionally, this representation can readily be manipulated symbolically to explore relationships not amenable to inquiry if the concrete form of representation were the limit of our description.
Parsimony is related to breadth of application. The greater the range of phenomena that can be accommodated by a limited number of concepts the more powerful and efficient is our mode of representation. There is no absolute scale of parsimony. A theory can only be judged parsimonious in respect of other theories claiming to account for the same data. Equally, whilst efforts are made to remove redundant concepts in a theory and sharpen the definitions of others, there is no 'ideal' number of concepts to be striven for. Any appeal for parsimony must recognise the considerable complexity of the problems social science theories deal with. Simple theories are to be preferred to complex theories only when they are equally valid and general.

Fruitfulness

We have noted earlier that a good theory is a rich source of empirical work. This is so, but the proviso to be emphasised is that the work must be productiveā€”it must have implications for the development of general theory. Industry is often confused with productivity. The advent of information processing theories in cognitive psychology has led to a massive surge in research but critics have recently noted that the majority of this work is not making a contribution to theoretical progress (Allport, 1975; Newell, 1974). The work is said to have become 'phenomena driven' rather than 'theory driven'. It seems that the theory is not amenable to direct, empirical investigation and as a consequence the data gathered have little clear implication for the development of theory.

Assessing Piaget's theory

In the above sections we have commented on the kinds of question one must ask of a scientific theory. None of the questions demands an absolute answer. Theories are judged in some respects with reference to competing theories. In other respects they are judged against our sense of scientific progress. In subsequent chapters we shall look at Piaget's theory in detail with such issues in mind. In the second half of this chapter we endeavour to locate Piaget's theory in the context of other views of intellectual development. In that section we focus on the issue we first nominated, that is the problem of making choices about the kinds of question to ask and the kinds of data to select.

Contrasting approaches to cognitive development

Bryant (1971) identified three approaches to cognitive development. There are those which focus on perception, those which emphasise the development of language and those which study logical development per se.
The work of Bower, 1974; Fantz, 1964; and Gibson et al., 1962 exemplifies an approach via the study of perception. In this view it is suggested that the infant is born with certain abilities to distinguish shape, distance and colour. Development consists of gradual changes from relatively simple codes for the identification of incoming data, to more sophisticated ones as a result of experience. The task of the developmental psychologist is then to determine exactly how the new distinctive features of stimuli come to be apprehended and learned.
The effects of language acquisition have been emphasised and studied by workers of quite different orientations (e.g. Vygotsky, 1962; Kendler and Kendler, 1962). In different ways both attempt to explain how language provides a symbol system which enables the child to develop from direct and immediate responses to specific stimuli towards a mediated form of behaviour which is more flexible and adaptive.
Piaget's studies examine the transition from immediate action to more reflective, logical processes. We shall describe his account in detail in Chapter 2. For the ...

Table of contents

  1. Cover
  2. Title
  3. Copyright
  4. Contents
  5. 1 Piaget and theories of development
  6. 2 Piaget's theory of cognitive development
  7. 3 Problems in validating the theory
  8. 4 Specific issues in the validation of Piagetian theory
  9. 5 Learning and the development of cognition
  10. 6 Retrospect and prospect
  11. Bibliography
  12. Index