The Roots of Special Relativity
eBook - ePub

The Roots of Special Relativity

Science and Society

  1. 404 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

The Roots of Special Relativity

Science and Society

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

Modern science has changed every aspect of life in ways that cannot be compared to developments of previous eras. This four-volume set presents key developments within modern physical science and the effects of these discoveries on modern global life. The first two volumes explore the history of the concept of relativity, the cultural roots of science, the concept of time and gravity before, during, and after Einstein's theory, and the cultural reception of relativity. Volume 3 explores the impact of modern science upon global politics and the creation of a new kind of war, and Volume 4 details the old and new efforts surrounding the elucidation of the quantum world, as well as the cultural impact of particle physics. This reprint collection pools the best scholarship available, collected from a large array of difficult to acquire books, journals, and pamphlets. Each volume begins with an introductory essay, written by one of the top scholars in the history of science. Students and scholars of modern culture, science, and society will find these volumes a veritable research gold mine.

Frequently asked questions

Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Yes, you can access The Roots of Special Relativity by Peter Galison,Michael Gordin,David Kaiser in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in History & World History. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Publisher
Routledge
Year
2013
ISBN
9781136709166
Edition
1
Topic
History
Index
History
SCIENCE AND SOCIETY:
The History of Modern Physical Science in the Twentieth Century
Volume 1: Making Special Relativity
ON THE ELECTRODYNAMICS OF MOVING BODIES
By A. Einstein
That Maxwell’s electrodynamics – the way in which it is usually understood – when applied to moving bodies, leads to asymmetries which do not appear to be inherent in the phenomena is well known. Consider, for example, the reciprocal electrodynamic interaction of a magnet and a conductor. The observable phenomenon here depends only on the relative motion of the conductor and the magnet, whereas the customary conception draws a sharp distinction between the two cases in which either the one or the other of these bodies is in motion. For if the magnet is in motion and the conductor at rest, there arises in the neighborhood of the magnet an electric field with a certain definite energy, producing a current at the places where parts of the conductor are situated. But if the magnet is at rest and the conductor in motion, no electric field arises in the neighborhood of the magnet. In the conductor, however, we find an electromotive force, to which in itself there is no corresponding energy, but which gives rise – assuming equality of relative motion in the two cases discussed – to electric currents of the same path and intensity as those produced by the electric forces in the former case.
Examples of this sort, together with the unsuccessful attempts to discover any motion of the earth relatively to the “light medium,” lead to the conjecture that to the concept of absolute rest there correspond no properties of the phenomena, neither in mechanics, nor in electrodynamics, but rather that as has already been shown to quantities of the first order, for every reference system in which the laws of mechanics are valid*, the laws of electrodynamics and optics are also valid.
We will raise this conjecture (whose intent will from now on be referred to as the “Principle of Relativity”) to a postulate, and moreover introduce another postulate, which is only apparently irreconcilable with the former: light is always propagated in empty space with a definite velocity c which is independent of the state of motion of the emitting body. These two postulates suffice in order to obtain a simple and consistent theory of the electrodynamics of moving bodies taking as a basis Maxwell’s theory for bodies at rest. The introduction of a “luminiferous ether” will prove to be superfluous because the view here to be developed will introduce neither an “absolutely resting space” provided with special properties, nor associate a velocity-vector with a point of empty space in which electromagnetic processes occur.
The theory to be developed is based – like all electrodynamics – on the kinematics of the rigid body, since the assertions of any such theory concern the relationships between rigid bodies (coordinate systems), clocks, and electromagnetic processes. Insufficient consideration of this circumstance is the root of the difficulties with which the electrodynamics of moving bodies presently has to contend.
I. KINEMATICAL PART
§1. Definition of Simultaneity
Let us consider a coordinate system in which the equations of Newtonian mechanics hold.* For precision of demonstration and to distinguish this coordinate system verbally from others which will be introduced later, we call it the “resting system.”
If a material point is at rest relatively to this coordinate system, its position can be defined relative to it by rigid measuring rods employing the methods of Euclidean geometry, and can be expressed in Cartesian coordinates.
If we wish to describe the motion of a material point, we give the values of its coordinates as functions of the time. Now we must bear carefully in mind that a mathematical description of this kind has no physical meaning unless we are quite clear as to what we will understand by “time”. We have to take into account that all our judgments in which time plays a role are always judgments of simultaneous events. If, for instance, I say, “That train arrives here at 7 o’clock.” I mean something like this: “The pointing of the small hand of my watch to 7 and the arrival of the train are simultaneous events.”**
It might appear possible that all the difficulties concerning the definition of “time” can be overcome by substituting “the position of the small hand of my watch” for “time.” In fact such a definition is satisfactory when we are concerned with defining a time exclusively for the place where the watch is located; but it is no longer satisfactory when we have to connect in time series of events occurring at different places, or – what comes to the same thing – to evaluate the times of events occurring at places remote from the watch. We could in principle content ourselves to time events by using an observer located at the origin of the coordinate system, and equipped with a clock, who coordinates the arrival of the light signal originating from the event to be timed and traveling to his position through empty space, to be timed with the hands of his clock. Yet as we know from experience, this coordination has the disadvantage that it is not independent of the standpoint of the observer with the clock. We arrive at a much more practical arrangement by means of the following considerations.
If at the point A of space there is a clock, an observer at A can time the events in the immediate vicinity of A by coordinating the positions of the hands which are simultaneous with these events. If there is at the space point B another clock – and we wish to add, “a clock being of exactly the same characteristics as the one at A” – then it is possible for an observer at B to time the events in the immediate neighborhood of B. But, without further definitions it is not possible to compare, in respect with time, an event at A with an event at B. Thus far we have defined only an “A time” and a “B time”, but no common “time” for A and B. The latter time can now be defined by requiring that by definition the “time” necessary for light to travel from A to B be identical to the “time” necessary to travel from B to A. Let a ray of light start at the “A time” tA from A toward B, let it at the “B time” tB be reflected at B in the direction of A, and arrive again at A at the “A time” t’A. The two clocks run in synchronization by definition if
images
We assume this definition of synchronization to be free of any possible contradictions, applicable to arbitrarily many points, and that the following relations are universally valid: –
1. If the clock at B synchronizes with the clock at A, the clock at A synchronizes with the clock at B.
2. If the clock at A synchronizes with the clock at B and also with the clock at C, the clocks at B and C also synchronize with each other.
Thus with the help of certain (imaginary) physical experiments we have defined what is to be understood by synchronous stationary clocks located at different places, and have clearly obtained a definition of “simultaneous,” or “synchronous,” and of “time.” The “time” of an event is the reading simultaneous with the event of a clock at rest and located at the position of the event, this clock being synchronous, and indeed synchronous for all time determinations, with a specified clock at rest.
In addition, in agreement with experience we further require that the quantity
images
be a universal constant (the velocity of light in empty space).
It is essential to have time defined by means of clocks at rest in a resting system, and the time now defined being appropriate to the resting system we call “the time of the resting system.”
§2. On the Relativity of Lengths and Times
The following considerations are based on the principle of relativity and on the principle of the constancy of the velocity of light. We define these two principles thus –
1. The laws by which the states of physical systems undergo changes are independent of whether these changes of state are referred to one or the other of two coordinate systems moving relatively to each other in uniform translational motion.
2. Any ray of light moves in the “resting” coordinate system with the definite velocity c, which is independent of whether the ray was emitted by a resting or by a moving body. Consequently,
images
where time interval is to be understood in the sense of the definition in §1.
Consider a rigid rod at rest whose length is l when measured by a measuring-rod which is also at rest. We now imagine the axis of the rod lying along the x-axis of the resting coordinate system, and that a uniform motion of parallel translation with velocity v along the x-axis in the direction of increasing x is then imparted to the rod. We now inquire as to the length of the moving rod, which we imagine to be determined by means of the following two operations: –
(a) The observer moves together with the given measuring-rod and the rod to be measured, and measures the length of the rod directly by superposing the measuring-rod, in just the same way as if the rod to be measured, observer and measuring rod were at rest.
(b) By means of clocks at rest set up in the resting system and synchronized in accordance with §1, the observer ascertains at what points of the resting system the two ends of the rod to be measured are located at a definite time t. The distance between these two points, measured by the measuring-rod already employed, which in this case is at rest, is also a length which may be designated “the length of the rod.”
According to the principle of relativity the length to be discovered by the operation (a) – we will call it “the length of the rod in the moving system” – must be equal to the length l of the rod at rest.
The length to be discovered by the operation (b) we will call “the length of the (moving) rod in the resting system,” which we shall determine on the basis of our two principles. We shall find that it differs from l.
Current kinematics assumes tacitly that the lengths determined by these two operations are precisely equal, or in other words, that a moving rigid body at the instant of time t may in geometrical respects be perfectly represented by the same body at rest in a definite position.
We imagine further that at the two ends A and B of the rod, clocks are placed which synchronize with the clocks of the resting system – that is, that their indications correspond at any instant to the “time of the resting system” at the places where they happen to be. Consequently these clocks are “synchronous in the resting system.”
We imagine further that with each clock there is a moving observer, and that these observers apply to both c...

Table of contents

  1. Cover Page
  2. Half Title page
  3. Series Content
  4. Title Page
  5. Copyright Page
  6. Contents
  7. Volume Introduction
  8. On the Electrodynamics of Moving Bodies
  9. Mach, Einstein, and the Search for Reality
  10. Einstein and the Cultural Roots of Modern Science
  11. Henri Poincaré's Criticism of Fin De Siècle Electrodynamics
  12. Reconsidering a Scientific Revolution: The Case of Einstein versus Lorentz
  13. The Special Relativity Theory: Einstein's Response to the Physics of 1905
  14. Einstein's Clocks: The Place of Time
  15. Understanding the history of special relativity
  16. The Relativity Revolution in Germany
  17. Cultural Issues in the Reception of Relativity
  18. In Defense of Ether: The British Response to Einstein's Special Theory of Relativity, 1905–1911
  19. Cambridge Mathematics and Cavendish Physics: Cunningham, Campbell and Einstein's Relativity 1905–1911: Part I: The Uses of Theory
  20. Acknowledgments