Autonomy and Liberalism
eBook - ePub

Autonomy and Liberalism

  1. 176 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Autonomy and Liberalism

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

This book concerns the foundations and implications of a particular form of liberal political theory. Colburn argues that one should see liberalism as a political theory committed to the value of autonomy, understood as consisting in an agent deciding for oneself what is valuable and living life in accordance with that decision. Understanding liberalism this way offers solutions to various problems that beset liberal political theory, on various levels. On the theoretical level, Colburn claims that this position is the only defensible theory of liberalism in current circulation, arguing that other more dominant theories are either self-contradictory or unattractive on closer inspection. And on the practical level, Colburn draws out the substantive commitments of this position in educational, economic, and social policy. Hence, the study provides a blueprint for a radical liberal political agenda which will be of interest to philosophers and to politicians alike.

Frequently asked questions

Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Yes, you can access Autonomy and Liberalism by Ben Colburn in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Philosophy & Political Philosophy. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Publisher
Routledge
Year
2010
ISBN
9781136996832

1
Three Conceptions of Autonomy

For all that it is a concept in common use in political philosophy, there is little consensus about what autonomy actually is. Clearly, this is a dangerous state of affairs if one is trying to justify a theory of liberalism based on a commitment to the value of autonomy. Justification is apt to be misunderstood, with different readers taking ‘autonomy’ to mean different (sometimes wildly different) things. Opponents of such a theory run the risk of attacking it on an understanding of autonomy different from that on which it is actually based; a parallel danger for me will be unwittingly playing upon equivocations to make justifications seem more plausible than they in fact are. These dangers cannot entirely be avoided. The best that can be done is briefly to survey the territory, then clear the undergrowth a little by clarifying what I shall mean by ‘autonomy’ in what follows, and why. This chapter deals with that task.
Before I start, it will be useful to make clear two distinctions between ways of understanding autonomy. First, we might distinguish between autonomy conceived of as a local property—that is, as a property of a person at a particular time and perhaps in respect of particular decisions or actions—and as a global property, meaning a property of a person’s life as a whole. Secondly, we can distinguish between different types of properties that one might take autonomy to be. Some conceptions take autonomy to be a condition that someone can be in, and others take it to be a capacity that one might possess, the possession of which is itself valuable (independently of its exercise, for example). These distinctions will prove significant later on, especially when I show how my conception of autonomy differs from the others I examine.
Despite the lack of consensus surrounding contemporary conceptions of autonomy, I suggest that we can identify a common thread running through them all. Following John Christman, I suggest that the core concept of autonomy is something like self-governance, or control of one’s commitments.1 Each of the conceptions autonomy that I examine below is a different understanding of a concept of self-governance.
There are three dominant conceptions of autonomy currently in circulation. First, there are conceptions of autonomy as rational self-legislation, most famously (though not exclusively) espoused by Kant and his intellectual successors. Secondly, there are conceptions that rely upon the notion of a hierarchy of motivations advanced by Harry Frankfurt and by Gerald Dworkin. Finally, there are conceptions built on a notion of self-authorship or individuality, such as that employed by Joseph Raz. Considering these three conceptions separately should not imply that they are necessarily in direct conflict with each other. As we shall see, I adopt my conception of autonomy partially in response to the flaws of the other positions, but I do not assume from the outset that it is impossible that the three families of conceptions examined here might coexist. There may just be three different and compatible ideals at work, each indicated by a different conception of autonomy.

1.1 AUTONOMY AND REASON

One family of substantive conceptions of autonomy understands self-governance to consist in rational self-legislation or determination. So, on these views, the concept of autonomy is to be fleshed out as an ideal of a condition possessed by agents at particular times: for an agent to be autonomous is for them to act with self-control in accordance with reason. Such conceptions fall into two main categories, which I shall call Kantian and non-Kantian rationalism respectively.
According to Kant, a person is autonomous if his will is self-ruling.2 To be self-ruling, the will must be ‘efficient independently of alien causes determining it,’ where alien causes include not only the agency of others (as, for example, if one were being controlled by hypnosis) but also the laws of nature. The latter includes things like desires and impulses: such mental phenomena are part of the causal chain of nature, and therefore constitute alien causes. Kant also wanted to exclude lawless action, for that too is a sort of slavery (though to chaos, rather than to alien causes). So, the autonomous will must be in accordance with laws of a special kind, namely those that have as their source nothing other than the will itself. That, Kant said, meant behaving in accordance with the Categorical Imperative, for that is the only law that can be derived just from pure reason. To be autonomous, the will must not act on anything that might be an alien cause. Alien causes derive from the particular, contingent circumstances of individuals: desires, impulses, adverse conditions and pressures, and so on. To avoid these, the will must act in a way completely undetermined by the particular circumstances under which it is acting. That means, though, acting on motives that one might will that anyone—including those who don’t share one’s particular circumstances— could also will. So, in Kant’s theory, the autonomous will is just one that acts in accordance with the Categorical Imperative.
Kant’s theory, as sketched here, has two components. First, there is the concept of autonomy for which he argued: autonomy is a property of a person’s will which consists in that will being determined only by laws given by the will itself. Secondly, there is the particular conception of autonomy that comes from his claim that the only law so given is the Categorical Imperative. It would be possible for someone to endorse the first component, but not the second. That is, we could agree that autonomy consists in acting only on laws given by the will itself, while thinking that the Categorical Imperative is not the only law that can be so given. We might, for example, disagree with Kant that all contingent factors count as alien causes in the relevant sense, and discriminate between different types of desire. Perhaps certain types of desire might not be alien to us, and that acting on those desires would not vitiate autonomy. Or, we might agree that all desires are alien causes, being part of the natural chain of causation, but think that there is nothing to stop the will from choosing autonomously to take them into consideration in its deliberation.
This gives us various possible Kantian conceptions of autonomy. The strictest position is that held by Kant himself: autonomy is equivalent to the behaviour demanded by morality, which is to say acting in accordance with the Categorical Imperative. Conceptions can vary in strictness by allowing that there might be other things than the Categorical Imperative that are non-alien in the relevant sense.
Contemporary philosophers who have used a Kantian conception of autonomy vary in their strictness. Jonathan Jacobs, for example, takes a position at the stricter end of the spectrum: he argues that someone who acts freely and voluntarily might nevertheless fall short of autonomy because they might fail to follow the moral law.3 Others defend conceptions that are less strict, sometimes considerably so. David Richards, for example, takes himself still to be a Kantian, but says that the requirement that the will is not determined by alien causes is satisfied by a weak endorsement condition: it is sufficient for autonomy to have exercised ‘the higher-order capacity of the agent to choose her or his ends, whatever they are’ for those ends to count as non-alien.4 Richards’ variant of the Kantian conception brings it close to collapsing into the conceptions I examine in Section 1.2, which emphasise higher-order endorsement as the key to autonomy. However, Richards’ view remains distinct insofar as—like Kant—he takes the non-alienness of causes to be centrally important, and endorsement important as the means to guaranteeing non-alienness.
At this point, we might worry whether Richards, Jacobs and Kant are really all using the same conception of autonomy. Indeed, we might even worry whether a Kantian conception of autonomy can properly be applied to political philosophy at all, since in Kant’s own theory its role is just to identify the quality that the will must have if it is to be able to act in accordance with morality. Kant’s conception of autonomy is sometimes called moral autonomy, and is contrasted with personal autonomy (which is normally equated with one of the other conceptions of autonomy I examine in this chapter). Drawing this distinction is often intended to motivate our avoiding moral autonomy as a potential subject for political philosophers to consider. This sometimes seems to be the position of John Rawls, for example.5 Even if we grant that a Kantian conception of autonomy can play a role in political philosophy, there is dispute about whether the people who take themselves to be Kantians are working within such a framework. Onora O’Neill argues, of positions such as Richards’, that they badly misrepresent their own foundations if they claim Kantian support.6
These are interesting problems, and they have received some attention in recent literature.7 However, they are somewhat tangential to our present business. As a matter of fact, there are political philosophers who adopt a Kantian conception of autonomy and apply it to political philosophy. So, they are worth examining here, even if we worry about their Kantian pedigree. To put it another way, regardless of whether we think them genuine interpretations of Kant, Kant-inspired, or only pseudo-Kantian, they all share the core thought that autonomy consists in acting only from non-alien causes, which they all identify roughly as acting only in accordance with reason. Another group of conceptions of autonomy exist, which while they do not trace a lineage to Kant, still place emphasis upon the notion of rational self-legislation or direction. So, for example, Robert Ladenson sketches a conception—which he attributes to Dewey—on which autonomy is identified with a life lived in accordance with reason, understood as
a set of abilities and capacities whose coordinated operation tends to result in a person’s attaining goods and avoiding evils, both on particular occasions and over the long run.8
These ‘more developed’ capacities are contrasted with lower ones such as emotions, instincts and habits. Hence, we suppose, for Ladenson being autonomous consists in being guided by reason and eschewing those lower capacities. Ladenson’s ideal has a teleological air—that is, it identifies an end-state condition which is valuable, and identifies autonomy with what is needed to get to it. Other proponents of rationalist autonomy avoid this teleological character and instead take the value of autonomy to be the exercise of a capacity. Some writers on Stoicism, for example, take autonomy to be a condition consisting of control over one’s urges and impulses, either through the exercise of willpower,9 or by the use of the capacity for reason.10 Others use a similar conception of autonomy, though they don’t identify it as especially Stoic in nature. So, George Sher says that an autonomous agent is self-governing in the sense of ‘exercising their will on the basis of good reasons’;11 Keith Lehrer suggests that autonomy consists just in being governed by reason;12 John Benson says that to be autonomous one must ‘put oneself in the best position to answer for the reliability of one’s beliefs’;13 and Lawrence Haworth says that to be autonomous an agent must display ‘full rationality’, which consists in both means-end reasoning and exercise of critical appraisal of the ends they adopt.14
In all these conceptions of autonomy there is a common emphasis upon rational behaviour. The concept of autonomy as self-governance is interpreted as an ideal of the exercise of reason. It is in respect of this emphasis on reason that the conceptions in this family are distinct from those I consider later. And because of this, these conceptions are all in danger of unjustifiably lionising reason over other possible sources of action and motivation. Why, we might ask, should we think that acting on reason is valuable, or at least the same sort of ideal as autonomy? Why should we think that only acting on reason can count as self-governance?
One consistent answer—but one which we might be reluctant to accept— was given by Kant. Kant gave an objective criterion by which he judged that pure reason was the only non-alien cause. According to Kant we should distinguish between the phenomenal world, in which our desires are bound within a causal chain that destroys freedom, and the noumenal world, in which we are free from such causal determination. It is only insofar as we act without being determined by the tyranny of causation that we govern ourselves. So, Kant’s motivation for identifying autonomy with acting on pure reason flowed from his broader metaphysical theory, and it serves as a motivation only if we accept that metaphysics.
Suppose that we reject Kantian metaphysics, or at any rate want to avoid basing our political philosophy on such controversial territory. What then? I suggest that, with Kant out of the picture, there is no justification for placing such weight on the exercise of reason in our account of autonomy. After all, introspection suggests that there are other motivations which seem, as much as acting on reason does, to derive from the ‘self’. So, if our core concept of autonomy is that of self-governance, it is unclear why those other motivations mightn’t also count. In the absence of a positive argument for abandoning common sense here (and assuming that we do not want to adopt the whole of Kant’s metaphysical position), this should make us wary of understanding autonomy in this way.
Admittedly, pointing out the absence of an argument for the emphasis on reason hardly refutes the rationalist conceptions of autonomy. However, there are other reasons to think that there is something unattractive about autonomy understood in this way. All the conceptions considered in this section take self-governance to mean self-governance according to what is demanded by reason. They differ in quite how stringent and specific they take those demands to be, but they are all committed to taking those demands to be binding. Hence, they recognise no authority for individuals over questions of what will make their lives go well. As we shall see in Section 1.3 I take this to a core component of the i...

Table of contents

  1. Routledge Studies in Contemporary Philosophy
  2. Anne Whyte 1924–1990 Pat Colburn 1913–1999 William Whyte 1914–2007
  3. Contents
  4. Acknowledgments
  5. Introduction
  6. 1 Three Conceptions of Autonomy
  7. 2 A Theory of Autonomy
  8. 3 Autonomy and Anti-Perfectionism
  9. 4 Autonomy-Minded Liberalism
  10. 5 Multicultural Liberalism
  11. Conclusion
  12. Notes
  13. Bibliography
  14. Index