The Mirror of the Self
eBook - ePub

The Mirror of the Self

Sexuality, Self-Knowledge, and the Gaze in the Early Roman Empire

Shadi Bartsch

  1. English
  2. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  3. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

The Mirror of the Self

Sexuality, Self-Knowledge, and the Gaze in the Early Roman Empire

Shadi Bartsch

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

People in the ancient world thought of vision as both an ethical tool and a tactile sense, akin to touch. Gazing upon someone—or oneself—was treated as a path to philosophical self-knowledge, but the question of tactility introduced an erotic element as well. In The Mirror of the Self, Shadi Bartsch asserts that theselinks among vision, sexuality, and self-knowledge are key to the classical understanding of the self.Weaving together literary theory, philosophy, and social history, Bartsch traces this complex notion of self from Plato's Greece to Seneca's Rome. She starts by showing how ancient authors envisioned the mirror as both a tool for ethical self-improvement and, paradoxically, a sign of erotic self-indulgence. Her reading of the Phaedrus, for example, demonstrates that the mirroring gaze in Plato, because of its sexual possibilities, could not be adopted by Roman philosophers and their students. Bartsch goes on to examine the Roman treatment of the ethical and sexual gaze, and she traces how self-knowledge, the philosopher's body, and the performance of virtue all played a role in shaping the Roman understanding of the nature of selfhood. Culminating in a profoundly original reading of Medea, The Mirror of the Self illustrates how Seneca, in his Stoic quest for self-knowledge, embodies the Roman view, marking a new point in human thought about self-perception.Bartsch leads readers on a journey that unveils divided selves, moral hypocrisy, and lustful Stoics—and offers fresh insights about seminal works. At once sexy and philosophical, The Mirror of the Self will be required reading for classicists, philosophers, and anthropologists alike.

Frequently asked questions

How do I cancel my subscription?
Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
Can/how do I download books?
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
What is the difference between the pricing plans?
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
What is Perlego?
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Do you support text-to-speech?
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Is The Mirror of the Self an online PDF/ePUB?
Yes, you can access The Mirror of the Self by Shadi Bartsch in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Philosophy & Philosophy History & Theory. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

1
The Mirror of Philosophy
Vision and knowledge have a long and intertwined history. If the act of seeing has been sometimes intimately linked to knowing—as the etymologies behind theory, reflection, speculation, and enlightenment make clear—at other times earthly sight has been criticized for blocking our vision of eternal verities. It was not only Kant or Descartes who thought that what we take for granted about our gaze on the world outside could undermine our ability to comprehend what that world really is; a philosophical sense of the precariousness of such an assumption has long roots in Greco-Roman antiquity, underlying, for example, the allegory of the cave in Plato’s Republic, and informing aspects of the philosophical thought of figures as diverse as Aristotle, Seneca, and Augustine. Like Plato, Dante in the Paradiso saw the world as an inferior copy of the heavens, a mere speculum inferius; later, with the advent of perspectivalism in Renaissance painting, the mathematical qualities of linear perspective were deemed pure enough be related to the transcendental qualities of God’s own sight.1 An interesting parallel is provided by modern quantum mechanics, in which our observations can never reveal the true nature of a physical object.
Despite the friction between seeing as blindness and seeing as insight, the idea of the gaze turned inward upon the self came to provide a lasting metaphor for the project of self-knowledge. John Locke’s so-called observer model of reflection famously appealed to a subject’s inner visual perception, which was directed toward his own mental operations as a method for self-knowledge, while RenĂ© Descartes’ notion that the mind inspects its ideas with an unwavering internal gaze provided, as some would claim, the fundamental ground of modern philosophy itself. As Rodolphe GaschĂ© writes, “The philosophy of reflection is generally considered to have begun with Descartes’ prima philosophia. . . . In Descartes the scholastic idea of the reditus [the inward turn] undergoes an epochal transformation, whereby reflection, instead of being merely the medium of metaphysics, becomes its very foundation” (1986, 17).2
This visual emphasis is present in ancient explorations of self-knowledge as well, and much of this book will focus on the intersection of vision and philosophy in classical formulations of coming to know the self. Nowhere in our ancient sources, however, do we encounter the idea of “the eye of the mind.” There is no version here of Cartesian self-knowledge as the mind mirroring its own processes, or reflecting upon its capacity for reflection. Instead, ancient formulations of the epistemological power of self-regard stress the specular capacity of the actual gaze rather than the mind’s eye — that is, its instructive potential when mirrored back upon the looking self. Indeed, the most common invocation of the possibility of self-knowledge thus holds that the mirror itself might help in the search for wisdom, and that the reflected image of the seeker after truth might have something to teach such a would-be philosopher. One might say that the mirror of philosophy had its most common instantiation in antiquity as the mirror in philosophy, and its invocation as a literal tool for use on the path to self-improvement was so common as to span the gamut of genres from sober treatises to impolite epigrams, and the run of authors from Plato to Martial — and beyond.
The distinctive quality of the ancient mirror consisted, of course, in its then rare ability to reflect the viewer to himself, and far more accurately so than other available resources, such as still water or polished stone. What this meant in Greco-Roman thought, rather than in a modern philosophy steeped in the conceptual apparatus of reflexivity, will emerge from this work. And the mirror as cultural object, too, elicits different reactions in different eras. We moderns tend to take mirrors for granted: a cheap one can be bought for a few cents at any drugstore, and they surround us in our lives from the first bathroom stumbles of the morning. The ancient mirror, by contrast, was an object of comparative rarity and considerable expense. It was the subject of optical theorizing, magic beliefs, and most of all, of moralizing discourses that either praised it for its ability to render back an accurate reflection or damned it as a luxury and a tool of vanity. It lay, as we shall see, at the basis of a long tradition in which it appeared now as a means to truth, now as a fount of illusion. Most important for this book, the ancient reception of the mirror provides a way to understand the interrelation of such seemingly disparate discourses in antiquity as the nature of self-knowledge, the visual emphasis of ancient culture, and the interaction of eros and philosophy; the mirror allows us entry into all three topics of this study at once. Accordingly, this chapter approaches classical notions of selfhood by exploring ancient approaches to the mirror, before turning to such objects of study as prescriptive philosophizing, sociohistorical contexts, and the terminology of sophrosyne and conscientia sui.
The uses of the mirror laid out in this chapter will have continued significance throughout this volume. Some of the key terms and ideas introduced here—especially the contrast between the mirror of the community, the erotic mirror, and Plato’s mirror—will recur in ways that offer startling insight into the cultural context in which they are produced. As we shall see, the Platonic gesture toward a mirror in which can be seen a divine perspective upon the self is partially recapitulated in the efforts of a Roman Stoic, Seneca the younger, to find ways of reflecting upon the self that might be independent of the judgment of one’s fellow man; at the same time, the notion of a “mirror of the self,” in all its permutations, beautifully elucidates the particular concerns of the elite of imperial Rome in the first century ce. In every case, the mirror illustrates the importance of the gaze of the subject, and on the subject, for the ethical development of the ancient self. For us too, then, as once for its Greek and Roman viewers, this implement will provide a view onto a larger picture.3
THE INCENTIVE TO VIRTUE
In late 158 or early 159 CE an unusual trial took place in the town of Sabratha in Roman North Africa. The defendant was Apuleius of Madaurus, the author of the Metamorphoses and a local philosopher and rhetorician of some prominence. The charge brought against Apuleius was that he was in fact a sorcerer who had put his magic skills to ill use by inducing a wealthy older woman to marry him. Accordingly, the accusers, headed by Apuleius’ new stepson, Sicinius Pudens, and a troop of other relatives eager to defend family moneys from the interloper in their midst, summoned up a motley collection of evidence, including Apuleius’ manufacture of tooth-powder and his purchase of various species of fish. But the prosecution also lingered on his appearance and modus vivendi: the long locks of hair, the love poems he wrote to young boys, and the discovery, in his house, of a mirror. These last items, they thought, hardly dovetailed with Apuleius’ supposed dedication to the life of the mind; on the contrary, they marked him as a man very much lodged in the flesh.
In the end, Apuleius would carry the day, and partly so by denying the lascivious implications of the hair, the poems, and the mirror.4 As he vigorously asserted in his rhetorical coup of a defense, his hair, far from the alluring coiffure of a fop, could be seen to be a matted and dirty mess.5 His love poems had a precedent in such eminent philosophers as Plato and Solon, and were less erotically explicit at that. As for the mirror, not only do all of us have an intrinsic affection for our own image, but even Socrates once avidly recommended its use to moral ends:
Is not Socrates the philosopher reported to have enjoined upon his students to contemplate themselves frequently in a mirror [crebro ut semet in speculo contemplarentur], that so those among them who were self-satisfied with their beauty might above all else take care that they did not disfigure the attractiveness of their body by bad character traits, but those who thought they were less good-looking might take pains to conceal their ugliness with the praise of their virtue? To such a degree did the wisest of all men use the mirror for the inculcation of good character [ad disciplinam morum]. (Apol. 15.8–15)
Apuleius, then, met these charges head on by focusing on the ostensibly philosophical use of the mirror for moral self-improvement, and deduced the innocence of his own specular self-indulgence from a practice he ascribed to none other than the venerable Socrates himself. Further evidence of the mirror’s utility, he added, could be seen in its scientific use to study the heavens, and even in its substitution for the judging eye of the other: Demosthenes, after all, rehearsed his orations in front of one quasi ante magistrum, as if before a teacher.6
Apuleius’ self-defense was merely a late manifestation of a distinguished tradition that united the ethicist and the mirror in the exhortation to virtue. Socrates’ dictum here, whether apocryphal or not, was quoted centuries earlier in Diogenes Laertius’ Lives of the Eminent Philosophers (2.33), and is invoked at the end of the first century CE, also with this attribution, in Plutarch’s Advice to Bride and Groom (141d).7 The later anthologist Stobaeus traces the recommendation to look in a mirror to a presocratic figure, Bias, who was one of the Seven Sages of Greek antiquity.8 Elsewhere, the idea that looking in a mirror could impose ethical directives on one’s behavior could be attributed to cultural authority figures such as the paterfamilias.9 The first-century CE Roman freedman Phaedrus weaves the familiar elements of the anecdote into a short fable in which two siblings, looking in a mirror, discover a discrepancy in comeliness. The boy, reveling in his good looks, preens in delight, but his homely sister, upset and jealous, runs to their father to tell on her brother: although he’s a boy, he’s handled something that only belongs to women (rem feminarum)! The wise father hugs them both and tells them to look in the mirror every day: “You” (to the son) “so that you won’t ruin your good looks with rotten deeds, but you” (to the daughter), “so that you can overcome that face of yours by your good character” (Phaedrus 3.8.14–16).10 Phaedrus’ introduction of the jealous sister to motivate the involvement of the father again draws attention to, and then dismisses, the negative connotations of such activity for the fable’s audience—almost as if Phaedrus anticipated that they, too, might be perturbed by the thought of a good-looking young man admiring his own features in a mirror.
These anecdotes share an understanding of the reflection in the mirror as the motivating force that can appeal to an individual to alter his or her ethical behavior in order to reinforce, or alternatively to mitigate, the judgment of the community on that person’s external appearance.11 This reflection does not bring with it any form of subjective, uniquely self-generated insight, nor does it suggest that outside appearances are negligible in the face of character—only that they can be upheld or overcome. Indeed, our own expression “handsome is as handsome does” reverses the terms of this Greco-Roman polarity: for Socrates and Bias, an attractive face elicits the ethical injunction to uphold that appearance by matching your behavior to it, while “handsome is as handsome does” suggests that one’s behavior is the true source of beauty. That this ancient impetus to self-improvement takes its origin from the visible features of the self-inspector, however they may be judged, is not surprising in face-to-face cultures such as Athens and Rome, in which personal appearance could be seen as an index of personal ethics.12 After all, as many a pithy saying decreed, the face was the mirror of the soul. Cicero reminds the would-be orator of this: “imago animi vultus, indices oculi” (De Or. 3.221; cf.Orat. 60.5). The novelist Achilles Tatius has his hero Clitophon remark that “it does not seem correct to me to say that the mind is entirely invisible: it reveals itself, as if in a mirror, on the face” (Clitophon and Leucippe 6.6.2).13 For Pliny the Elder, “in man alone is the brow an index of sadness, happiness, mercy, severity.”14 A common expression held that the eyes were the mirror of the soul.15 Indeed, what you could read on a man’s visage could tell you much about his character: “Qualem intus putas esse animum cuius extra imago tam foeda est?” as Seneca would remark of a man whose face was distorted with rage (De ira 2.35.4; cf.Ep. 52.12).16
If mirrors could be conceived of as encouraging forms of behavior that lived up to—or escaped the limitations of—the message of the face, another, equally widespread, strand of justification for the use of the mirror suggested that specular self-inspection could put a quick end to forms of akrasia, lapses in self-control; in other words, that the image in the mirror could cut short bad behavior as well as encourage good. Diogenes Laertius claims of Plato that ...

Table of contents

  1. Cover
  2. Copyright
  3. Title Page
  4. Contents
  5. Acknowledgments
  6. Introduction
  7. 1. The Mirror of Philosophy
  8. 2. The Eye of the Lover
  9. 3. Scopic Paradigms at Rome
  10. 4. The Self on Display
  11. 5. Models of Personhood
  12. Notes
  13. References
  14. Index
Citation styles for The Mirror of the Self

APA 6 Citation

Bartsch, S. (2017). The Mirror of the Self ([edition unavailable]). The University of Chicago Press. Retrieved from https://www.perlego.com/book/1852720/the-mirror-of-the-self-sexuality-selfknowledge-and-the-gaze-in-the-early-roman-empire-pdf (Original work published 2017)

Chicago Citation

Bartsch, Shadi. (2017) 2017. The Mirror of the Self. [Edition unavailable]. The University of Chicago Press. https://www.perlego.com/book/1852720/the-mirror-of-the-self-sexuality-selfknowledge-and-the-gaze-in-the-early-roman-empire-pdf.

Harvard Citation

Bartsch, S. (2017) The Mirror of the Self. [edition unavailable]. The University of Chicago Press. Available at: https://www.perlego.com/book/1852720/the-mirror-of-the-self-sexuality-selfknowledge-and-the-gaze-in-the-early-roman-empire-pdf (Accessed: 15 October 2022).

MLA 7 Citation

Bartsch, Shadi. The Mirror of the Self. [edition unavailable]. The University of Chicago Press, 2017. Web. 15 Oct. 2022.