Caring for Liberalism
eBook - ePub

Caring for Liberalism

Dependency and Liberal Political Theory

  1. 306 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Caring for Liberalism

Dependency and Liberal Political Theory

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

Caring for Liberalism brings together chapters that explore how liberal political theory, in its many guises, might be modified or transformed to take the fact of dependency on board. In addressing the place of care in liberalism, this collection advances the idea that care ethics can help respond to legitimate criticisms from feminists who argue that liberalism ignores issues of race, class, and ethnicity. The chapters do not simply add care to existing liberal political frameworks; rather, they explore how integrating dependency might leave core components of the traditional liberal philosophical apparatus intact, while transforming other aspects of it. Additionally, the contributors address the design of social and political institutions through which care is given and received, with special attention paid to non-Western care practices. This book will appeal to scholars working on liberalism in philosophy, political science, law, and public policy, and it is a must-read for feminist political philosophers.

Frequently asked questions

Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on ā€œCancel Subscriptionā€ - itā€™s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time youā€™ve paid for. Learn more here.
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlegoā€™s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan youā€™ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, weā€™ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Yes, you can access Caring for Liberalism by Asha Bhandary, Amy R. Baehr in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Philosophy & Philosophy History & Theory. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Publisher
Routledge
Year
2020
ISBN
9781351186292

Part I

Historical Sources

1 On Domination and Dependency

Learning From Rousseauā€™s Critique of Inequality1

Christie Hartley and Lori Watson
Without needlessly drawing out the details, everyone must see that since ties of servitude are formed solely by menā€™s mutual dependence and the reciprocal needs that unite them, it is impossible to subjugate a man without first having placed him in the position of being unable to do without another.
(Rousseau 1997a, 159)2

Introduction

Political theorists have grappled with how political and social institutions should respond to the facts of human dependency. Human beings are both dependent upon others and interdependent in multiple and intersecting ways that raise serious concerns for justice. For example, all human beings, at least at some times, are dependent upon others for help with certain needs related to basic human functioning (e.g., nutrition). Infants are completely dependent upon caretakers for their survival; as children age, they still depend on others for help with their most basic needs for a number of years. Some adults, too, due to temporary illness or accident or due to some permanent conditions require care from others to meet basic needs. Thus, dependency on others for help with basic needs is one important sense of dependency relevant for justice; yet, there are others.
As social and moral creatures, human beings also have interests relevant to justice for certain social and moral goods. For example, childrenā€™s interests include social and emotional care, a moral education, and various supports from others for the development of their moral capacities. They are dependent on others for these goods, and such interests are a matter of justice. Adults also have interests in social and moral goods that are a matter of justice and for which they depend on others. Crucially, among the basic interests of persons in political society is the recognition of their moral status as a free and equal person and of their political status as a free and equal citizen. This requires recognition respect from others, in which others acknowledge an individualā€™s standing and authority as a moral person (Darwall 2006, 119ā€“147) and as an equal citizen in political society. Persons depend on others for this recognition, and this social recognition among persons must be supported by norms, practices, and institutions that embody and/or provide the social goods needed to sustain relationships of equal moral and political status among persons. Such norms, practices, and institutions are the social conditions of recognition respect (Watson and Hartley 2018).
In this chapter, we are especially concerned with the following three ways in which persons are dependent on others, though this is not an exhaustive list of dependency relations: human beings, at least at times, require the care of others to have certain basic needs met; human beings depend on others (and are often interdependent) for the realization of important social goods relevant to justice (e.g., goods involving support for social interaction and emotional care); and human beings depend on others for recognition respect as equal moral persons and as equal citizens and for maintaining the social conditions of recognition respect.
Liberal political theory, in particular, has been roundly criticized for its failure to adequately address the fact that human beings, at least at times, depend on others for help in meeting their basic needs and for social and emotional care. Feminist theorists have led the way in developing this critique of liberalism.3 They tend to focus on and criticize the liberal conception of persons as independent and self-reliant. They also argue that the work of caring for dependents is socially necessary work, that it is not properly valued or compensated, and that it has been traditionally assigned as ā€œwomenā€™s workā€ to the disadvantage of women. This feminist critique of liberalism is sometimes referred to as ā€œthe dependency critique.ā€4
However, some early liberals and some republicans did address a sense in which consideration of human dependency is central for theorizing justice.5 Their concern, though, was with the way in which some social and political institutions created the conditions for some adults (men) to be dependent upon the will of other adults (men). Their deepest concern was with the way in which social and political relationships could undermine the freedom of some men by exposing them to the arbitrary power of anotherā€™s will.6 This concern seems distinct from the type of dependency noted earlier, and these early theorists simply ignored or never considered the other ways in which human beings depend on others to have certain basic needs met.
Here, we explore the connections between these various senses of dependency with the aim of considering whether a liberal concern with finding a solution to dependency on the will of another can be extended to address some issues of justice related to other senses of dependency. Specifically, we explore some of the resources of a particular form of egalitarianism ā€“ namely, relational egalitarianism ā€“ for theorizing about matters of justice and human dependency, in all three senses noted earlier.7 Relational egalitarians hold that equality fundamentally concerns how people stand in relation to one another and that justice requires people have the same social position ā€“ one of equal standing and authority as moral persons and as citizens (Anderson 1999, 312ā€“315).8 For persons to have equal standing and authority as moral persons and as citizens, they must be treated as equals in certain respects in certain social domains. We are concerned here with those domains of social life that bear on oneā€™s status as a free and equal citizen, such as (1) the political sphere; (2) civil society, where members of society seek goods, services, and participation in places of public accommodation; (3) education and employment, where members of society seek to develop and exercise some of their talents and skills and produce needed goods; and (4) care frameworks, where members of society provide and receive care. Certain types of hierarchies in these contexts, that is, certain types of relationships of domination and subordination among persons or groups of persons in these contexts, are antithetical to all persons enjoying their status as equal moral persons and as equal citizens. We note that relationships of equality may require that particular material conditions obtain given personā€™s interests as equal moral persons and as equal citizens (Anderson 1999, 313ā€“314).
The structure of this chapter is as follows: first, we briefly discuss basic human needs, social and moral goods, and dependency. We emphasize the following: (1) all human beings must rely on others at times to have their basic needs met and for social and moral goods; (2) the way human beings depend on others and the degree to which human beings are dependent varies; (3) sometimes social conditions make human beings dependent on others; (4) sometimes human beings are dependent on others due to their stage in human development or due to illness or impairment, and some human beings would be dependent given any social conditions (e.g., newborns and persons with certain profound cognitive impairments are completely dependent on others for having their basic needs met and would be so regardless of the circumstances); and (5) those whose dependency is greatest or those who are completely dependent on others are most vulnerable to harm.
We further stress that any theory of justice must address certain needs and interests of persons, and many of these concern relations of dependency. However, by the end of the chapter, it will be clear that we think it is a mistake for liberals to make a sharp distinction between the complete and extreme dependency of some and the less extreme forms of dependency of others. We are all dependent on others. Understanding this fact is crucial for keeping in perspective the fragility of the human condition, for helping us realize and appreciate our dependence on others in myriad ways over the course of a life, and for helping us dispel the fiction of independence and self-reliance that has infected and distorted much political thought. That is, the complete dependency of some should not be viewed as a special case or unique problem that liberals must somehow address in a theory of justice for persons who are overwhelmingly independent and self-reliant; rather, liberals must view persons as always dependent on others in some ways and sometimes dependent on others in other ways. They must determine what justice requires for persons in such relationships and what sorts of dependency relations are incompatible with justice.
Following our general discussion of dependency, we consider how Rousseau, a figure from whom many liberals draw insights, was deeply concerned with dependency relations and how such relations may lead to inequality. We are interested in developing Rousseauā€™s concern for dependency to consider how relational egalitarians are well situated to answer the dependency critique. Rousseau may seem like an especially odd choice for drawing inspiration to respond to a feminist critique. After all, his views on women are abhorrent.9 Nonetheless, nothing in his critique of inequality depends upon the sexist views he expresses in his work, and we find the core of his critique concerning the connections between inequality, dependency, and injustice to be trenchant and illuminating. We develop his critique of inequality as a useful, but incomplete, model for thinking about how dependency relations can lead to systematic inequalities that instantiate relationships of domination and subordination (as a form of injustice). In particular, we draw on Rousseauā€™s insights concerning the need for recognition respect as central to social equality and his insights concerning the way in which social arrangements can construct and create dependency.
With Rousseauā€™s account explained, we extend and develop his views to consider forms of dependency that were not of concern to him, as our interest in social institutions and practices and their relation to dependency and domination has a much broader focus than his. We aim to show how social arrangements and institutions can construct dependencies that place persons in relationships in which they are socially subordinated and, hence, unequal in unjust ways. In the final section of the chapter, we highlight the critical features of relational egalitarian views that we think demonstrate their usefulness for thinking about dependency relations as a central concern of justice. To the extent the arguments we provide are persuasive, we hope to make some headway in addressing the worry that liberal theories do not have the resources necessary for recognizing and addressing the facts of human dependency that are a matter of justice.

Dependency

Again, all human beings are needy and vulnerable, but not all persons are dependent in the same ways and to the same degree. We do not aim to offer a full account of the basic needs and interests of persons that are a matter of justice. Nor do we aim to offer a full account of the ways in which persons depend on others for interests that are relevant to justice. Here we simply discuss some basic needs and interests relevant to justice, including, for example, recognition respect, and we consider some types of dependency as we consider how dependency relates to justice.
All human beings depend on others to meet their basic needs as children; some, later in life, depend on others, again, for help with their basic needs; some human beings are always dependent on others for help with basic needs. The fact that persons must rely upon others for having some of their basic needs met is an important source of dependency relations among persons.10 When persons think of basic needs, they tend to think of needs having to do with nutrition, health care, mobility, bathing and grooming, and shelter. Sometimes, those who are completely dependent on others for meeting these particular needs are viewed as ā€œdependentā€ and contrasted with others who are viewed as ā€œindependent.ā€ As we note in the introduction, this way of thinking is problematic. It is false, and it leads us to mischaracterize our condition. Furthermore, the contrast for the sake of emphasizing the needs of the most vulnerable has not been effective or helpful for securing justice for them.
Beyond the most basic of needs, persons have interests in social and moral goods. Children need a great deal of social and emotional care as they develop into adults, and they are dependent on others for this. Adults, too, depend on others for emotional care, and certain types of social relationships are central to many views of a good human life.11 We depend on others in social relationships in which these interests are met. Again, for children moral education and support for the development of their moral capacities are essential; they are dependent on others for this. Also, as we noted in the introduction, recognition respect among persons requires mutual acknowledgment of personsā€™ equal standing and authority. In a social relationship of equality, persons depend on each other for recognition, and, together, persons create and maintain the social conditions of recognition respect. Further, insofar as self-esteem and self-respect depend to some extent on social relationships with others, persons are partially dependent on others for these as well and for the social conditions on which they depend.
Crucially, the way in which the social world is constructed matters for how (and sometimes if) specific dependency relations arise and whether the conditions in which they take place are just. The aspects of dependency relations that have fostered the most reflection from liberal political philosophers concern the fact that human beings must cooperate to satisfy their needs. Social cooperation requires assistance from and reliance upon others in the context of mutual exchange. Thus, cooperation creates forms of interdependence among persons. For example, in modern democratic states, individuals are dependent on othersā€™ labor for the production of goods and services necessary for their survival, such as food and shelter, and, too, for the goods and services necessary for functioning as free and equal citizens, which take us much beyond basic needs. In modern democracies, arguably the interests of persons as citizens include, inter alia, education, certain types of opportunities, and access to civil society. Complex and extensive cooperative systems are necessary for the satisfaction of such interests. The choice or development of some particular institution (or set of institutions), rather than others, creates and shapes the kinds and degrees of dependencies present in society. For example, the accessibility of labor market firms with respect to infrastructure, technology, and business practices determines who can participate in the interdependent relations of the labor market and who cannot, which creates certain types of asymmetric dependencies. Or, consider that the frameworks, or lack thereof, for providing childcare assistance to those responsible for the care of children determine the kind and degree of dependency of caretakers on others.
Whether persons are asymmetrically or mutually dependent on others, they are vulnerable to them. Relying on another for the satisfaction of oneā€™s needs and interests leaves one in a position in which one is at risk of harm. While some types of dependency are inevitable (e.g., an infantā€™s dependency on a caretaker), other types are not (e.g., a blind personā€™s dependence on others in a social world designed only for the sighted). But, all dependency relationships are social relationships. All social relationships occur in a context of norms, roles, practices, and institutions that bear on these social relations. For example, an infant is utterly and inevitably dependent on a caretaker for having physical, social, and emotional needs met. However, norms, roles, practices, and institutions bear on how the infantā€™s needs and interests are understood and how they are addressed. Social norms, roles, practices, and institutions also bear on how a caretakerā€™s work is understood, valued, and supported.
The kind of equality central to relational egalitarianism is incompatible with certain types of dependency relationships and with some ways of structurin...

Table of contents

  1. Cover
  2. Half Title
  3. Series
  4. Title
  5. Copyright
  6. Dedication
  7. Contents
  8. Acknowledgments
  9. Introduction to Caring for Liberalism
  10. Part I Historical Sources
  11. Part II Individualism and Autonomy
  12. Part III Working With Rawls
  13. Part IV Policy and the Design of Institutions
  14. List of Contributors
  15. Index