Getting Our Act Together
eBook - ePub

Getting Our Act Together

A Theory of Collective Moral Obligations

  1. 174 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Getting Our Act Together

A Theory of Collective Moral Obligations

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

Winner of the 2022 North American Society for Social Philosophy Book Award

Together we can often achieve things that are impossible to do on our own. We can prevent something bad from happening, or we can produce something good, even if none of us could do it by ourselves. But when are we morally required to do something of moral importance together with others?

This book develops an original theory of collective moral obligations. These are obligations that individual moral agents hold jointly but not as unified collective agents. The theory does not stipulate a new type of moral obligation but rather suggests that to think of some of our obligations as joint or collective is the best way of making sense of our intuitions regarding collective moral action problems. Where we have reason to believe that our efforts are most efficient as part of a collective endeavor, we may incur collective obligations together with others who are similarly placed as long as we are able to establish compossible individual contributory strategies towards that goal. The book concludes with a discussion of 'massively shared obligations' to major-scale moral problems such as global poverty.

Getting Out Act Together: A Theory of Collective Moral Obligations will appeal to researchers and advanced students working in moral, political and social philosophy, philosophy of action, social epistemology and philosophy of social science.

Frequently asked questions

Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Yes, you can access Getting Our Act Together by Anne Schwenkenbecher in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Philosophy & Ethics & Moral Philosophy. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Publisher
Routledge
Year
2020
ISBN
9781000290929

1
Collective Obligations in a Nutshell

The philosophical literature on collective agency, collective responsibility, social epistemology and social ontology is burgeoning. Scholarly interest in ‘collective’ phenomena and theories reflects a persistent desire to tackle an old conundrum – the relationship between individual agents and the collectives they compose. The problem of reconciling these two perspectives is not one for philosophy alone.1 There is a notable shift away from a strict individualism towards theories that reflect the fundamentally social, cooperative nature of human activities.
This book attempts to shed light on the issue of collective moral obligations – that is, obligations that individuals in loose groups (as opposed to group agents) may have together.2 I take moral obligations to be a basic feature of our moral repertoire. Put in the simplest possible terms, there are things we ought and things we ought not to do.3 For instance, we ought not to harm others without good reason and we ought to assist those in need. Further, we might want to distinguish between pro tanto and all-out obligations. Pro tanto obligations are demands on us that give us some reason to act but which can be overridden by other, more important reasons. All-out obligations are those we ought to meet all-things-considered, taking all the different moral considerations into account.
In this first chapter, I will give a brief account of my approach to collective obligations and I will sketch some of my core arguments. Subsequent chapters will provide in-depth discussion of the various contentious issues as well as a comprehensive defence of my view against rival views.

1.1 The Starting Point

I argue that our moral obligations (pro tanto and all-out) can sometimes be collective in nature. By this I mean that moral obligations can jointly attach to two or more agents in that neither agent has that obligation on its own, but they – in some sense – share it or have it in common. To have a collective obligation is a plural moral predicate much like to play a duet is a plural non-moral predicate. I will explain this in more detail later.
I believe that the notion of collective moral obligations fills a conceptual gap in philosophy. In a sense, one could say that moral philosophy has traditionally been concerned with the question “what ought I to do?”,4 while what we ought to do as communities has been the focus of political philosophy. But some of the things that we together can (and potentially ought to) do may be neither the political communities’ responsibility nor straightforward individual obligations. Furthermore, even where some desirable goal or action is primarily the political community’s responsibility, as a matter of fact, political agents (e.g. states and their institutions) often fall short of meeting their obligations. In either case, there may be groups of individual agents who can step up and produce the desired outcomes or perform the required actions. Examples include our joint ability to overcome collective action problems even in the absence of state action, such as closing (or reducing) the so-called global emissions gap (Blok et al. 2012; Wynes and Nicholas 2017). On a national scale, our ability to produce herd immunity against some infectious disease should be seen as collective. I will come back to these examples at the end of the chapter. My starting point will be a simpler, small-scale, real-world example of spontaneous collaboration between complete strangers:
[Motorcyclist] Ten passersby witness a car accident in which a motor-cyclist gets trapped underneath a car, which has caught fire on one side. Somebody has to act very quickly to pull him out the other side and in order to do so the car will need to be ever so slightly lifted. None of the passersby can lift the car on their own and pull the man out, but together they can (without taking any undue risks to their own health and safety). As it happened, the people manage to lift the car and save the motorcyclist’s life.5
For the sake of argument, let us assume that the following is the case: it is obvious to the witnesses of the accident that the man is in imminent danger, and it is fairly clear what needs to be done to get him out of danger.
There are several scholars who argue that under circumstances such as these individual moral agents can be under a collective obligation (or have collective responsibility) to assist (Held 1970; May 1992; Wringe 2005; Miller 2010; Wringe 2010; Isaacs 2011; Schwenkenbecher 2013 b; Pinkert 2014; Schwenkenbecher 2014 b; Wringe 2016; Schwenkenbecher 2019). Collective obligations, on their accounts, are distinct from and not reducible to individual obligations (to contribute to cooperative ventures, for instance).
In the following, I will distinguish different ways of spelling out such collective obligations. But before I do so, let me briefly talk about why anyone might think that we need the notion of collective obligations. One of the starting points of many debates on collective obligations is the observation that in cases like the one earlier, in order to produce the morally best outcome, or in order to perform the action most likely to secure that outcome, individual agents need to cooperate with one another and coordinate their individual actions. It takes more than one person’s effort to make a difference to the person in need.
More generally, there is a class of actions (and outcomes) that cannot be performed (or produced) by one person on their own. They require at least two people in order to be realised, and no one individual agent can guarantee the success of the collective endeavour. These cases are char-acterised by ‘joint necessity’.6 Playing a duet is a joint-necessity type of activity. By definition, it cannot be done by one person. Another example is ‘talking past one another’. Joint necessity can be analytic (as in the two examples just given), where it is part of what it means to do x that x is done by at least two people. Or joint necessity can be circumstantial, where as a matter of fact (rather than as a matter of principle) something cannot be done by one person – for instance, if it takes two or more people to lift a heavy table (or a car, for that matter).
We can further distinguish between strict and wide joint necessity.7 For strict joint necessity to apply, the number of available contributors to a collective outcome equals the number of contributors minimally necessary to produce it. What it means to be an available contributor would depend on the outcome in question. For the motorbike accident described earlier, it would mean anyone close enough to see what is happening and able to make some kind of contribution. For strict joint necessity, the success of the joint venture is counterfactually dependent on each available contributor playing their part. It is entirely within my power to stymie any efforts of our duet playing, and the same applies to you.
Wide joint necessity applies where there are more available contributors to a joint outcome than minimally necessary. There are many large-scale examples of wide joint necessity, such as producing herd immunity (against a certain infectious disease), bridging the emissions gap (UNEP 2017) or producing a referendum outcome in favour of marriage equality. In order for herd immunity against a particular communicable disease to be achieved, it is not necessary that everyone who can safely be vaccinated should be in fact vaccinated. Depending on the disease, the figure may be around 90%. What this means is that, in contrast to strict joint-necessity cases, my unilateral defection in a wide joint-necessity case does not guarantee collective failure and neither does yours. This might lead someone to the conclusion that therefore individual obligations to contribute to such goods are always less stringent. But I think this would be the wrong conclusion to draw, as I shall show later.
In many joint-necessity scenarios, something morally important is at stake. Especially where lives are in imminent danger, people tend to share the intuition that those who could help ought to do so; for example, those witnessing the motorbike accident ought to assist the trapped person. But this common intuition may create a dilemma, because no individual can guarantee the success of the joint endeavour (or produce the desired collective good).8 That is, individually, none of these passers-by can assist the trapped motorcyclist. Hence, it cannot be any individual agent’s obligation to rescue him. They can only help jointly. So, whose obligation is it? We might want to say that it is the obligation of all of them together. But what does that mean? Is it the ‘group’ of passers-by that has the obligation to assist? Or is there ‘merely’ an obligation on each of us to do our best, given others’ actions? The answer is not straightforward. In my view, this impasse is regularly felt when we try to make moral decisions: it is the pull between the individualist option (to do something that is under one’s individual control only) and the collectivist option (where the success of one’s actions often depends on others’ contributions).
Scholars have chosen different routes to answer the question about the locus of moral obligation in joint-necessity cases. Roughly, they can be divided into two groups, which I will call ‘conservatives’ and ‘revisionists’. Revisionist scholars will usually introduce new moral vocabulary and concepts to fill what they believe to be a gap in traditional moral theorising where joint necessity is concerned. Many argue that there is some kind of group-level obligation (or responsibility) that applies to loose collections of individuals such as the passers-by in scenarios like our exemplary case (Held 1970; May 1992; Wringe 2010; Isaacs 2011). Other revisionists, including myself, speak of individuals holding joint obligations (Miller 2010; Schwenkenbecher 2013 b; Pinkert 2014; Schwenkenbecher 2014 b; Schwenkenbecher 2019) or sharing obligations (Björnsson 2014). Conservative scholars, in contrast, do not see the need for new conceptual tools but attempt to resolve collective action puzzles in a way that is maximally continuous with existing theory. They tend to argue that joint-necessity cases give rise to (perhaps slightly more complex than usual) contributory duties only. According to Parfit, for instance, each of the individual passers-by simply has an obligation to contribute if she thinks that enough others contribute to get the joint endeavour off the ground (Parfit 1984). Collins and Lawford-Smith would argue that each ought to take steps towards forming a group that can then act as an agent (Collins 2013; Lawford-Smith 2015), though Collins’ view has shifted and in her latest work she appears to endorse a more revisionist approach (2019).
I will discuss the merits of these different types of approaches in more detail in Chapter 6. The obvious downside of the conservative approach is that the obligation to produce the collective good (or to realise the joint endeavour) is not allocated. In our example, then, there is no obligation to free the trapped motorcyclist, even though individual agents have obligations to contribute.9 Holly Lawford-Smith acknowledges this problem for the conservative approach but bites the bullet because she thinks the advantages of this approach still outweigh its disadvantages (2015). In contrast, the obvious downside of the first type of revisionist approach is this: it seems to be built on the assumption that there is a (novel) entity, a group agent of sorts, that not only can act on the problem at hand but has a sufficient level of unity such that it can hold a moral obligation (or be held morally responsible). Revisionist scholars have tried to avoid this kind of criticism by arguing that being an agent is not a necessary condition for being the bearer of a moral obligation as far as groups (or collections of agents) are concerned (Wringe 2010).
However, my aim here is not to give an overview of the literature but to instead flesh out my own (revisionist) approach to collective obligations and show how it applies in a range of cases.10 This approach, while revisionist, avoids the objection sketched earlier by refraining from postulating a group agent (even a putative or potential one) and instead conceiving of the obligations to assist in joint-necessity cases as shared or ‘joint’.

1.2 Jointly Held Obligations

What does it mean to say that a number of agents jointly hold a moral obligation? On my view, collective obligations are not a novel type of obligation but moral obligations held in a collective mode: I can individually hold an obligation to do x or we (for instance, you and I) can jointly hold an obligation to do x (for instance, where x is only collectively feasible). To jointly hold an obligation is a plural predicate – it can only meaningfully apply to two or more agents, very much like other (non-moral) plural predicates such as ‘playing a duet’ or ‘walking past one another’. On this approach, the obligation that the passers-by in our example assist the trapped driver is a joint obligation; they hold it together.
Joint obligations give rise to further individual obligations. If you and I jointly have an obligation to lift a heavy table, then each of us has an individual obligation to do our part or make an effort towards the joint endeavour. But joint obligations do not reduce to individual obligations to play our part. In order to see why, let us return to wide joint-necessity cases, where we have more potential contributors than minimally necessary for the success of the collective performance. Suppose that it takes two people to lift a heavy table, but three potential contributors are available. Suppose further that two is also the maximum number of people who can successfully lift the table together, because of the way each needs to position themselves to lift it. So out of the three potential contributors only two should act. It cannot be the case that each of the three has an obligation to act (because a three-way effort will not succeed). Neither should we think that any combination of two people (out of the three) is obligated to contribute. Because if we did, we would either (i) arrive at an impasse where we could not say exactly which two people have these obligations (i...

Table of contents

  1. Cover
  2. Half Title
  3. Series Page
  4. Title Page
  5. Copyright Page
  6. Contents
  7. Acknowledgements
  8. Introduction
  9. 1 Collective Obligations in a Nutshell
  10. 2 Joint Oughts and the Agency Principle
  11. 3 Joint Ability and ‘Ought’ Implies ‘Can’ for Pluralities of Agents
  12. 4 Knowing When We Have Collective Moral Obligations
  13. 5 What Collective Obligations Mean for Individual Agents: Contributory Obligations, Non-compliance and Joint Blameworthiness
  14. 6 A Comparison of Existing Accounts of Collective Obligations
  15. 7 Massively Shared Obligations and Global Poverty
  16. Conclusion
  17. Glossary
  18. References
  19. Index