Scientific Autobiography
eBook - ePub

Scientific Autobiography

And Other Papers

  1. 196 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Scientific Autobiography

And Other Papers

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

In this fascinating autobiography from one of the foremost geniuses of twentieth-century physics, Max Planck tells the story of his life, his aims, and his thinking. Published posthumously, the papers in this volume were written for the general reader and make accessible Planck's scientific theories as well as his philosophical ideals, including his thoughts on ethics and morals.

Frequently asked questions

Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Yes, you can access Scientific Autobiography by Max Planck in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Technology & Engineering & Science & Technology Biographies. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.
The Meaning and Limits of Exact Science 3
EXACT SCIENCE—what wealth of connotation these two words have! They conjure up a vision of a lofty structure, of imperishable slabs of stone firmly joined together, treasure-house of all wisdom, symbol and promise of the coveted goal for a human race thirsting for knowledge, longing for the final revelation of truth. And since knowledge always means power, too, with every new insight that Man gains into the forces at work in Nature, he always opens up also a new gateway to an ultimate mastery over them, to the possibility of harnessing these natural forces and making them obey his every command.
But this is not all—nor even the most important part of it. Man wants not only knowledge and power. He wants also a standard, a measure of his actions, a criterion of what is valuable and what is worthless. He wants an ideology and philosophy of life, to assure him of the greatest good on earth —peace of mind. And if religion fails to satisfy his longing, he will seek a substitute in exact science. I refer here merely to the endeavors of Monism, founded by outstanding scholars, philosophers and natural scientists, a school of thought which commanded high respect only as recently as a short generation ago.
Yet, in these our days hardly a word is being heard about the Monists, although the structure of their ideology was unquestionably erected to endure for a long time to come, and it started out on its career with high hopes and great promises. There must be something wrong somewhere! And in fact, if we take a closer look and scrutinize the edifice of exact science more intently, we must very soon become aware of the fact that it has a dangerously weak point—namely, its very foundation. Its foundation is not braced, reinforced properly, in every direction, so as to enable it to withstand external strains and stresses. In other words, exact science is not built on any principle of such universal validity, and at the same time of such portentous meaning, as to be fit to support the edifice properly. To be sure, exact science relies everywhere on exact measurements and figures, and is therefore fully entitled to bear its proud name, for the laws of logic and mathematics must undoubtedly be regarded as reliable. But even the keenest logic and the most exact mathematical calculation cannot produce a single fruitful result in the absence of a premise of unerring accuracy. Nothing can be gained from nothing.
No phrase has ever engendered more misunderstanding and confusion in the world of scholars than the expression, “Science without Presuppositions.” It was coined originally by Theodor Mommsen, and was meant to express that scientific analysis and research must steer clear of every preconceived opinion. But it could not be, nor was it, intended to mean that scientific research needs no presuppositions at all. Scientific thought must link itself to something, and the big question is, where. This question has occupied the minds of the most profound thinkers of all epochs and all nations, since time immemorial, from Thales to Hegel, setting in motion all forces of man’s imagination and logic. But it has been demonstrated again and again that a final, conclusive answer cannot be found. Perhaps the most impressive proof of this negative finding is that until now all attempts have failed to discover a world view uniformly acceptable, in its general features at least, by all minds capable of judgment. The only conclusion which this fact permits, according to every dictate of reason, is that it is absolutely impossible to place exact science in an a priori manner on a universal foundation possessing a fixed and inclusive content.
Thus, at the very outset of our quest for the meaning of exact science, we are confronted by an obstacle which must be a disappointment to everybody who is seriously striving for knowledge. In fact, this obstacle has driven many a critically disposed thinker to join the ranks of the skeptics. And a no less regrettable fact is that there are perhaps just as many, or even more, individuals of the opposite disposition whom the fear of falling victims to skepticism—an ideology which they consider intolerable—drives to look for salvation to prophets of creeds like, for instance, anthroposophy. Such prophets appear on the scene in all epochs, not excepting our own, with their brand new message of salvation, and they often succeed, with an amazing rapidity, in gathering a following of enthusiastic disciples, eventually to make their exit from the stage and to sink back into the all-engulfing abyss of oblivion.
Is there a way out of this fatal dilemma? And where can it be found? This is the first question to claim our attention. I shall attempt to show that there is a positive answer to it, and that this answer will cast a light both on the meaning and limits of exact science. I submit to the judgment of each of you the validity of my proposed resolution of the problem.
I.
If we seek a foundation for the edifice of exact science which is capable of withstanding every criticism, we must first of all tone down our demands considerably. We must not expect to succeed at a stroke, by one single lucky idea, in hitting on an axiom of universal validity, to permit us to develop, with exact methods, a complete scientific structure. We must be satisfied initially to discover some form of truth which no skepticism can attack. In other words, we must set our sights not on what we would like to know, but first on what we do know with certainty.
Now then, among all the facts that we do know and can report to each other, which is the one that is absolutely the most certain, the one that is not open even to the most minute doubt? This question admits of but one answer: “That which we experience with our own body.” And since exact science deals with the exploration of the outside world, we may immediately go on to say: “They are the impressions we receive in life from the outside world directly through our sense organs, the eyes, ears, etc.” If we see, hear or touch something, it is clearly a given fact which no skeptic can endanger.
To be sure, we speak also of illusions, but never with the intention of implying that the sense perceptions involved are incorrect or even questionable. For instance, when a person happens to be deceived by a mirage, the fault lies not with his perception of the visual image, which is actually present, but in his inferences which draw false conclusions from the given sensory data. The sensory impression is always a given fact, and therefore incontestable. What conclusions the individual attaches to it, is another story, which need not concern us for the time being. Therefore, the content of the sensory impressions is the most suitable and only unassailable foundation on which to build the structure of exact science.
If we call the sum total of sensory impressions “the sense world,” we may state briefly that exact science issues from the experienced sense world. The sense world is that which, so to speak, furnishes science with the raw material for its labors.
However, this seems to be a very meager result. For the content of the sense world is, in any case, only something of a subjective character. Every individual has his own senses, and in general, the senses of one individual are quite different from those of another, whereas the aim of exact science is to achieve objective, universally valid knowledge. It may seem, therefore, that in adopting our present approach we have been following the wrong track.
But we must not jump to conclusions. For it will become manifest that considerable progress can be made along the line of advance now open to us. Considered as a whole, the matter reduces itself to the fact that we human beings have no direct access to the knowledge conveyed to us by exact science, but must acquire it one by one, step by step, at the cost of painstaking labors of years and centuries.
Now, if we examine the content of our sense world, it obviously falls apart into as many separate fields as we have sense organs—there is a field corresponding to sight, another to hearing, and still others corresponding to the senses of touch, smell, taste and heat. These fields are totally different from each other, and have initially nothing in common. There is no immediate, direct bridge between the perception of colors and the perception of sounds. An affinity, such as may be assumed by many art lovers to exist between a certain shade of color and a certain musical pitch, is not directly given, but is the creation, stimulated by personal experiences, of our reflective power of imagination.
Since exact science deals with measurable magnitudes, it is concerned primarily with those sensory impressions which admit of quantitative data —in other words, the world of sight, the world of hearing, and the world of touch. These fields supply science with its raw material for study and research, and science goes to work on it with the tools of a logically, mathematically and philosophically disciplined reasoning.
II.
What, then, is the meaning of this work of science? Briefly put, it consists in the task of introducing order and regularity into the wealth of heterogeneous experiences conveyed by the various fields of the sense world. Under closer examination, this task proves to be fully consistent with the task which we are habitually peforming in our lives ever since our earliest infancy, in order to find our way and place in our environment. This is a task which has kept man busy ever since he first began to think at all in order to be able to hold his own in the struggle for existence. Scientific reasoning does not differ from ordinary every-day thinking in kind, but merely in degree of refinement and accuracy, more or less as the performance of the microscope differs from that of the naked eye. The truth of this statement, and that it must necessarily be so, is evident from the very fact that there is only one kind of logic, and, therefore, even scientific logic cannot deduce anything else from given presuppositions than can the ordinary logic of untrained common sense.
We shall therefore obtain an intuitively clear understanding of the results which science achieves through its labors, if we take our point of departure from the experiences known and familiar to us from daily life. If we review our own personal, individual development, and consider the point which our world view has gradually reached in the course of the years, we can say that we are trying to use the facts of experience as the foundation for a unified, comprehensive and practically serviceable picture of the world in which we live; that we conceive the outside world as filled with objects which act on our various sense organs, thus producing our different sensory impressions.
However, since this practical world picture which every human being carries within himself is not a directly given notion, but an idea elaborated gradually on the basis of facts of experience, it is possessed of no final character. It is changed and adjusted by every new datum of experience, from infancy to adulthood, first at a quicker, then at a slower pace. The same principle applies to the scientific world picture. The scientific world picture or the so-called phenomenological world is also not final and constant, but is in a process of constant change and improvement. It differs from the practical world picture of daily life not in kind, but in its finer structure. It is to the world picture of daily life approximately as the world picture of the adult human being is to the world picture of the human child. Therefore the best start toward a correct understanding of the scientific world picture will be to investigate the most primitive world picture, the naive world picture of the child.
Let us, therefore, try to place ourselves, as best we can, in the child’s mind and world of ideas. As soon as the child begins to think, he begins to form his world picture. For this purpose, he directs his attention toward the impressions which he receives through his sense organs. He tries to classify them, and in this endeavor he makes all kinds of discoveries, such as, for instance, that there is a certain orderly interrelation between the inherently different impressions conveyed by the senses of sight, touch and hearing. If you give the child a toy, let us say, a rattle, he will find that the tactile sensation is always accompanied by a corresponding visual sensation, and as he moves the rattle back and forth, he also perceives a certain regular auditory sensation.
While in this instance the different mutually independent sense worlds appear to be interlocking to a certain degree, on other occasions the child will make an observation which he will find to be no less remarkable—that certain impressions which are completely indistinguishable from one another and have their origin in a common sense world, may nevertheless be of a totally different character. Thus, for instance, the child may look at a round electric light and observe that it looks just like the full moon. The light sensation may be exactly the same. Yet, the child finds a great difference, for he can touch the lamp, but not the moon; he can pass his hand around the lamp, but not around the moon.
What, then, does the child think as he makes these discoveries? First of all, he wonders. This feeling of wonderment is the source and inexhaustible fountain-head of his desire for knowledge. It drives the child irresistibly on to solve the mystery, and if in his attempt he encounters a causal relationship, he will not tire of repeating the same experiment ten times, a hundred times, in order to taste the thrill of discovery over and over again. Thus, by a process of incessant labor from day to day, the child eventually develops his world picture, to the degree needed by him in practical life.
The more the child matures, and the more complete his world picture becomes, the less frequently he finds reason to wonder. And when he has grown up, and his world picture has solidified and taken on a certain form, he accepts this picture as a matter of course and ceases to wonder. Is this because the adult has fully fathomed the correlations and the necessity of the structure of his world picture? Nothing could be more erroneous than this idea. No!—The reason why the adult no longer wonders is not because he has solved the riddle of life, but because he has grown accustomed to the laws governing his world picture. But the problem of why these particular laws and no others hold, remains for him just as amazing and inexplicable as for the child. He who does not comprehend this situation, misconstrues its profound significance, and he who has reached the stage where he no longer wonders about anything, merely demonstrates that he has lost the art of reflective reasoning.
Rightly viewed, the real marvel is that we encounter natural laws at all which are the same for men of all races and nations. This is a fact which is by no means a matter of course. And the subsequent marvel is that for the most part these laws have a scope which could not have been anticipated in advance.
Thus, the element of the wondrous in the structure of the world picture increases with the discovery of every new law. This holds true even of scientific research and inquiry in our own day, which continually produce something new. Just think of the mysteries of the cosmic rays, or the mysterious hormones, or the remarkable revelations of the electron microscope. To the research scientist, no less than to the child, it is always a gratifying experience and an added stimulus to encounter a new wonder, and he will labor industriously to solve the riddle by repeating the same experiments with his refined instruments just as the child does with his primitive rattle.
However, let us not leap too far ahead, but proceed in an orderly fashion. First, let us investigate in what respect the structure of the child’s world differs from the sense world as originally given. The first fact to claim our attention is that sensations, the sole and exclusive constituents of the original world picture, have been driven appreciably into the background. The dominant elements of this world picture are not sensations, but the objects which produce them. The toy is the dominant element, and the tactile, visual and auditory sensations are merely secondary consequences. But we would not do full justice to the state of affairs were we to say simply that this world picture is nothing but a synthesis of different sensory impressions achieved with the help of the unifying concept of thing. For, conversely, a single undifferentiated sense experience may correspond to several different objects. An example of this possibility is the previously mentioned case of an illuminated surface which produces in us a definite sensory impression, and yet is sometimes attributed to an electric light while at other times to the full moon. This is a case of a single undifferentiated sensation which corresponds to two different objects. The contrast, therefore, lies deeper, and can be characterized exhaustively only by introducing the concept of an objectively valid regularity. The sensations produced by objects are private, and vary from one individual to another. But the world picture, the world of objects, is the same for all human beings, and we may say that the transition from the sense world to the world picture amounts to a replacement of a disordered subjective manifold by a constant objective order, of chance by law, and of variable appearance by stable substance.
The world of objects, in contrast to the sense world, is therefore called the real world. Yet, one must be careful when using the word, real. It must be taken here in a qualified sense only. For this word has the connotation of something absolutely stable, permanent, immutable, whereas the objects of the child’s world picture could not rightly be claimed to be immutable. The toy is not immutable, it may break or burn. The electric lamp can be smashed to smithereens. This precludes their being called real in the sense just mentioned.
This sounds both self-evident and trivial. But we must bear in mind that in the case of the scientific world picture, where as we have seen, the situation is quite analogous, this state of affairs was by no means found to be self-evident. For just as to the child the toy is the true reality, so for decades and centuries the atoms were taken by science to constitute the true reality in natural processes. The atoms were considered to be that which remains immutable when an object is smashed or burned, thus representing permanency in the midst of all change—until one day, to everybody’s astonishment, it was found that even atoms could change. Therefore, whenever in the sequel we refer to the “real world,” we shall be using the word real primarily in a qualified, naive sense, adjusted to the particular character of the dominant world picture, and we must constantly bear in mind that a change in the world picture may go hand in hand, simultaneously, with that which people call “real.”
Every world picture is characterized by the real elements, of which it is composed. The real world of exact science, the scientific world picture, evolved from the real world of practical life. But even this world picture is not final, but changes all the time, step by step, with every advance of inquiry.
Such a stage of development is represented by that scientific world picture which today we are accustomed to call “classical.” Its real elements, and hence its characteristic feature, were the chemical atoms. In our own day, scientific research, fructified by the theory of relativity and the quantum theory, stands at the threshold of a higher stage of development, ready to mould a new world picture for itself. The real elements of this coming world picture are no longer the chemical atoms, but electrons and protons, whose mutual interactions are governed by the velocity of light and by the elementary quantum of action. From today’s point of view, therefore, we must regard the realism of the classical world picture as naive. But nobody can tell whether some day in the future the same words will not be used in referring to our modern world picture, too.
III.
But what is the meaning of this constant shift in what we call “real”? Is it not utterly unsatisfactory to all men who seek definite scientific insight?
The answer to this question must be, first of all, that our immediate concern is not whether or not the situation is satisfactory, but what its essentials are. But the pursuit of this question will lead to a discovery which we must regard as the greatest of all the wonders previously mentioned. First of all, it must be noted that the continual displacement of one worl...

Table of contents

  1. Cover
  2. Title Page
  3. Contents
  4. Introduction - MEMORIAL ADDRESS
  5. A Scientific Autobiography
  6. Phantom Problems in Science
  7. The Meaning and Limits of Exact Science
  8. The Concept of Causality in Physics
  9. Religion and Natural Science
  10. Notes
  11. Copyright