SUNY series in Contemporary Continental Philosophy
eBook - ePub

SUNY series in Contemporary Continental Philosophy

From Cinema to the Digital Revolution

  1. 166 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

SUNY series in Contemporary Continental Philosophy

From Cinema to the Digital Revolution

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

In The Flesh of Images, Mauro Carbone analyzed Merleau-Ponty's interest in film and modern painting as it relates to his aesthetic theory and as it illuminates our contemporary relationship to images. Philosophy-Screens broadens the work undertaken in this earlier book, looking at the ideas of other twentieth-century thinkers concerning the relationship between philosophy and film, and extending that analysis to address our experience of electronic and digital screens in the twenty-first century. In the first part of the book, Carbone examines the ways that Sartre, Merleau-Ponty, Lyotard, and Deleuze grappled with the philosophical significance of cinema as a novel aesthetic medium unfolding in the twentieth century. He then considers the significance of this philosophical framework for understanding the digital revolution, in particular the extent to which we are increasingly and comprehensively connected with screens. Smartphones, tablets, and computers have become a primary referential optical apparatus for everyday life in ways that influence the experience not only of seeing but also of thinking and desiring. Carbone's Philosophy-Screens follows Deleuze's call for "a philosophy-cinema" that can account for these fundamental changes in perception and aesthetic production, and adapts it to twenty-first-century concerns.

Frequently asked questions

Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Yes, you can access SUNY series in Contemporary Continental Philosophy by Mauro Carbone, Marta Nijhuis in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Philosophy & Aesthetics in Philosophy. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Publisher
SUNY Press
Year
2019
ISBN
9781438474663
PART ONE
WHAT IS A “PHILOSOPHY-CINEMA?”
I wasn’t stupid enough to want to create a philosophy of cinema.
—Gilles Deleuze, “The Brain Is the Screen”

1

Sartre and Deleuze via Bergson

Sartre Anticipates Deleuze:
The Cinema, a “Bergsonian Art”
“Together we would like to be the Humpty-Dumpty of philosophy, or its Laurel and Hardy. A philosophy-cinema.” 1 Thus writes Deleuze, referring to himself and to FĂ©lix Guattari, in his “Note to the Italian Edition of The Logic of Sense,” published in 1974. This sentence seems to echo the passage by which, six years earlier, he had finished the Preface to Difference and Repetition: “The time is coming when it will hardly be possible to write a book of philosophy as it has been done for so long: ‘Ah! The old style 
’ The search for a new means of philosophical expression was begun by Nietzsche and must be pursued today in relation to the renewal of certain other arts, such as the theatre or the cinema.”2 In short, Deleuze found that the novelty of cinema implied a renewal of the philosophical questions concerning not only our relationships to ourselves, to the others, to the things, and to the world, but also—and inevitably—concerning philosophy itself: that is, concerning its expressive style and, hence, the very style of its own thinking. Indeed, the question of the “philosophy-cinema” does not belong to a single thinker. Rather, it involves a whole epoch, as the Preface to Difference and Repetition suggested. In this sense, it is a question regarding thinking itself. As such—that is to say, precisely as it concerns a whole epoch—it is not surprising to see it emerge, every now and then, all through that epoch. Actually, also Jean-Paul Sartre, in a posthumously published writing, seems to have come across this question—with the imprudence of his (then) twenties. Apparently, such writing dates back to his last khĂągne3 trimester (1924) or to his first year at the École Normale SupĂ©rieure (1924–25); in any case, well before his first approach to phenomenology, which was to occur about ten years later. The writing’s title is “Apologie pour le cinĂ©ma. DĂ©fense et illustration d’un Art international [Apology for the Cinema. Defense and Illustration of an International Art].”4
The starting point Sartre chose for this writing is what his former philosophy teacher and one of the time’s most influential “masters of thinking”—namely, Emile-Auguste Chartier, better known as Alain—maintained in one of his own 1923 Propos sur l’esthĂ©tique (Thoughts on Aesthetics), significantly titled “L’immobile [Immobility].”
This is how Alain started: “Art expresses human power through immobility. There is no better sign of a soul’s strength than immobility, since the thinking is recognizable in it.”5 He concluded by affirming that “the art of the screen provides an a contrario evidence”6 of this artistic research of immobility, “without even looking for it; for the perpetual movement is the very law of films, not only because speech is lacking completely—and it becomes clear that to be mute from birth does not mean to keep silent—but most of all because the actor feels obliged to be restless, as if to pay homage to the mechanical invention.”7
In short, this is roughly the syllogism proposed by Alain: if all art is a “search of immobility in movement,”8 and if—as we just read—“the perpetual movement is the very law of films,” then “the art of the screen” is not an actual art.
The young Sartre highlights that he traces in Alain’s question “the elements [of a problem] that is far more important than the sterile discussions of someone like Winckelmann: does [beauty consist] in immobility or rather in change?”9 Indeed, for Sartre, the most important problem is raised by the passage in which we heard Alain affirm that thinking is recognizable in immobility. In reconsidering this question, Sartre gives it a significant twist. Alain’s thesis suggested that thinking is, by its very essence, recognizable in immobility. In Sartre’s opinion, such a thesis expresses the attachment (the word he uses is, precisely, attached [attachĂ©]) of the human mind “to what is motionless, and not only in aesthetics.”10 Sartre hence explains that “[i]t is [easier to understand] the immutable. In particular, it is easier to love what does not change, and one tries to blind one’s self to this point: ‘You have not changed. You still look the same.’ ”11 It is not hard to trace, in this sentence, some underlying Bergsonian echoes—which will later be confirmed—concerning the interpretation of our practical life.
Sartre hence seems to suggest that Platonism understood as the thinking of Being meant as endurance consists precisely in this effort to blind one’s self. Still, “a new philosophy has dethroned that of the immutable Ideas,”12 he claims. However, he only names it a few lines farther. “At the moment, there is no reality outside change. Will aesthetics not benefit from this?”13 Such a question allows Sartre to introduce his reflection on the cinema, for—as he will explain further—the cinema “inaugurates mobility in aesthetics.”14
It looks as if we could synthesize things as follows: for Sartre, the cinema—by inaugurating mobility in aesthetics—has helped to unveil the fact that the supposed acknowledgment of thinking’s essence in what is motionless was but an attachment to what is “easier.” Hence, the cinema questions philosophy itself, for it “dethrones” Platonism and literally gets us thinking anew. Or rather, what shall be thought anew imposes onto philosophy, no less inevitably, the responsibility to think of itself as a “philosophy-cinema,” we might say echoing Deleuze.
Yet, there is more. To Alain’s dismissive judgment apropos of the cinema’s mutism, Sartre responds as follows: “We are closer to non-speaking actors, who do in fact sing, and their song (I mean, that of the violins) signifies much better whatever they may say [
] does better than just teaching us what Mary Pickford thinks, since it makes us think as she does.”15
On this basis, he hence recurs “to some Bergsonian passages,”16 in which one can notice the repeated reference to the melody as an example of composed and yet undecomposable movement. Indeed, it is through these passages by the grand philosopher that the young student aims at “making understand that a film, with its sound accompaniment, is a consciousness like ours.”17 In other words—as in the case of a melody—it is “an indivisible flow.”18 Besides, in the previous lines, Sartre had already declared that, since it “inaugurates mobility in aesthetics,” “the cinema provides the formula of a Bergsonian art.”19 Thus, he unveiled the identity of the “new philosophy” to which he was referring, and, by such means, he claimed something that, surprisingly enough, would anticipate in one single shot the double action by which, in 1983, Deleuze would begin, in his turn, the Movement-Image.
Indeed, the first chapter of this book by Deleuze appeared to be in accordance with the substance of the Sartrean judgment. At the same time, it implicitly reminded us that Bergson himself would have never allowed such a judgment, for it was he who, in Creative Evolution (1907), matched the “typical example of false movement”20 precisely with the cinema, which had then been born only a dozen years earlier and, still according to Bergson, claimed to reconstruct movement itself as a sum of “immobile sections and abstract time.”21
The problem is raised, first of all, by the fact that in a movie, as we know, at each second comes a succession of a certain number of photograms—between sixteen and eighteen at the time of silent pictures, later twenty-four. Such photograms are spaced by as many instants of black, which remain unperceived by the spectator. In fact, each of these motionless photograms is separated from the others by such an exiguous temporal gap that the ensemble we perceive creates an impression of continuity.
Sartre seems to refer precisely to this question when, in his “Apologie pour le cinĂ©ma,” he writes: “You may even consider it [the film] as a roll of motionless negatives; this is no more a film than the water from the tank is the water from the source, or a consciousness divided by associationism is the actual consciousness.”22 Convinced that one may say about the film what Bergson claimed apropos of the melody—and suggesting a little further that their respective indivisibility is one and the same with the rhythm that characterizes both23—the young Sartre peremptorily stresses that “[t]he essence of the film is in mobility and in duration.”24
About sixty years later, it is Deleuze who will proceed in a similar direction, by recurring precisely to Bergson so as to criticize the judgment on cinema, which Bergson himself had expressed in Creative Evolution: “Cinema does not give us an image to which movement is added, it immediately gives us a movement-image.”25 Deleuze also makes clear that this is the movement-image Bergson himself had discovered—in the first chapter of Matter and Memory—as he overcame the opposition between “[m]ovement, as physical reality in the external world, and the image, as psychic reality in consciousness.”26
Sartre Quits Bergsonianism and Film Theory
However, the parallel between the young Sartre’s path and that of Deleuze’s book comes to an end here, for they will move on in opposite directions. Starting from 1933, Sartre will discover Husserl’s phenomenology, which he finds—with respect to his desire to move “toward concreteness”27—more satisfactory than Bergson’s thinking. Of course, such concreteness includes that of images.28 As for Deleuze, he will describe Bergson’s and Husserl’s paths as two antagonist replies to the same historical need “to overcome this duality of image and movement, of consciousness and thing.”29 As is well known, he will then take sides in favor of Bergson’s reply against Husserl’s. Hence, if the editors of the young Sartre’s “Bergsonian” text considered it as a “pre-phenomenological”30 writing, Deleuze rather qualifies the position Sartre assumed after the encounter with phenomenology in ter...

Table of contents

  1. Cover
  2. Title
  3. Copyright
  4. Contents
  5. List of Illustrations
  6. Preface: In The Light of Our Screens
  7. Acknowledgments
  8. Part One: What Is a “Philosophy-Cinema?”
  9. Part Two: The Animated Life of Screens
  10. Notes
  11. Index
  12. Back Cover