A Philosophical Defense of Misanthropy
eBook - ePub

A Philosophical Defense of Misanthropy

  1. 124 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

A Philosophical Defense of Misanthropy

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

This book argues that it can be both reasonable and appropriate to adopt a certain kind of misanthropy. The author defends a cognitivist version of misanthropy, an attitude whose central feature is the judgment that humanity is morally bad.

Misanthropy is often dismissed on moral grounds. Many people hold that malice toward human persons is problematic and vulnerable to moral objections. In this book, the author advocates for cognitivist misanthropy. He defends an Asymmetry Thesis, according to which a morally bad deed carries more weight than a morally good deed, even if the harm of the former is exactly equal to the benefit of the latter. He makes the case that being misanthropic in the cognitivist sense is morally permissible and compatible with a broad range of moral reasons for action. He also considers the role of misanthropy in environmental thought, arguing that charges of misanthropy against certain "non-anthropocentric" views do not have the force they are typically thought to carry. Finally, the author investigates the practical implications of adopting cognitivist misanthropy, asking what living with such an attitude would involve.

A Philosophical Defense of Misanthropy will appeal to researchers and advanced students working in ethics and the philosophy of human nature.

Frequently asked questions

Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Yes, you can access A Philosophical Defense of Misanthropy by Toby Svoboda in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Philosophy & Ethics & Moral Philosophy. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Publisher
Routledge
Year
2022
ISBN
9781000583724

1 Introducing Misanthropy

DOI: 10.4324/9781003189398-1

Evaluating a Species

Imagine that an orbital probe discovers life on a distant planet and commences observation of that world, transmitting information back to earth. After years of study, it becomes clear that the planet, though rich in biodiversity, is dominated by a single species. As it happens, that species is unquestionably causing a mass extinction event through its activities, and numerous species are dying off with every revolution of that planet around its star. During further study, it becomes clear that the species poses a very high risk of ecological catastrophe that would undermine conditions for complex life on the planet, including that species’ own members.
Let us stop there for a moment and ask how we would judge this situation. I am not asking whether knowledge of mass extinction and ecological catastrophe on a distant planet would sadden us personally. For many, it would no doubt matter very much to their personal lives. Rather, the question is how we would regard this situation if asked to make an honest value judgment about it. After centuries of hoping to discover life elsewhere in the universe, we are immediately faced with its imminent self-destruction. Would we not find this scenario to be unfortunate, regrettable, bad, tragic, or something of the sort? Would we hesitate to identify this species as malignant, much as we regard an invasive species on earth that threatens native species?
Now suppose that we discover the dominant species to be highly intelligent. It is capable of complex decision-making, learning from the past and planning for the future. This is not, say, some animal species that lives moment to moment, constantly searching for food and other means of survival, lacking the cognitive means to think about the distant future. Consequently, the species is aware that it is causing mass extinction and threatening the survival of complex life on the planet. Moreover, thanks to our effective probe, we learn that the species not only is aware of these problems but also understands their causes and has identified effective measures of greatly reducing the risks in the future. However, we observe that the species largely declines to pursue these measures, aside from small gestures here and there.
Let us stop again to assess the situation. The natural question, of course, is why the dominant species would decline to address an existential risk to itself and complex life on its planet. We have a species that is in the process of likely destroying itself and the rest of complex life on its planet. That might be deemed tragic. But then we discover that this same species could likely avert the catastrophe but chooses not to do so. That is puzzling. We would look for possible explanations. Perhaps the species is deeply irrational. Perhaps the only solutions carry unbearable costs, although it is difficult to imagine what those might be in comparison with the extinction of complex life. Perhaps the species has, from our point of view, a very odd biology that prevents it from acting in rational ways. Undoubtedly, we would want to know the answer and so further study is warranted, as they say.
After receiving and analyzing even more data, we have a fuller picture of the planet’s dominant species. As it turns out, the costs of averting catastrophe, though substantial, are rather manageable, and the necessary technology either is already available or likely would be after a serious investment in research. Why then does the species choose not to act? Fortunately, by intercepting various communication signals, our probe allows us to piece together both the history of this species and its current political arrangements. As for the former, we discover that aggression has been common; war and domination drive almost all of the major events of the recorded history of the species. As for the latter, we find that this aggression has not abated, even if the forms it takes have changed to some degree. Specifically, the threat of environmental catastrophe remains unaddressed simply because those with the means to do so prefer not to pay the substantial but manageable costs that are required, prioritizing short-term benefits to themselves over the long-term survival of complex life on the planet. Some members of the species protest, insisting that serious action ought to be taken, but they are dismissed as kooks or smeared as liars. As for the rest, the majority of the species, they simply do not care (very much) about the approaching catastrophe.
How would we regard this species after learning all this? Again, we should do our best to judge honestly, ignoring for now the obvious analogy that I will draw momentarily. It seems clear to me that we would judge the species very harshly. How else to assess the prioritization of short-term enrichment for some at the expense of widespread death, destruction, and extinction? In our speculative example, there is nothing that provides a plausible excuse for the species’ indifference to planet-wide extinction. The costs of action are not prohibitive. The relevant risks and how to reduce them are well understood. Any necessary technology is (or soon could be made) available. There is no strange aspect of the species’ biology that prevents its ability to act. Instead, we have a case in which an intelligent species has chosen to prioritize short-term benefits over the survival of itself and other species, condemning future generations to the ravages of the catastrophe in question. It is hard to conceive of a reasonable defense for this behavior.
Initially, we might think that the species is simply irrational. Even from a purely selfish point of view, the long-term benefits of a decent survival for the species surely outweigh the short-term costs of averting the catastrophe. Although that is probably true from a collective point of view, decisions and cost–benefit analyses are made by individual members of the species—assuming, as we are entitled to do in this fictional case, that this species is composed of discretely conscious individuals. If the goal is to maximize one’s own well-being, then it is not instrumentally irrational for such an individual to prioritize short-term benefits for itself at the cost of catastrophe for others. In ignoring the impending crisis, these individuals are doing what is best for themselves, at least in a narrow economic sense. If this case is objectionable, that is not due to straightforward irrationality.
Our objection to this species would likely be moral in nature. The threat of catastrophe it poses is not only a bad thing: that threat is also morally bad. This is plausible because, given its intelligence, the species is perfectly capable of averting catastrophe. It has all the required knowledge, technology, and wealth, yet it chooses largely to ignore the threat. The reason it makes this choice is that it values short-term benefits for some of its own members over the survival of complex life on the planet. It is difficult to imagine a more obvious case of greed, selfishness, and injustice. Matters would be otherwise if the dangerous species turned out to be one limited in its intelligence or capacity to respond to risks. If something resembling earth’s rodents overpopulated the planet and led to the collapse of the biosphere, we would judge that to be deeply unfortunate and possibly tragic, but we would not blame the rodent-like species for this terrible outcome. Members of such a species are not plausible candidates for moral agents, for they would lack the intelligence needed to understand the risks and the flexibility needed to alter the behavior. In the case I have imagined, however, the dominant species has no such excuse. It knows perfectly well that it risks destroying complex life on its own planet and that the termination of complex life will be preceded by unimaginable harm. It has the capacity to avert that outcome, but it simply shrugs off any serious concern over the matter. Surely this counts as morally reprehensible and perhaps simply evil.
Of course, the parallel here is with our own species. This is not an exaggeration. Homo sapiens is unquestionably an extremely destructive force on earth. It is responsible for an ongoing mass extinction event, causing enormous losses to non-human life. It is altering the climate to an extent and at a rate not seen for millions of years. Anthropogenic climate change poses a genuine risk of ecological catastrophe. Even if we turn out to be very lucky, averting the worst outcomes, there is no question that climate change will bring substantial harm to both human and non-human life. It is already doing so, having created a more dangerous world of rising seas, novel and more frequent extreme weather events, and the like. We may add to this other types of ecological damage for which humanity is responsible, such as ocean acidification, deadly air pollution, and poisoned waterways. Again, all of these cause substantial harm to both human and non-human life. Moreover, on any plausible conception of justice, these ecological harms are obviously unjust to human beings, disproportionately affecting the poor and future generations.
There is hope. These problems are fairly well understood. For example, there is no mystery as to the cause of climate change despite a long campaign of lies from some parties. Likewise, it is fairly clear what must be done in order to avert climatic catastrophe. As always, there are various geophysical, social, and economic uncertainties, but it is nonetheless evident that reducing the risk would involve substantially cutting greenhouse gas emissions, investing in alternative sources of energy, adopting laws and social policies to discourage damaging behavior, and the like. Unfortunately, time is very short, so serious action needs to be taken immediately. How has the species responded so far? Mostly with indifference. To be sure, there are honorable exceptions; some individuals and groups are making the case that the general population and governments should take our ecological crises seriously. Although there have been some relatively modest measures, these fall far short of what is needed. In short, we are aware of the devastation we are causing, and we know how to arrest it, but for the most part we choose not to do so. We are not like the rodent species that can neither understand risks nor change its behavior. Rather, we are like the intelligent species in my imagined case.
This inaction might appear puzzling at first to non-terrestrial observers who are unacquainted with Homo sapiens, but we know the reasons for it perfectly well. Human beings, especially those with the most power and thus the greatest capacity for action, have a very strong preference for short-term benefits to themselves, even if that means risking the destruction of the earth’s biosphere. This might sound like an outlandish claim but it is true. For many years now, politicians have told us with a straight face that serious action on climate change is infeasible because it would hurt something called “the economy.” Given that climate change threatens far-reaching economic damages in the future, this can only refer to the short-term economic interests of some, such as fossil fuel companies worried about quarterly profits or upper middle-class citizens irritated by the prospect of a carbon tax. Other aspects of our ecological crisis, such as mass extinction, barely register on the political scene. Some might say that all this is merely politics, the implication being that we should not bring moral judgments to bear upon political matters. I agree with the first claim, but politics is the venue in which humanity has committed many of its gravest crimes. If anything warrants moral condemnation, it is the march of war, slavery, genocide, and the like that constitutes so much of our political history. Of course, power-seeking political figures would prefer that we not moralize regarding their own corruption and the harm they cause, but I am aware of no reason to grant their wish.
So how should we regard our own species from a moral point of view? It seems to me that our assessment of humanity should be very similar to our assessment of the non-terrestrial species in my imagined case. Because that other species would deserve moral condemnation for its indifference to the catastrophe it causes, our species deserves much the same. Now this is merely an analogy, but at the very least it is enough to ground the reasonableness and plausibility of the misanthropic view that I will develop and defend in the coming chapters.
From a moral point of view, human history has been a great catastrophe. This is rarely acknowledged, but it seems obvious when we attend to the events that historians consider important to the course of civilization. The student of history becomes acquainted with every manner of violence and oppression: war, slavery, genocide, bloody revolution, and the like. These events are often presented via sanitized or exculpatory descriptions, as with the Europeans who “explored” the Americas, but the underlying realities are horrific. To be sure, some historical events do not fit this ugly trend but these are exceptional. Moreover, such events are often mere ameliorations of existing moral ills, as when some case of oppression is reduced or, in rare cases, removed. When we consider current affairs, there is little reason to expect this trend to change. We shall look more closely at these matters in subsequent chapters.
In Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason, Kant famously identifies a “radical evil” in human nature but this is not as exciting as it sounds. Roughly, Kant means by this a propensity in human beings to prioritize their own self-interest over the moral law. Roughly, human beings are naturally inclined to grant more importance to their own gratification than to conducting themselves in a moral fashion. This radical evil does not entail that human beings must be immoral, of course. First, sometimes self-interest and morality are perfectly compatible, such that being a moral person involves no cost. This is common. Most of us abstain from punching strangers in the face, and this is easy to do given that we usually have nothing to gain from assaulting strangers. Second, even when self-interest and morality come into conflict, Kant thinks it is always possible to do the right thing. Or, to be more precise, he thinks that, as a matter of practical reason, we must postulate that we have the freedom that is required to act out of duty rather than inclination. A person who acts in conformity with the moral law, despite her inclination to the contrary, is not free of radical evil in Kant’s sense, for that evil just is the tendency to prioritize self-interest. A being free of radical evil is difficult to imagine. To us it is an alien nature. But such a being would not feel the temptation to deviate from the moral law when doing so is beneficial to itself.
Not unrelated to radical evil is Kant’s distinction between acting from duty and acting merely in accordance with duty. As we have seen, it is often very easy to act in accordance with the moral law, simply because we have no reason to do otherwise. On a normal day, each of us could perform thousands of wrongful actions if we chose, but in many cases there is no benefit to oneself in being unkind, dishonest, unjust, abusive, and so on. But our motivation for according with morality in this way might be merely some non-moral consideration: a wish to get along with others, a desire to be trusted, or something of the sort. The real test comes when being moral bears a cost, for that gives some indication of whether or not the true motive of our typically duty-according actions is esteem for morality itself. Giving into the radical evil of one’s nature is compatible with frequently acting in accordance with one’s duties. For Kant, the genuinely moral action is one that not only accords with the moral law but also proceeds from the right kind of motivation, namely one that involves respect for the moral law itself. We might suspect that, on Kant’s standard, genuinely moral actions would be very rare in our world. Although I will not defend a specifically Kantian view of normative ethics or moral psychology in this book, the idea that genuine morality is rare strikes me as plausible.

Disambiguating “Misanthropy”

Misanthropy gets a bad rap. The term “misanthropy” has various senses. Literally, of course, it means hatred of humanity but that definition is itself ambiguous and does not capture many of the ways in which the term is used. Before considering the case for misanthropy, then, we need to engage in some disambiguation. We shall then be in a position to describe several different views that plausibly count as misanthropic. In later chapters, I will reject some of these, such as those involving genuine hatred, but argue that other misanthropic views are both reasonable and worthy of serious consideration. Let us begin by isolating misanthropy into two components: misos and anthropos. The latter refers to the target of misos, which can be individual humans or humanity in general. I shall have more to say about this throughout this book, especially when it comes to distinguishing between misos for humans in an individual sense versus a collective sense. It will be useful to say something now regarding the nature of misos.
Sometimes a person who merely dislikes other human beings is described as misanthropic. Call this misanthropy as disliking. Such misanthropes harbor a distaste for others, an attitude which may or may not be evident to those others. To count as misanthropy, this disliking cannot be directed solely toward specific persons. One might dislike another for certain idiosyncrasies that one finds grating but this is not sufficient to make one a misanthrope in the present sense—if it were, then virtually everyone would be misanthropic. Aside from simply having an attitude of disliking toward some other persons, genuine misanthropy as disliking seems to require a more general attitude of dislike toward human beings. This type of misanthrope will generally dislike other human beings rather than merely dislike some individuals for their (possibly uncommon) traits or actions. This is perhaps easiest to see in cases in which someone dislikes features that one takes to be common among humans. Our misanthrope here carries a distaste for humans in general because of (allegedly) common features, and although this is compatible with her disliking specific individuals who display those features, the general attitude does not depend on just those individuals. Suppose one dislikes humans in general because he finds them excessively prideful. Naturally, he is liable to dislike specific persons he encounters who seem to him excessively prideful. Imagine, however, that this person discovers that he had misjudged some individual as having this flaw and that his previous dislike toward that person is dissolved. If he is a genuine misanthrope, his dislike of other human beings will remain, for he will have discovered only that some individual does not possess the flaw he still believes to be present in other persons.
A second type of misanthropy is genuine hatred of humans or humanity. Our conception of this type of misanthropy will depend in part on what is meant by hatred. For instance, we might take hatred to be a rather intense form of disliking, such that a misanthrope would be someone who intensely dislikes humans or humanity. But we might instead view hatred as more than intense disliking. Perhaps it involves a voluntary component, such that the misanthrope is someone who wishes ill up...

Table of contents

  1. Cover Page
  2. Half Title Page
  3. Series Page
  4. Title Page
  5. Copyright Page
  6. Dedication
  7. Contents
  8. Acknowledgements
  9. 1 Introducing Misanthropy
  10. 2 The Example of Schopenhauer
  11. 3 The Ethics of Misanthropy
  12. 4 Arguing for Cognitivist Misanthropy
  13. 5 Objections to Cognitivist Misanthropy
  14. 6 Misanthropy and Non-Human Nature
  15. 7 Living as Misanthropists
  16. Bibliography
  17. Index