William Desmond's Philosophy between Metaphysics, Religion, Ethics, and Aesthetics
eBook - ePub

William Desmond's Philosophy between Metaphysics, Religion, Ethics, and Aesthetics

Thinking Metaxologically

  1. English
  2. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  3. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

William Desmond's Philosophy between Metaphysics, Religion, Ethics, and Aesthetics

Thinking Metaxologically

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

This volume collects seventeen new essays by well-established and junior scholars on the philosophical relevance of metaxological philosophy and its main proponent, William Desmond. The volume mines metaxological thought for its salience in contemporary discussions in Continental philosophy, specifically in the fields of metaphysics, philosophy of religion, ethics, and aesthetics. Among others, topics under discussion include the goodness of being, the existence and nature of God, and the aesthetic dimensions of human becoming. Interest in metaxological philosophy has been on the rise in recent years, and this volume provides both a practical introduction and thorough engagements with it by experts in the field. The volume concludes with a series of responses by William Desmond on the issues raised by the contributors.

Frequently asked questions

Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Yes, you can access William Desmond's Philosophy between Metaphysics, Religion, Ethics, and Aesthetics by Dennis Vanden Auweele in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Philosophy & Philosophical Metaphysics. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Year
2018
ISBN
9783319989921
© The Author(s) 2018
Dennis Vanden Auweele (ed.)William Desmond’s Philosophy between Metaphysics, Religion, Ethics, and Aestheticshttps://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-98992-1_1
Begin Abstract

1. Introduction

Dennis Vanden Auweele1
(1)
KU Leuven (University of Leuven), Leuven, Belgium
Dennis Vanden Auweele
End Abstract
Of late, philosophy appears to have become a business of trends, including trend watchers who make us aware of what counts for these days—hot and what not. There are trends that promised to be the next big thing but now seem passĂ© such as deconstruction (which seems to have passed its sell-by date), but also trends that grow from older fads such as neo-Thomism. Nostalgia can be a trend too: endlessly and voraciously scavenging in texts of yore, looking to apply old insights in new contexts. Philosophical trends make philosophy not only a business but also an epochal practice: there is a time for this, and then there is a time for that. What would it mean to stand outside of all of this? How is one ever not in the business of doing philosophy, not in the business of following the latest trends and not in the business of reducing philosophy to its merely epochal concerns? In such a case, one would be an outsider who transcends the business of the day whilst donning a mischievous grin. Culture is replete with images of outsiders, and many believe themselves to be one of these. Perhaps the literary most pronounced outsider is Dostoyevsky’s anonymous protagonist in Notes from the Underground. In raising the middle finger to polite society, he puts himself on the fringes, shamelessly abusing all others. Not coincidentally, Nietzsche felt immediate kinship to Dostoevsky’s most misanthropic character. Both of them were in recognition of the overwhelming strength and authority of the business of the day, but refused to blend smoothly within it: “Of course I cannot break through the wall by battering my head against it if I really have not the strength to knock it down, but I am not going to be reconciled to it simply because it is a stone wall and I have not the strength” (1918, p. 59). I have come to believe that such outsiders are parasitic upon the insider, desperately seeking recognition through their dissidence. Ultimately, these blend into epochs of their own; they will have their day like Schopenhauer who in his old age finally received the recognition he believed to deserve. Nietzsche said of God that He is not now our taste. Are the outsiders Nietzsche , Dostoyevsky or Schopenhauer now our taste? Or have we, as Nietzsche suggests at times, forsaken all discerning taste and have now become voracious gluttons incapable of saving ourselves for the finer things?
For sure, William Desmond is an outsider in the business of philosophy, but not in the same way as the agonal rebellion of a Nietzsche or the nihilism of Dostoevsky’s man of the underground. Desmond’s thought is not parasitic upon existing ways of doing philosophy and not in any trend or business, though he does clearly enjoy kinship with phenomenology and its theological turnings, dialectical philosophy and neo-Thomism. He is this, and more. In a word, William Desmond’s philosophy is metaxology, and metaxology is metaphysics. Metaphysics is not only not now to our taste, but it is not a matter of tastes of trends. Metaphysics is of all times and of none; there is always a time for metaphysics, but no specific time from which to do metaphysics. Perhaps this is the cause of why Desmond has been slow to receive mainstream attention, simply because of standing outside and above such mainstream? Metaphysics is attentive to its own history, but it is not exhausted by its history. This is so because metaphysics must always start again from wonder, which Plato told us is the true beginning of all philosophy. But if wonder is the beginning of philosophy, is there a way for thought to move beyond wonder determinatively? Can we just take wonder as a brief moment of perplexity that can be determinatively overcome by scientific or dialectical thought? Is there a return to wonder after wonder? And is our philosophical attempt at determinacy then not chastised by its inability to cut the cord with wonder?
These are some of the issues that are at the fore of metaxological philosophy: a metaphysical and therefore timeless returning of philosophy to wonder, again and again refreshing thought beyond its self-complacent systematics. These brief introductory pages hope to serve as an initial guide through the maze of metaxological philosophy. Even Dante did not stop short at one guide and neither should the student of metaxology. After our initial descent with Virgil in this introduction (though, hopefully, not into inferno), the chapters to follow serve as the outstretching hand of Beatrice, hoping to ascend from Purgatory towards Paradise. At the end of the book, this guide, too, will have to be left behind. Hopefully, Saint Bernard is awaiting in other work.1
According to a well-known anecdote, Martin Heidegger was once asked which term in the title of his opus magnum Being and Time was most important. His impish response was ‘and’. Metaxology is in some ways similar to Heidegger’s playful response, as its focus is first on intermediation. Metaxology is Greek-English, a logos or speaking from the metaxu or between. But when one says the word ‘between’, one is immediately asked: between what and what? Like Heidegger, Desmond is not primarily interested in the two or more terms to which a relationship should be coordinated (although these surely play a role of importance), but with the very idea of relationality itself. The between is an openness or porosity, a space of passing and communication. In one place, Desmond defines it as “an ontological milieu that is overdeterminate: both indeterminate and determinate, taking form in a plurivocal interplay between otherness and sameness, openness and definition, and yet excessive to final fixation” (EB 1).
What does it mean to philosophize from the between, from this space where different views, ideas and passions transverse? This means that one is attentive to the singular identity of any idea but also the dialectical, even non-dialectical, relationality of things. Philosophy has taken some time to come to think of relationality on a par with identity. In the beginning of philosophy, and even still today in some circles, much of philosophy has fancied its binary oppositions: being and non-being, intelligible and unintelligible, good and evil, and so on. Desmond opposes such easy binary opposition as, borrowing a phrase from Blaise Pascal, an overindulgence in esprit de gĂ©omĂ©trie rather than the subtleness of esprit de finesse. This is unsurprising because Desmond’s initial fame came as a student of Hegel, who was renowned for his search to overcome binary opposition. Hegel’s one-time philosophical compatriot Schelling would even point out that the “main weakness of all modern philosophy” was that it “lacks an intermediate concept” which results in that “everything that does not have being is nothing, and everything that is not spiritual in the highest sense is material in the crudest sense, and everything that is not morally free is mechanical, and everything that is not intelligent is uncomprehending” (2000, p. 64 [286]). To think of reality in terms of simple opposition is simplistic. There is a constant going-over and going-under, a dialectical back and forth between abstract oppositions. All things exceed simple determination in pre-established systems of rationalist intelligibility. With and after Kant, philosophy started to stress relationality and dialectics over simple, univocal determinacy.
Metaxology takes its cues initially from dialectical philosophy, but as one repays a teacher poorly by remaining ever faithful—or so Nietzsche says in Thus spoke Zarathustra2—so Desmond has said his farewells to Hegel after taking his inheritance. He senses there to be something amiss with dialectical thought à la Hegel. The stress is there on dialectical self-determination, which leads easily towards a higher sense of determinate univocity, not fully true to the challenge of thinking otherness as otherness. This is Desmond’s main qualm with Hegel even before Hegel’s God: A Counterfeit Double?3 where God, as the capitalized Other, is turned into the developmental progress of historical self-determination through spirit (Geist). Hegel might have thought that he overcame Kantian dualism by rethinking and revamping the absolute in terms of world history but, in truth, while Hegel might have believed this to be a step forwards, it is not progress. Something of the other as other is lost here, which leaves open the door for a potentially tyrannical appropriation of otherness by means of an over-reaching of dialectical self-mediation. One might even ask if the theodicy of Hegel’s God is one that justifies all on the slaughter bench of history.
This is not the only sense of dialectical philosophy to be sure, as, for instance, the Socratic or Platonic practice of dialogue is more apt to escape potential tyranny. Hegelian dialectics had then a good point of departure, but it did not make it to the finish line unscathed. It is time then perhaps for Hegel, Schelling and even Nietzsche to pass the relay stick to different ways of thinking about the community of being, being good and absolute being. This would have to be a way of thinking that is mindful of (absolute) difference, but open to infinite mediation and revelation. There is intimacy and familiarity in the between, but also mind-boggling strangeness. All of this is to be accounted for as intelligently as possible. In one place, such an approach is described thus: “It lives between peril and crux. As a figuring of the primal ethos, it divines the nature of the togetherness, the absolved relativity, with heed to the difference, and without forgetting the transcendence of the divine and its reserves. We need a finessed, transdialectical logos of the metaxu” (GB 117). In order to come to such a rethinking, we are in need foremost of two things: a phenomenologically robust account of wonder, astonishment and perplexity and a community between philosophy , religion and art.
In a number of places, Desmond outlines what could be called his philosophical method. This is not alike to a methodology that navigates from research question to results—as one is forced to write in ‘research projects’ these days. Instead, this is a method that is wary of the f...

Table of contents

  1. Cover
  2. Front Matter
  3. 1. Introduction
  4. Part I. Being, Knowing and Intimacy
  5. Part II. Absolute Being and Talking God
  6. Part III. Autonomy, Porosity, and Goodness
  7. Part IV. On Wholeness, Hegel and Pan(en)theism
  8. Part V. Creation, Embodied Being and Beauty
  9. Back Matter