The Morality of Radical Economics
eBook - ePub

The Morality of Radical Economics

Ghost Curve Ideology and the Value Neutral Aspect of Neoclassical Economics

  1. English
  2. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  3. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

The Morality of Radical Economics

Ghost Curve Ideology and the Value Neutral Aspect of Neoclassical Economics

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

This book is in equal parts a treatise on morality and economics, a critique of neoclassical orthodoxy, a brief for replacing mainstream economics with a radical political economics, and an argument for the abandonment of neoliberal capitalism in favor of democratic socialism. It includes a detailed proposal for a "demand and cost" alternative to "supply and demand" analysis and an in-depth technical critique of both neoclassical "high theory" and "applied microeconomic analysis" demonstrating that these are not only infeasible or immoral, but have directly contributed to public policy disasters. Further, the book suggests that only a moral economics in the form of radical political economy can address the looming economic and environmental crises of today's world.
Baiman begins with an introduction to morality and ethics in both general sciences and in economics in particular. He then guides readers through evidence of how neoclassical economics has not only failed to remain objective and value-free, but has become an ideology of apologetics protecting an immoral system. In addition to breaking down real-world examples to demonstrate his assertions, Baiman analyzes a theoretical Utopia design exercise. He concludes by arguing that the only form of economics that supports widely shared human values—such as social equity, democracy, and solidarity—is so-called "radical economics", and that all true economics science should be directed toward achieving more socially productive economic activity. An invaluable guide to morality and economics, this book will appeal to researchers and teachers looking to change the way we think about economics, policy, and society.

Frequently asked questions

Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Yes, you can access The Morality of Radical Economics by Ron P. Baiman in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Economics & Economic Theory. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Year
2016
ISBN
9781137455598
Part I
Economics as a Moral Science: The Philosophy and Science of Morality
Are people atoms or molecules? Are societies solar systems? Or insect colonies? Can a social science be value-free? Is not morality or empathy for our fellow humans and other living beings, a core part of being human?
Should social science attempt to be value-free? Can it do this? What are values or morals? Do they have meaning outside of specific cultures, religions, and histories? Are there universal values and can they be reasonably debated based on empirical evidence?
Can economics be value-free? Should it? Are there economic schools of thought that are openly values-based? Is there a choice? Is it not time to expose the value neutral pretense of mainstream or Neoclassical (NC) and economics as a status-quo supporting ideological construct, and acknowledge that economic thinking is always values-based and that the real issue is what values?
Part I is an exploration of these questions.
© The Author(s) 2016
Ron P. BaimanThe Morality of Radical Economics10.1057/978-1-137-45559-8_1
Begin Abstract

1. Introduction

Ron P. Baiman1
(1)
Benedictine University, Illinois, USA
End Abstract

Introduction

A 2013 Oxfam report estimates that the richest 85 people in the world own as much wealth as the entire bottom half of the world’s population (Oxfam 2014).1 Another recent report indicates that 23.1 % of children in the USA live in poverty, the highest percentage among 35 developed countries—surpassed only by Romania,2 even as the country hosts, at 5.9 % of households, the highest share of millionaire households, with over a million dollars in private financial wealth, of any large country in the world.3 A widely disseminated “political economy book of the century”4 documents in devastating empirical and historical detail the increasing “patrimonial” nature of twenty-first-century capitalism showing that it is well on its way to resurrecting a nineteenth-century class system based on inherited wealth that violates even the most basic notions of meritocracy (Piketty 2014).
The direct causes of these extreme concentrations of poverty and wealth are obvious for any who cares to look. A marquee example is Walmart, the largest private employer in the world.
Walmart has what is euphemistically called “a low-wage business model.”5 In 2012, a leaked document detailing Walmart’s official compensation policy revealed that its “sales associates” typically start at or near minimum wage ($7.25 an hour for states without higher state minimums) and received raises of only 20–40 cents an hour in incremental promotions. A worker with consistently “flawless performance evaluations” who started at $8.00 an hour could, after 6 years, expect a maximum hourly wage of $10.60.6 Walmart workers are paid so poorly that they are eligible for numerous US means tested public subsidies such as food stamps, Medicaid payments, and earned-income tax credits.7A 2013 report for the Democratic staff of a US Congressional Committee estimated that the average Walmart store costs US taxpayers $904,000 a year or roughly $5000 per employee.8 Walmart is also notoriously antiunion and a pioneer and leader in low-wage outsourcing from China (Workplace Fairness 2014)9 (Scott 2007).10
At the same time, Walmart made $17 billion in profits in 2013, paid its CEO in excess of $20 million, and provided an estimated $3.16 billion in dividends to entities controlled by three Walmart heirs.11 In 2014, the six Walmart heirs were estimated to be worth at least $ 150 billion.12 In 2010, they were estimated to own more wealth than the bottom 42 % of US families combined.13 With this enormous concentrated economic power, the Walmart heirs are actively supporting numerous conservative political causes (Rich 2014).14 These six passive investors, by virtue of their inheritance, are sitting on and controlling a $150 billion pile of claims to resources, resources that allow them to extract billions in further claims from the work of a veritable army of low-paid workers who can barely survive, even as they toil to generate more wealth for their passive billionaire owner-employers.15
In the advanced capitalist countries, Walmart has increasingly become the rule rather than the exception. As noted above, using the most detailed and exhaustive data on individual income ever assembled, Piketty (2014) has shown that inherited privilege has become a dominant “law of motion” of modern capitalism. Does this make any sense to anyone? Are these enormous levels of wealth inequality functional or justifiable?
Even if the initial accumulation was “earned” through a combination of talent, education, luck, and ruthless monopolistic business strategies, as for example, in the case of Bill Gates, does it make sense for one person to be, in the words of American Federation of Teachers President Randy Weingarten, “richer than God” with an estimated $80 billion in wealth? (Sorkin 2014).16
When a single individual has this much personal economic power, anything they do is almost sure to swamp the political and democratic process. For example, Gates and his philanthropic Foundation are (arguably, unlike the Waltons) trying to do good things for drug and vaccine development and public education, but his brute economic power renders even the most well-intentioned initiatives controversial. For example, Gates’ Foundation staff reportedly “don’t talk about drug patents,” a critical barrier to drug and vaccine dissemination, because it is a source of Gates’ wealth,17 and as prominent education scholar Diane Ravitch points out, in reference to a Gates’ “Big History Project” education initiative: “I wonder how Bill Gates would treat the robber barons. I wonder how Bill Gates would deal with issues of extremes of wealth and poverty.”18
Does anybody think that these conditions are the mark of a successful economic system? Neoclassical (NC) economics19 legitimizes these, intolerable by every major religious and philosophical moral standard, absolute and relative disparities of income and wealth by claiming to be value neutral 20 with regard to socially preferred wealth and income distribution.21 Is there an economics school of thought that robustly condemns this outcome as the moral, political, and economic failure that it is and that bases its theoretical and policy analysis on this understanding? This book argues that so-called radical economics in the USA, and progressive “heterodox economics” or “political economy” in other countries, is based on this understanding—an understanding that should be shared by all economic schools of thought.
This is not just a matter of a destructive economic model.22 It is a moral outrage. Economists should not eschew their moral responsibility to condemn these grossly unjust and undemocratic arrangements by pretending to be value-free and amoral, and they should surely not be in the business of justifying these economic systems out of some misguided conception of impartiality. Silence on these and the many other profoundly immoral outcomes of modern capitalism is complicity. If it is to be relevant to people and to society, economics must be based on moral values. There is no excuse for not condemning economic arrangements that violate the most universally shared moral imperatives to help and support the poor and destitute and to condemn wealthy exploiters of the poor. Economic theory needs to be based on these broadly accepted moral values and should not hide behind an indecisive, misplaced, and effectively apologetic amorality, or moral relativism.
We have accepted a status quo in which billions of human beings are reduced to mass deprivation, exploitation, and abuse. A good part of this is due to economic arrangements that place property rights above human needs by, for example, sanctioning the rights of rentiers, or passive investors, to accumulate unfathomable wealth even as the billions of humans who produce this wealth are reduced to hopelessness and misery. This includes both abysmally low-paid workers and the millions who are languishing without employment,23 all without a public response to create well-paid employment and minimal guaranteed income (Baiman et al. 2011). The hegemonic economic school of thought, NC economics, bases its core theoretical analysis on hypothetically fully employed labor markets and the optimal welfare efficiency of capitalist market economies (Weeks 2014, Introduction; Taylor 2004). Economics should not be at the forefront of justifying this illegitimate system as an unavoidable outcome of markets and sacrosanct property rights but, rather, should be leading efforts to expose the immorality of this kind of economic arrangement and proposing and advocating policy solutions for it.
This does not mean that economists need to be wild-eyed utopians. Realistic and politically popular policy options, such as the “Robin Hood” tax on financial speculation, to fund large-scale living-wage job programs in green energy, social services, and infrastructure are perfectly plausible (Baiman et al. 2012).24 Piketty (2014, Chap. 14) has suggested a global tax on capital. Many other perfectly realistic proposals have been offered (Hartmann 2014). Hill (2010), Huber and Stephens (2001), and Baiman (2014) and many countries, particularly in northern Europe, have made tremendous progress toward building more just, sustainable, and democratic economies by removing a large proportion of economic activity completely or partially out of the private for-profit production sector.
Why can we not “euthanize the rentier” as Keynes famously advocated (in their economic function, not as people) (Keynes 1936, Chap. 24)? The answer, of course, is political; but a major source of political legitimation for this manifestly inequitable and increasingly dysfunctional global economic system is NC economics—a theory based on the presumption that the natural and normal way for national and world economies to function is as capitalist market economies with minimal constraints on capital. And this argument continues to be made even as rentierism, a fundamental and increasingly dominant characteristic of these economies, undermines their ability to generate real production and living-wage employment and avoid a planetary crisis (Klein 2014).
Karl Polanyi (1944) pointed out at the end of the previous round of debate over what were then liberal, and now neoliberal, free-market policies, that markets are fundamentally creatures of society. There is no such thing as markets act...

Table of contents

  1. Cover
  2. Frontmatter
  3. 1. Economics as a Moral Science: The Philosophy and Science of Morality
  4. 2. Textbook Fables Support Immoral Policies: Economics Is Not About Supply and Demand or Aggregate Supply and Demand
  5. 3. The Morality of Radical Economics: Investigating the Value Neutral Aspect of Neoclassical Economics
  6. Backmatter