Alienation and Emancipation in the Work of Karl Marx
eBook - ePub

Alienation and Emancipation in the Work of Karl Marx

  1. English
  2. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  3. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Alienation and Emancipation in the Work of Karl Marx

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

This book considers Karl Marx's ideas in relation to the social and political context in which he lived and wrote. It emphasizes both the continuity of his commitment to the cause of full human emancipation, and the role of his critique of political economy in conceiving history to be the history of class struggles. The book follows his developing ideas from before he encountered political economy, through the politics of 1848 and the Bonapartist "farce, ", the maturation of the critique of political economy in the Grundrisse and Capital, and his engagement with the politics of the First International and the legacy of the Paris Commune. Notwithstanding errors in historical judgment largely reflecting the influence of dominant liberal historiography, Marx laid the foundations for a new social theory premised upon the historical consequences of alienation and the potential for human freedom.

Frequently asked questions

Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Yes, you can access Alienation and Emancipation in the Work of Karl Marx by George C. Comninel in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Politics & International Relations & Political History & Theory. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.
© The Author(s) 2019
George C. ComninelAlienation and Emancipation in the Work of Karl MarxMarx, Engels, and Marxismshttps://doi.org/10.1057/978-1-137-57534-0_1
Begin Abstract

1. Introduction

George C. Comninel1
(1)
Department of Politics, York University, Toronto, Canada
George C. Comninel
End Abstract
Karl Marx was never an academic. After abandoning the career in law that his father wanted for him, and completing a doctoral degree in philosophy in 1841, he became a radical journalist and political activist. Throughout his life, during which his family suffered from real poverty, he remained on this basis an agitator for human freedom. The greatest part of his writings—both published and unpublished—were devoted to the critique of political economy, and it was through this medium that he particularly confronted the dominant ideas of his time, especially historical social theory or the philosophy of history. On these grounds, he certainly qualifies as a great philosopher, yet his purpose was never merely philosophical. His main objective, from even before he encountered political economy, was always the realization of human emancipation, which from the start he understood to be more than simply a political goal.
Already inclined to pursue a radical project of revolutionary transformation going beyond the achievements of the French Revolution, Marx had at university overcome his initial dislike of G. W. F. Hegel’s apparently conservative philosophy to work with the Left Hegelians.1 Together with Ludwig Feuerbach, Bruno Bauer, Max Stirner, Arnold Ruge, Moses Hess, and others, Marx embraced a view that the social and intellectual development of humanity that had been realized over the course of history—the fundamental subject of Hegel’s philosophy—had not, in fact, reached its pinnacle in the Prussian monarchy of his day. It was through this Left Hegelian perspective that Marx first came to appreciate both the nature of alienation in society and the extent to which human emancipation had at its core overcoming alienation in its various forms. From the beginning, but especially after his first encounter with political economy in 1844, Marx understood the issues of alienation and emancipation to lie at the heart of historical social development.
In 1843, having been forced from his career as newspaper editor due to the suppression of its issues by reactionary Prussian censors, Marx undertook to analyse seriously the forms of alienation obstructing human freedom. He began with a close critique of part of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right.2 Where the Left Hegelians, particularly following Ludwig Feuerbach, had already criticized religion as a form of human alienation—their central philosophical challenge to Hegel himself—Marx went beyond this to find alienation also in the form of the state.3 Moses Hess had recently published a book chapter that criticized money also to be a form of alienation.4 Shortly after—in the article “On The Jewish Question”, written for the Deutsch-Franzöische JahrbĂŒcher that Marx co-edited, and challenging Bauer’s preoccupation with religion—Marx reproduced this insight, but extended it to include more generally wealth in the form of property.5 Through these works of 1843, but especially as a result of encountering the ideas of Frederick Engels —writing for the same journal—Marx was brought to confront the ideas that political economists had advanced about capitalist society. As a result of this, he was led to consider how the human condition in his day should be understood in relation to social development in history and to a future realization of humanity’s real potential.
In his Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844, Marx advanced the idea that alienation of labour constituted the essential form of exploitation, and was, in fact, the source of private property, not its consequence. Though he was still a long way from the critique of political economy achieved in Capital , already he recognized that the antagonistic social relations between workers and capitalists had a profound significance in human history. Indeed, he asked, “What in the evolution of mankind is the meaning of this reduction of the greater part of mankind to abstract labour?”6 He conceived “the entire movement of history” in a broad sweep from early social forms (“ancient Rome, Turkey, etc.”)—where the “antithesis between lack of property and property” remained as yet undeveloped—to labour and capital, which, in their opposition, “constitute private property as its developed state of contradiction”.7 He then conceived this contradiction-laden historical process to result in “Communism as the positive transcendence of private property as human self-estrangement, and therefore as the real appropriation of the human essence by and for man.”8 The reduction of the mass of humanity to exploited labour first led to expanded productive capacities, then—through communism—to greater human freedom. The classic articulation of this analysis, of course, is later contained in The Communist Manifesto.
Like Hegel and many others, Marx understood history in terms of developmental processes shaping human society. The philosophical cast of his early thought—human capacities realized through sequential historical forms, expressing successively higher levels of social experience—is unmistakable. This was, however, equally central to most varieties of social theory emerging over the last three centuries, informing historiography, sociology, and political science. Yet, while Marx began with such ideas, his approach to history did not end there.
On the one hand, engaging with the capitalist system of production compelled him to address how it differed from previous forms of society, and how it came to be. On the other hand, in later life, he began to consider seriously the sociopolitical situation and potential for emancipation in societies outside the framework of Western philosophy and social theory, like India and Russia. This brought him to consider other historical trajectories, both in actual development and as alternative possibilities.
It is essential to confront historical social theory in appropriating Marx’s ideas today. His critique of political economy is widely recognized as relevant today, even by mainstream economists, but what of his project of concluding the long history of human exploitation and unfreedom? Despite the widespread presumption that his historical theory is fundamentally based on a sequence of modes of production, there is no account of such that stands as definitive.9 Indeed, many grounds exist for challenging unilinear and universal conceptions of historical development (as Marx himself came to do in his later years). Moreover, Marx relied upon existing historical ideas since proved wrong, leaving several concepts to be squared with evidence. Faced with such doubts and challenges, we must take heart from Marx’s willingness to stray beyond the framework with which he began, and learn from his ongoing efforts to advance historical understanding.

The Importance of the French Revolution to Marx’s Ideas

Born in Trier—a formerly free city that reactionary Prussia acquired in defeating France—Marx was from his youth preoccupied with the politics of the French Revolution and their limits. Indeed, the French Revolution dominated the world of Marx’s youth and had a profound impact on his personal and intellectual development. The Revolution’s issues and controversies, politics and ideology, achievements and failures—together with the profound reshaping of societies for which it was responsible—continued to be primary determinants of the European social context until at least the revolutions of 1848.10 For more than two decades, near constant warfare had embroiled Europe, with corollaries stretching from North Africa to the Caribbean, to North America. The impact of the Revolution on the nineteenth century was in many ways comparable to the impact that the First and Second World Wars had on the twentieth century.
The Revolution both loomed as an obvious and crucial historical turning point in Marx’s ideas, and had enormous influence on his early work. This was not due to any role it may be supposed to have played in the transition from feudal class relations to those characteristic of capitalist society, but fundamentally because the Revolution trumpeted the cause of freedom: libertĂ©, Ă©galitĂ©, fraternitĂ©. The class interests generally identified with the bourgeoisie in the Revolution—even by Marx—were all immediately political: republicanism, liberal rights, modestly representative democracy, and nation building. Together, these goals defined the core mission of Jacobin politics. Above all, such objectives were recognized to be antithetical to aristocratic privilege and absolute monarchy, and it was in this sense specifically that the Revolution was understood to have marked a break with feudalism .
The final defeat of the Revolution in 1815—when the vestiges of Jacobin politics, and any scant hope for a return to democracy notwithstanding the imperial ambi...

Table of contents

  1. Cover
  2. Front Matter
  3. 1. Introduction
  4. 2. Approaching Marx’s Theory
  5. 3. Emancipation in Marx’s Early Work
  6. 4. The Developing Conception of Historical Materialism
  7. 5. Problems of The German Ideology
  8. 6. The German Ideology versus Historical Materialism
  9. 7. The Puzzle of the Manifesto of the Communist Party
  10. 8. Debating Marx’s Conception of Class in History
  11. 9. Historical Materialism and the Specificity of Capitalism
  12. 10. Capital as a Social Relation
  13. 11. Capital and Historical Materialism
  14. 12. Marx and the Politics of the First International
  15. 13. Marx and Social Theory
  16. Back Matter