Moral Respect, Objectification, and Health Care
eBook - ePub

Moral Respect, Objectification, and Health Care

  1. English
  2. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  3. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Moral Respect, Objectification, and Health Care

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

This book fills an important gap in existing health care ethics literature by describing an egalitarian conception of moral respect which applies to autonomous and non-autonomous patients alike. It reframes questions about respect, from its target to the role that respect plays in our moral lives. Taking into account various forms of objectification, it suggests that the unique role of moral respect is to recognize a person as more than a mere object; to recognize them as an equally intrinsically valuable being who possesses dignity. Further, the book argues that respect is central to health care because medicine and experiences of illness are both inherently objectifying. Objectification is sometimes morally permissible, and other times morally troubling—a context of respect can help to distinguish between these situations. Because we can reduce others to mere objects in ways other than violating or denying their autonomy, the approach presented here can also accommodate non-autonomous patients directly without considering them as marginal cases.

Frequently asked questions

Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Yes, you can access Moral Respect, Objectification, and Health Care by Meredith Celene Schwartz in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Philosophy & Philosophy & Ethics in Science. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Year
2019
ISBN
9783030029678
© The Author(s) 2019
Meredith Celene SchwartzMoral Respect, Objectification, and Health Carehttps://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-02967-8_1
Begin Abstract

1. Introduction

Meredith Celene Schwartz1
(1)
Department of Philosophy, Ryerson University, Toronto, ON, Canada
Meredith Celene Schwartz

Abstract

Schwartz fills an important gap in existing health care ethics literature by describing an egalitarian conception of moral respect which applies to autonomous and non-autonomous patients alike. It reframes questions about respect, from its target to the role that respect plays in our moral lives. Taking into account various forms of objectification, it suggests that the unique role of moral respect is to recognize a person as more than a mere object; to recognize them as an equally intrinsically valuable being who possesses dignity. Schwartz describes various forms of objectification and considers three cases in which patients are disrespected even while the doctor is upholding their autonomous decision-making.

Keywords

Moral respectObjectificationDignitySecond-person standpointRespect for autonomyInformed consent
End Abstract

1.1 Introduction

My aim is to provide an egalitarian account of moral respect as it applies in health care contexts. The concept of respect is central to medical ethics. Some discussion of ‘respect’ has been part of medical ethics since the early days of the discipline (e.g. The Belmont Report 1979). The dominant discussion of ‘respect’ in the context of health care ethics focuses on ‘respect for autonomy’ and this conception is well-entrenched in legal frameworks in a number of countries. The conception of ‘respect for autonomy’ leaves a gap in medical ethics because it does not apply to those patients who are not autonomous. In the seventh edition of The Principles of Biomedical Ethics, Beauchamp and Childress explicitly write that the principle of respect for autonomy does not include those who are not autonomous and cannot be rendered autonomous, such as children or patients diagnosed with late-stage Alzheimer’s disease. They state that those who are not autonomous are still covered by the concept of moral respect (Beauchamp and Childress 2013, p. 108). The concept of moral respect remains unanalysed in their edition, however. I fill this gap by reframing questions about moral respect around the role that the concept plays in our moral lives. I suggest that the fundamental role of moral respect is to recognize a person as more than a mere object, as an entity with intrinsic value of dignity rather than merely use-value of price.
To further explore the role of respect as recognizing someone as more than a mere object, I consider what it means to treat someone as an object. I suggest that disregarding someone’s autonomy or violating their autonomy is one important way of treating someone as a mere object. So respect for autonomy will remain central on my account. There are, however, a number of additional ways that we can reduce someone to a mere object and I pay particular attention to these additional forms of objectification.
I describe three aspects of the concept of respect: the grounds of respect, the target of respect and the behaviour that enacts respect. The ground or basis of respect tells us why respect is owed or warranted. The target of respect identifies what sorts of things must be respected. The behaviour that enacts respect describes how respect is put into practice in respectful relationships (Dillon 2010). A concept of moral respect should be egalitarian in the sense that it should apply equally to all persons, or members of the moral community. I suggest that we should understand respect as a concept that is grounded in dignity, which recognizes both the absolute moral value of individuals as well as the concrete particularity of their perspectives. As a result, the target of respect on this view is the person themselves, rather than an abstract feature or fact about the person. Respect is enacted through interactive second-person asymmetrical relations that treat others as more than mere objects. We disrespect others when we reduce them to mere objects, and so I consider what it is to objectify someone. There are a number of way to treat someone as an object, so the account of respect that I offer is relational and pluralist.

1.2 Respect for Autonomy and Informed Consent

The most common and legally-entrenched conception of ‘respect’ in health care ethics and law focuses on respect for autonomy, where autonomy is understood as making informed, voluntary choices about particular medical treatments or other aspects of care. This kind of autonomy is protected by ensuring that patients are well-informed about their condition and treatment options and that patients can give voluntary consent or refusal to these treatments. This conception of respect and its protection through informed consent is important and deserves its central place in medical practice and health law. Nothing in my discussion would undermine the importance of respect for autonomy. Respecting the autonomous decisions of competent patients is a necessary component of respecting them. Violations or denials of autonomy remain one important way that the moral equality of autonomous patients can be denied. Instead, my claim is that respecting autonomous decision is not sufficient for moral respect in health care settings. There are two reasons that it is not sufficient. First, it is inegalitarian because it does not apply to non-autonomous patients. Second, there are cases where even autonomous patients can arguably be disrespected even while their choices about medical treatments are accepted and they have given competent informed consent. To make these two criticism clear I begin by describing Beauchamp and Childress’ influential discussion of respect for autonomy. They themselves note that this conception of respect does not apply equally to all patients. The second claim will be developed throughout this chapter and the rest of the book.
On Beauchamp and Childress’s account, the grounds, object, and obligations of respect all centre on capacities for autonomous decision-making and supporting patients in making autonomous decisions. The understanding of ‘autonomy’ that Beauchamp and Childress invoke focuses on localized, specific instances of autonomous choice, rather than a broader conception that understands ‘autonomy’ as abilities, skills, or traits of the person (2009, p. 100; 2013, p. 102). Beauchamp and Childress select ‘autonomy’ as the grounds of our obligations of respect in health care contexts because they want “to be as precise as possible about what is and must be respected” (Beauchamp and Childress 2009, p. 70; 2013, p. 68). They eschew the language of respect for dignity and respect for persons because they believe that the terms ‘dignity’ and ‘person’ are vague and inherently contestable (2009, pp. 66, 69–70; 2013, pp. 65, 68).
The object of respect is also autonomous decision-making on Beauchamp and Childress’s view. That is, the presence of competence and other capacities for autonomous choice both explains why we must respect autonomous decisions, and autonomous decisions are the target of our respect. Since the early editions of Principles of Biomedical Ethics Beauchamp and Childress have contended that when we show respect to patients, the target of our respect is their choice; however, the obligations of respect have strengthened over subsequent editions. In the first edition, Beauchamp and Childress tell us, “To respect autonomous agents is to recognize with due appreciation their own considered value judgements and outlooks even when it is believed that their judgements are mistaken. To respect them in this way is to acknowledge their right to their own views and the permissibility of their actions based on such beliefs” (1979, p. 58). These obligations focused on granting persons the right to their own views, and the negative prohibition on interfering with their liberty. In more recent editions, Beauchamp and Childress have strengthened these requirements considerably and now require positive elements that acknowledge “the value and decision-making rights of persons and [enable] them to act autonomously” (2009, p. 103; 2013, p. 107). This involves “respectful action, and not merely a respectful attitude” (Beauchamp and Childress 2013, p. 107; emphasis in original). The respectful actions include such things as providing information, building up the capacity for autonomous choice, and dealing with emotions, such as fear, or other conditions that might distort autonomous actions. In contrast, disrespect for autonomy involves actions and attitudes that “ignore, demean, or are inattentive to others’ rights of autonomous action” (Beauchamp and Childress 2009, p. 103; 2013, p. 107). On this view, the behaviours and attitudes associated with both respect and disrespect focus on autonomous decision-making.
Although Beauchamp and Childress’s account of ‘respect’ is clearer than some of the discussions of respect found within general mainstream bioethics, this clarity is bought at a price when we consider the scope of respect—that is, to whom (or what) respect is owed. Because Beauchamp and Childress take autonomy as the object of respect, on their view our obligations related to this kind of respect extend only to those who are autonomous or those who have expressed their wishes through advance directives. They write, “Our obligations to respect autonomy do not extend to persons who cannot act in a sufficiently autonomous manner (and who cannot be rendered autonomous) because they are immature, incapacitated, ignorant, coerced or exploited. Infants, irrationally suicidal individuals, and drug-dependent patients are examples” (2009, p. 105). In the seventh revision to their view, Beauchamp and Childress have added the sentence “This standpoint does not presume that these individuals are not owed moral respect. In our framework, they have a significant moral status
 that obligates us to protect them from harm-causing conditions and to supply medical benefits” (2013, p. 108). Interactions with those who cannot act sufficiently autonomously will still be subject to the remaining three principles of beneficence, non-maleficence, and justice. Beauchamp and Childress offer a vague suggestion that non-autonomous patients will still deserve some form of respect. This other form of respect, that Beauchamp and Childress call moral respect remains unanalysed in their book, however. I infer that Beauchamp and Childress recognize that their account of respect is inegalitarian in that it treats autonomous and non-autonomous patients differently while moral respect is egalitarian and would require respect for patients regardless of their decision-making capacities. This latter form of egalitarian moral respect is my focus in this book.1

1.3 Cases of Disrespect?

My second criticism, that respect for autonomy is not sufficient for moral respect even among autonomous patients, is more difficult to establish. To...

Table of contents

  1. Cover
  2. Front Matter
  3. 1. Introduction
  4. 2. Dignity, Respect, and Objectification
  5. 3. Respect and Non-autonomous Patients
  6. 4. Respect and the Lived Experience of Illness
  7. 5. Conclusion
  8. Back Matter