Hans Blumenberg
eBook - ePub

Hans Blumenberg

Myth and Significance in Modern Politics

  1. English
  2. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  3. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Hans Blumenberg

Myth and Significance in Modern Politics

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

This book investigates the writings of German intellectual historian and philosopher Hans Blumenberg. While Blumenberg was not an explicitly political thinker and remains relatively under-explored in Anglophone academia, this project demonstrates that his work makes a valuable contribution to political science. The author considers the intellectual contributions Blumenberg makes to a variety of themes focusing primarily on myth. Rather than seeing myths in a pejorative sense, as primitive modes of thought that have been overcome, Blumenberg reveals that myths are crucial to dealing with the existential anxieties we face. When we trace his thought as it developed throughout his life, we find a rich source of philosophical insights that could enhance our understandings of politics today.

Frequently asked questions

Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Yes, you can access Hans Blumenberg by Xander Kirke in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Politics & International Relations & Political History & Theory. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.
© The Author(s) 2019
Xander KirkeHans BlumenbergGlobal Political Thinkershttps://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-02532-8_1
Begin Abstract

1. Introduction

Xander Kirke1
(1)
School of Geography, Politics and Sociology, Newcastle University, Newcastle upon Tyne, UK
Xander Kirke

Abstract

This introduction outlines the main objectives of this book. It offers a brief description of Hans Blumenberg’s work and considers why it may not have been as widely received by Anglophone audiences. It goes on to discuss the key themes of Blumenberg’s theory of myth that will be important throughout the latter stages of the book. Translation of a complicated author like Blumenberg is a challenge and raises profound analytical and normative issues. I consider these towards the end, and outline how I approach the issue of translation in these works. Finally, I explain how the book will be structured and the content of the chapters.

Keywords

BlumenbergTranslationMythStructure Nachlass
End Abstract
The works of Hans Blumenberg are widely known and discussed within German academia. Scholars there have long appreciated the breadth and depth of observations he has made about the human condition. In the Anglophone world, Blumenberg’s writings are not widely approached, with the exceptions of the few who have engaged systemically with his work throughout their careers such as Angus Nicholls and Robert W. Wallace. The latter offered a superb translation of two of Blumenberg’s most critical works, Arbeit am Mythos (Work on Myth) and Die LegitimitĂ€t der Neuzeit (Legitimacy of the Modern Age). These translations have proven invaluable in allowing non-German speakers to unpack the thoughts of a philosopher who (as this book will argue) can help us to understand our tumultuous political times. 1
One reason for Blumenberg’s rarity in Anglophone academia may be that he is a relatively challenging author to read. His prose is often dense, and many of the points he makes must be understood within the context of previous philosophical debates that some readers may not be familiar with. Yet many other authors of similar difficulty to read, albeit unique in their philosophical outlooks, have still been widely read in the Anglophone world. One example would be Martin Heidegger’s Sein und Zeit ( Being and Time) an invariably challenging text that provokes much debate to this day, whether read in German or English. Yet Heidegger’s influence has been widespread, with his thought and his understanding phenomenology still underpinning research projects across the humanities and social sciences. While it would be unjustified to compare Blumenberg and Heidegger, it becomes apparent through reading Blumenberg that he has many profound additions to the overarching questions raised by Heidegger and which continue to be discussed. This includes (at least indirectly) our experiences of ‘being-in-the-world’. However, more definitively, Blumenberg’s work coalesces well with a canon of philosophical thought that questions our experiences of being, the extent to our freedom, and how alienated we may be from the world around us. This canon is often referred to as existentialism, although many of those who have been attributed the label of ‘existentialist’ would have profound disagreements with one another. Blumenberg’s work addresses many of the same questions, and I would argue that we find this most strikingly in his writings on myth.
It may be that the dominant analytic philosophy of the UK and the USA would have limited interest in Blumenberg’s works. Proponents of the analytic tradition of philosophy emphasise clarity and precision of arguments, formal logic, and occasionally make reference to natural sciences and mathematics. Analytic philosophy contrasts with continental philosophy in multiple ways, but most notably in terms of method. Whereas analytic philosophy often tries to solve philosophical problems by reducing phenomena into their parts and the relations in which these parts stand, continental philosophy address questions in a more integrative manner, considering particular issues to be parts of larger unities that can only be understood ‘fitted into those unities’. 2 Neil Levy similarly remarks that analytic philosophy would see itself as a ‘problem-solving’ activity whereas continental philosophy is closer to ‘humanistic traditions’ including literature and art, and is generally more ‘politically engaged’. 3 Analytical philosophy privileges rationality over non-rationality, and seeks logical arguments to move towards objective truth. Students of such a school of thought would therefore oppose the understanding of ‘myth’ proposed by authors such as Blumenberg (described more below), instead viewing it as an inferior mode of thought to be overcome. It may be that the very basis for much of Blumenberg’s work would be dismissed by analytical philosophy on these grounds alone.
Contrary to such assertions, this book aims to demonstrate that key aspects of Blumenberg’s philosophy would offer a unique and much-needed approach to reading contemporary politics. It serves as an introduction to Blumenberg’s thoughts on myth and a political reading of them in contemporary times. While such a project must inevitably engage with other aspects of Blumenberg’s work, it does not claim to provide a comprehensive overview of Blumenberg’s entire oeuvre as political thought. Furthermore, it is strictly an introductory text that contributes to other works bringing Blumenberg’s thought into Anglophone academia, and it will particularly interest those who are concerned with the study of politics. While Blumenberg has traditionally not been understood as a political thinker, these perceptions have begun to shift following publications from the Nachlass . Indeed, these are not just interpretations of his philosophy in a political context, but often explicitly political writings made by Blumenberg himself that were not made public by him for various reasons. As mentioned, it would be beyond the scope of this book to reconceive Blumenberg’s entire canon as political thought, but I nonetheless identify an existential-political thread that we can glean from his conceptualisation of myth.

Blumenberg’s Myth: A Preliminary Summary

For Blumenberg, myth exists as a response to human experiences of what he terms the ‘absolutism of reality’. Briefly described, Blumenberg is one among many philosophers who noted a unique condition for human beings: the lack of an exclusive natural environment that can compensate for some of our deficiencies as a species. On the other hand, what we do have is a remarkable ability to adapt to multiple different scenarios, whether in terms of the very different natural environments in which we have created civilisations, or the variegated social structures we encounter and adapt to as we move between places. While this may sound like a good thing in principle, our lack of a specific environmental ‘niche’ means our horizons have broadened to such an extent that we often feel faced with innumerable simultaneous events occurring around us, many of which are entirely indifferent to our existence. We can only mitigate against this vulnerability by finding ways to ground a sense of significance (Bedeutsamkeit) within the world.
The immediate question that needs answering is what exactly Blumenberg means by ‘significance’? How do we differentiate it from similar concepts such as ‘meaning’? The first step is to recognise that meaning is a broader and much less specific term than significance. As Chiara Bottici points out when making this distinction, there is meaning wherever there is language. Indeed, the world as explained us through natural science contains mathematical formulae that we can readily access, and these could certainly be classed as a form of ‘meaning’. However, it may still prove to be insignificant for us. 4 On the other hand, ultimate meanings, such as the meaning of life or the existence of an afterlife, may also not be significant for a particular person, or group, in some situations. Ultimate meanings of existence that are answered by religions tend to counteract the plurality of myths that may exist within societies and, indeed, this is an argument made directly by Blumenberg in regard to Christianity. Significance operates in the space between simple meanings and ultimate meanings, and is therefore concerned with making things we experience within the world less indifferent to us.
Over generations, human beings have established concepts, names, and themes that underpin contemporary myths, many of which predate our own lives. The contents of myths are innumerable, but we may frequently associate them with tales of collective origins, with heroes, villains, and prophecies. Myths develop and evolve over time, providing the fundamental themes, names, and other materials that we adapt to suit the needs of present circumstances. This preceding body of myths is the culmination of what Blumenberg refers to as the ‘Work of Myth’, as distinguished by the equally important Work on Myth. The latter refers to the process of telling, retelling, and reproducing myths to adapt to the needs for significance at a particular moment in time. While myths must have an element of narrative constancy to act as an appropriate lens to view events, they must also be able to adapt to the needs of the present. Put simply, as times change, so myths must change with them. Myths must therefore be understood as a process which elaborates on a single narrative ‘core’, but which is in a constant process of being told by people and adapted to specific circumstances. As Blumenberg puts it, myths are ‘stories that are distinguished by a high degree of constancy in their narrative cores and an equally pronounced capacity for marginal variation’. 5
Blumenberg explicitly does not see myth as either an inferior mode of thought or something that is necessarily deceptive or false that can be overcome by scientific progress. This places Blumenberg among others in opposition to the long-held distinction between ‘mythos’ and ‘logos’ in philosophy. Briefly, this refers to an assumption that reasoned explanations of the world (logos) had ultimately overcome mythical ones (mythos). Blumenberg is one of many philosophers to argue against this distinction, and instead point out that myths remain central within our societies, albeit in diverse forms. This may be counter-intuitive to many of us, as in our daily lives we may use the term ‘myth’ to describe a claim or story that is untrue and refutable. Readers will need to be aware that this is not the usage of the term employed by Blumenberg. Indeed, whether a myth is actually true or false is not be of great importance. What matters is the function of myth, or, to use the established terminology how it provides us with a sense of significance within the absolutism of reality.
Why might these observations be political, or at least concern contemporary politics? The first thing to consider is the metaphorical expansion of the absolutism of reality that has been actively created by human beings through technology. Since Blumenberg’s death in 1996, we have seen a plethora of technological advances that enable us to transport information and entertainment across the world instantaneously. Social media in especially has allowed to consume, produce, and reproduce narratives, and many of these are political in content, and many are saturated with what Blumenberg would understand as myths. More specifically, technological change has enabled the work of myth to be accessible, and the work on myth is undertaken at a rate that is unprecedented in human history. One may assume that social media, and ‘globalisation’ as a general phenomenon, would actually reduce the size of the world metaphorically, and allow us to gain mastery of it more readily. Surely, we could ‘know’ the world more substantively than ever since we are able to learn of events beyond our immediate horizons, in places that we may never physi...

Table of contents

  1. Cover
  2. Front Matter
  3. 1. Introduction
  4. 2. Blumenberg: His Background and Influences
  5. 3. Anxiety and the Absolutism of Reality
  6. 4. Debates on Myth
  7. 5. Blumenberg, Myth, and Politics
  8. 6. Conclusion
  9. Back Matter