The Government of Life
eBook - ePub

The Government of Life

Foucault, Biopolitics, and Neoliberalism

  1. 304 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

The Government of Life

Foucault, Biopolitics, and Neoliberalism

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

Foucault's late work on biopolitics and governmentality has established him as the fundamental thinker of contemporary continental political thought and as a privileged source for our current understanding of neoliberalism and its technologies of power. In this volume, an international and interdisciplinary group of Foucault scholars examines his ideas of biopower and biopolitics and their relation to his project of a history of governmentality and to a theory of the subject found in his last courses at the College de France.Many of the chapters engage critically with the Italian theoretical reception of Foucault. At the same time, the originality of this collection consists in the variety of perspectives and traditions of reception brought to bear upon the problematic connections between biopolitics and governmentality established by Foucault's last works.

Frequently asked questions

Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Yes, you can access The Government of Life by Vanessa Lemm, Miguel Vatter, Vanessa Lemm, Miguel Vatter in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Philosophy & Political Philosophy. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Year
2014
ISBN
9780823255993
PART ONE
The Nomos of Neoliberalism
ONE
The Fourth Age of Security
Frédéric Gros
In this essay I discuss what I call the four ages of security. My reconstruction of the four great ages of security owes much to the work of Foucault, and I will address the idea of biopolitics through the lens of the fourth age of security. The four ages of security refer neither to social or political practices, nor to representations or mentalities. They stand for four great historical problematizations of security that Foucault marked out, but did not fully develop. For that matter, the concepts of “security” and “biopolitics” were never objects of any sustained conceptual elaboration on Foucault’s part. The schema I propose is by no means definitive, and constitutes a set of hypotheses rather than one thesis. I will describe four homogenous, relatively systematic sets of statements (énoncés) that have had important effects on political and ethical reality. I am describing knots of problematization.
The first age of security is the spiritual age and corresponds to the first sense taken on by the term “security” in the West. The word “security” derives from the Latin securitas, which can be deconstructed into sine curae: without troubles, without cares. The Greek equivalent, a-taraxia, also means without worries, without unrest. Security designates, in its first problematization, the mental state of the wise man that has attained definitive serenity through a series of appropriate spiritual exercises. Here, security has a spiritual meaning, rather than a political one. Seneca writes in the Letters to Lucilius, “Securitas proprium bonum sapientis est.” Security is the proper goal of the wise man. A certain number of remarks can be made with respect to this first sense of security. First, Foucault describes this state of mental serenity as well as the techniques of the self that allow for its attainment, mainly in his 1982 course at the Collège de France titled The Hermeneutics of the Subject, which strongly emphasizes the wisdom of the Stoics. It is important to note that it is only in Hellenistic and Roman philosophy that security comes to be thought as the aim of the philosophical life. In the classical philosophy of Plato and Aristotle, the term ataraxia is mostly absent. However, in the works of the Skeptics, the Stoics, the Epicureans, and the Cynics, the idea of ataraxia takes on a capital importance, since the pursuit and attainment of this security will come to define the philosophical enterprise. Philosophy is an enterprise of security in the sense that it promises to help achieve this mental state. What varies from one philosophical school of thought to another is the means and techniques to attain ataraxia, as well as the quality of this mental state itself. Let me provide only a few brief indications of these differences. For the Skeptics, ataraxia depends on a mental conversion, called epokhe, through which one renounces all judgments pertaining to the truth of what happens to oneself. There follows a mental security, a serenity made up of detachment and indifference. Abandoning the illusory pursuit of some definitive truth, one learns to experience a steadiness of the soul that permits one to maintain a perpetual calm in the midst of events. For the Epicureans, instead, ataraxia is conceived as the securing of the simple pleasure of existing. Through regular practices of meditating on the gods, conversation with friends, contemplation of basic philosophical precepts, and actively remembering moments of joy from the past, the goal is the crystallization of the pure happiness of existence, so as to make it a feeling that is always at one’s disposal. For the Stoics, ataraxia or securitas hinges on a long series of exercises, of askeses, of constant and highly codified tests, a series that has been studied in depth by Foucault, as for example the sorting of representations, meditation on death, morning and evening self-examination, and so forth. The goal is to reach in this way a perfect mastery of oneself and of one’s emotions, to constitute a strong ego that would be able to act in the world and confront the world’s hazards without ever allowing oneself to become destabilized. This Stoic security designates the stability of a subject who does not allow him- or herself to be moved by anything and who has at his or her disposal spiritual means that are powerful enough to prevail over all of the world’s misfortunes. This first sense of security as serenity, as the condition of the wise man, as steadiness of disposition has been of great importance for our culture. It returns again in contemporary philosophy, when Wittgenstein, for example, in his Lecture on Ethics, says that security constitutes one of the three fundamental moral experiences.1 It is important to understand that in this first sense “security” does not refer to the feeling of being protected or to the absence of any danger, but instead to the capacity to maintain the tranquility of one’s soul in the middle of these dangers and to find the source of security exclusively within oneself.
The second age of security is the imperial age, a concept that has often been suggested by Foucault, even if he never devoted any longer exploration to this problem. Still, on at least three occasions during his course at the Collège de France—for example, the lectures of March 22, 1978; January 5, 1983; and February 2, 19842—Foucault evokes the famous political myth of the Middle Ages, the Empire of the last days, a myth based on Christian millenarian doctrine. This millenarian doctrine—largely founded on (re)readings of the Apocalypse of Saint John and the Pauline Epistles, particularly the letter to the Thessalonians, in which the famous expression “pax et securitas” can be found—consists in the belief in a period of a thousand years preceding the Last Judgment which will be a period of peace, prosperity, and happiness on Earth, and which idyllic era would be followed by a series of great catastrophes (climactic, political, and social) and brought to an end with a final confrontation with the forces of Evil.3 The Church quite rapidly condemned this doctrine of one thousand years of terrestrial happiness before the Last Judgment and the end of the world. However, it has not ceased to reappear throughout history, and in particular it reappears in the High Middle Ages and takes on an important political dimension. Naturally, the simple utopia of a period of happiness, peace, and tranquility promised to humanity is not in itself particularly original and can be found in a number of cultures and historical periods. It often represents nothing more than the expression of a hope oriented toward the future which is complementary to a nostalgic longing for the golden age of the disappeared past. On the other hand, what is particularly interesting about the Christian millenarianism of the Middle Ages is the way in which this period of peace comes to graft itself on the idea of Empire and on the idea of security. This synthesis between the ideas of Empire, peace, and security had already been prepared by the Roman Empire in the time of Nero when one could find coins engraved with the motto “pax et securitas.” But in the European Middle Ages this security, a propaganda theme in the Roman Empire, becomes a political program founded on a mystical hope. In millenarian doctrine, this thousand-year period before the Last Judgment will witness simultaneously the end of history and the disappearance of borders. Indeed, this period of peace and security presupposes the establishment of a single Empire, the Empire of the last days, which brings together all nations around one single faith and in one single political space. One sole flock, as these millennium texts repeat over and again, with one solitary shepherd. The great problem that confronts the medieval West is how to know who this last Emperor will be: will he be French (a new Charlemagne), German (a new Frederick), or might it even be the pope, leader of Christendom? Every successful kingly campaign to conquer foreign lands or expand the borders of the realm was typically interpreted as a possible sign of the coming of the Emperor of the last days, of the onset of an age of peace and security, and of the end of history. As if authentic security could only be obtained by the constitution of a perfectly homogenous political and cultural space, and by the exclusion or destruction of all the figures of the Other. The last great resurgence of this political myth in the contemporary world was during the first Persian Gulf War promising a New World Order, made possible by the end of the Cold War and by the faith in the immanent extension of the model of liberal democracy to the entire globe. The president of the United States thus would have been the Emperor of the last days and the pax Americana would have led to the reign of a definitive security. For here security is Empire; security is the unification of worlds; security is the end of history.
The third age of security corresponds to the history of Western Europe and the rise of political philosophies centered on the state of nature and the social contract, that is, Hobbes, Locke, Spinoza, and Rousseau. Foucault elaborated on this third age at length in his course Security, Territory, Population at the Collège de France in 1978, in his studies of reason of state (raison d’État) and, in particular, in the development of the diplomatic–military dispositif, as well as in 1976, in his interpretation of Hobbes’s thought in Society Must Be Defended. This third age of security can be understood on the basis of the disappearance of the medieval dream of Empire, starting with the construction of a new political space composed of a plurality of sovereign states, each attempting to maintain its individual place in the midst of all the others, exemplified by Westphalian Europe. Here it is no longer a question of security as a spiritual condition, nor of the myth of an Empire of the last days. Instead, the goal is to think the consistency of a nation-state in the midst of history. Security will be defined as the consistency of the state, which is simultaneously the consistency supplied by the state to the rights of its citizens and to the existence of its subjects, and the consistency that the state provides for itself as one political subject in relation to others. Indeed, the very meaning of the word “security” is immediately divided into internal security and external security.
The great political philosophers of the modern age all thought of security as the goal of civil society, as the essential function of the state: “the virtue of a state is its security [securitas]”;4 “the people, who have a right to … provide for their own safety and security, which is the end for which they are in society”;5 “them that did institute the Common-Wealth, for their perpetual, and not temporary, security.”6 But clearly one must try to understand exactly what “security” entails in this new context. It is important to note here, that security is not simply a question of “public order,” and that in no way do these philosophies simply seek to legitimate a police state. Otherwise, one could not make intelligible why these texts, which all place security at the heart of a state’s legitimacy, were considered as dangerous and subversive by the ruling powers of their time. A general pattern can be found everywhere in the above-mentioned examples of modern political philosophies. Their point of departure is the description of a catastrophic state of nature, in which a certain number of natural, fundamental dispositions of man are made impossible: for example, the ownership of the fruits of one’s labor, equality as well as solidarity between men, and, lastly, freedom in the authentic sense of the term. In the state of nature, ownership is fragile; violence, suspicion, and dependency are the rule. None of man’s natural, fundamental dispositions are able to develop themselves. This is to say that all modern political philosophers want to give a double meaning to the word “nature”: it refers either to the savage immediacy of the state of nature, or to the conformity to Reason and God (natural law or laws). The creation of society and the institution of the state have as their purpose to make possible the application of the laws of nature understood as rational and divine laws: let ownership gained through labor be guaranteed, let the equality of all before the law be respected, let public freedom be preserved, let human solidarity be maintained and encouraged. In all these texts, security does not appear as a right among others, but as the very movement through which our natural dispositions must be assured, guaranteed, maintained, and all this against the eventual abuses of power by a biased, unjust state and against the influence of pressure groups representing particular interests. Security is the process through which consistency must be given by the state and by society to the fundamental, natural dispositions of man, which, in the state of nature, are precarious and in vain.
But, soon enough, a second meaning of “security” will overlay this first meaning. Most of these authors (Hobbes, Rousseau, Spinoza) indicate, although in a purely marginal way, that states stand in relation to one another as individuals in the state of nature: a permanent state of war holds sway among them. But the situation is not entirely the same: the state of nature is less destructive, and the state of war less absolute, between states than between individuals, since this violent situation does not necessarily lead to the creation of a global society. Each state must provide its citizens with security, must give consistency to their natural rights, and also guarantee its own security as a political subject. But the term “security” cannot have the same meaning in both cases. The defining feature of “political realism” in thinkers such as Hans Morgenthau, Raymond Aron, and Henry Kissinger, to give some contemporary examples, is precisely the conception of security as external security.7 For a state, then, external security signifies the defense of its territorial integrity, the development of its military power, the necessity of alliances (which will always be fragile and reversible), the cynical calculation of its interests, the development of a systematic suspicion of all other countries, and its ability to start wars or make peace as soon as its interests come into play. In expressions such as “nuclear security,” “UN Security Council,” or “collective security system” it is this sense of “security” which is predominant, and which has been predominant in Europe across the nineteenth century and up to the end of the Cold War. I refer to this sense of security as sovereign security.
Biopolitics names the fourth age of security. Thanks to Foucault’s analyses of neoliberalism and biopower, it is possible to define its outlines. I am here interested in analyzing a series of statements pertaining to security so as to be able to locate transformations and ruptures. These statements constitute a discursive network that defines, for any given security dispositif, an object (what must be secured or safeguarded: a spiritual condition, a unified world, a sovereign state), an actor (who must perform the securing: the wise man, the emperor, the state), a modality (how to perform this securing: by means of spiritual exercises, kindly solicitude, the constant threat of war), and a scope of action (that against which something must be secured: the pains of existence, the divisions of the world, invasions by the enemy). I have shown above that the set of these definitions varies historically. I propose that the contemporary era is marked by a very profound transformation in the idea of security itself, which is visible in a new discursive network, a new series of statements such as those pertaining to “human security,” “bio-security,” “global security,” or even “affective security.” To simplify things somewhat, I proceed by opposition, by showing first of all how the biopolitical age can be opposed to the age of sovereign security.
The object of security has changed. The great statements of political realism named, as the principal object of security, the defense of the state’s territorial integrity, which may require the sacrifice of citizens. The doctrine of human security instead proclaims insistently that living populations and individuals ought to constitute the new object of security. They are w...

Table of contents

  1. Cover
  2. Half Title
  3. Series Announcement Page
  4. Title Page
  5. Copyright
  6. Contents
  7. List of Abbreviations
  8. Acknowledgments
  9. Introduction
  10. Part I: The Nomos of Neoliberalism
  11. Part II: Genealogies of Biopolitics
  12. Part III: Liberalism between Legality and Governmentality
  13. Part IV: Philosophy as Ethics and Embodiment
  14. Notes
  15. Bibliography
  16. List of Contributors
  17. Index
  18. Series Page