Peirce on Signs
eBook - ePub

Peirce on Signs

Writings on Semiotic by Charles Sanders Peirce

  1. 294 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Peirce on Signs

Writings on Semiotic by Charles Sanders Peirce

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

Charles Sanders Peirce (1839-1914) is rapidly becoming recognized as the greatest American philosopher. At the center of his philosophy was a revolutionary model of the way human beings think. Peirce, a logician, challenged traditional models by describing thoughts not as "ideas" but as "signs, " external to the self and without meaning unless interpreted by a subsequent thought. His general theory of signs -- or semiotic -- is especially pertinent to methodologies currently being debated in many disciplines. This anthology, the first one-volume work devoted to Peirce's writings on semiotic, provides a much-needed, basic introduction to a complex aspect of his work. James Hoopes has selected the most authoritative texts and supplemented them with informative headnotes. His introduction explains the place of Peirce's semiotic in the history of philosophy and compares Peirce's theory of signs to theories developed in literature and linguistics.

Frequently asked questions

Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on ā€œCancel Subscriptionā€ - itā€™s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time youā€™ve paid for. Learn more here.
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlegoā€™s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan youā€™ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, weā€™ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Yes, you can access Peirce on Signs by James Hoopes in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Philosophie & Logique en philosophie. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

1 An Essay on the Limits of Religious Thought Written to Prove That We Can Reason upon the Nature of God

The following is from the first of a group of brief essays, written in the summer of 1859 and unpublished in Peirceā€™s lifetime. Here he argues that though some notions, such as the idea of God, are literally unthinkable and cannot be immediately present in the mind, they can nevertheless be represented and can therefore be thought of. While this view was not radical, the assertion that thinking can be done in signs was a step along the path to Peirceā€™s eventual conclusion that all thinking is in signs.
Source: Writings of Charles S. Peirce, 1:37.
What can we discuss? Can we discuss nothing we do not comprehend? Can we not even discuss that which has no existence in nature or the imagination? We can discuss whatever we can syllogise upon. We can syllogize upon whatever we can define. And strange as it is we can give intelligible comprehensible definitions of many things which can never be themselves comprehended.
I will give two instances of this; one simple and the other practical. Suppose somebody should talk about an OG and when you asked him what he meant he should say it was a four-sided triangle. You would proceed to show that he had no such conception that nobody had. You would reason upon that which you could not conceive of. This instance is too elementary. Suppose someone should tell me he could imagine two persons interchanging identities. I should proceed to reason on the pretended imagination and show that it was inconceivable.

2 [A Treatise on Metaphysics]

If the mind immediately perceives ideas but the ideas are representatives of things without, then the truth of those representative ideas is in doubt. Immanuel Kant had addressed himself to demonstrating, within limits, the truth of perception in his Critic of Pure Reason. Peirce as a teenager had studied Kant assiduously and then, in his early twenties, rejected Kantā€™s critical transcendentalism as an unwitting return to faith. Peirce preferred to base philosophy on a frank acknowledgment that knowledge always contains an element of faith, an undemonstrable but necessary belief that ā€œthe normal representations of truth within us are really correct,ā€ as he says in the following extract from a projected book of which he wrote ten thousand words in 1861. In the three sorts of representation that the youthful Peirce here identifiesā€”copy, sign, and typeā€”he adumbrates his eventual general typology of signs as icon, index, and symbol.
Source: Writings of Charles S. Peirce, 1:72ā€“83.

Introduction

Chapter III On the Uselessness of Transcendentalism

Ā§ 1. The Stand-point of the Transcendentalist
When the view that metaphysics is the study of the human consciousness is carried out in a one-sided way, in forgetfulness that it is as truly Philosophy and also the Analysis of Conceptions, it produces Transcendentalism (better named Criticism), which is the system of investigation which thinks necessary to prove that the normal representations of truth within us are really correct. . . .
Ā§3. On Faith
A. Need of It
I shall show
Ī±. that the Transcendentalists conclude with a return to Faith.
Ī². that the use they make of it in their own procedure is the source of all that is valuable in their investigations.
Ī³. that while their own faith is necessarily blind, their reasoning is not so close as to leave no room for demonstrably trustworthy faith.
I. Kantā€™s Work
An inference is involved in every cognition.
Proof. Relative cognition is the recognition of our relations to things.
All cognition of objects is relative, that is we know things only in their relations to us.
Every cognition must have an object (the subject of the proposition). The faculties whereby we become conscious of our relation to things are known as perceptions or sense.
āˆ“Every cognition contains a sensual element.
Now the information of mere sensation is a chaotic manifold, while every cognition must be brought into the unity of one thought.
āˆ“Every cognition involves an operation on the data.
An operation upon data resulting in cognition is an inference. āˆ“&c.
This demonstration is extracted from Kant. It does not extend to the cognition ā€œI think.ā€
Nothing is certain except what rests on the combined testimony of the senses and I think.
Proof. All knowledge, as we have just seen, is an inference from sensual minor premisses. In metaphysics, all inferences have major premisses. All knowledge is inferential except the I think. No cognition is certain which rests only on what is inferential. āˆ“&c.
Such is Kantā€™s reasoning. He then proceeds to test all our Conceptions as to objective validity by finding whether they are anything but particular expressions of the I think or of sensuousness. The following he makes objectively valid:ā€”
The Form of the External Senseā€”Space
The Form of the Internal Senseā€”Time
The Conceptions of the Understanding
I II
Of Quantity Of Quality
Unity Reality
Plurality Negation
Totality Limitation
III IV
Of Relation Of Modality
Substantia et Accidens Possibilityā€“Impossibility
Causality Existenceā€“Non-existence
Action and Reaction Necessityā€“Contingency
The following can never enter into any certain thought:ā€”
The Ideas of Reason.
1. The Immateriality, Incorruptibility, Personality, Animality1 of the Soul.
2.
Images
3. God.
Ī±. Though Kant cannot demonstrate the validity of the Ideas of pure reason, yet he chooses to believe it. Although there is not to him one whit more probability that they are true than that they are false, still he trusts in them,ā€”he has Faith.
Ī². He also takes the validity of sensibility and of the I think for granted. Yet only by doing so has he made any solid work.
Ī³. A part of his argument is that nothing which rests only on what is inferential can be certain. This is not axiomatic nor demonstrable. It therefore leaves hope of proving the contrary which establishes the validity of faith. . . .
B. Reason of Faith
Unfaith is either total or partial scepticism.
The different faculties have different realms by which they are distinguished. No faculty is to be trusted out of its own realm. āˆ“Hence no faculty can derive any support from another but each must stand upon its own credibility. No one faculty has more inherent credibility than another. āˆ“Partial scepticism is inconsistent. Total scepticism condemns itself. āˆ“Faith is the only consistent course.
The argument has the following advantages.
1. It puts faith on the same ground as all certitude.
2. It does not make it so sure that it is no longer faith.
3. By showing that faith is inherent in the very idea of the attainment of truth, it makes its acceptance axiomatic, and thus explains how we were already sure before we had reasoned about Faith.
C. Nature of Faith
I. What Faith is Not
1. It is not a purely intellectual principle; it is an unaccountable impulse to confide in certain truths.
This is forgotten by those who are over-anxious about the details of evidence in religion. They forget that with the highest certitude of inspiration and of history, belief still depends on an internal impulse. For, some things we should not believe though the angel Gabriel told us, while true religion is instinctively accepted by the ingenuous mind.
2. Faith is not peculiar to or more needed in one province of thought than in another. For every premiss we require faith and nowhere else is there any room for it.
This is overlooked by Kant and others who draw a distinction between knowledge and faith. Wherever there is knowledge there is Faith. Wherever there is Faith (properly speaking) there is knowledge.
3. There is no such thing as having immediate faith in the statements of others, be they men or angels or what. For whenever we believe statements, it is either because there is something in the fact itself which makes it credible or because we know something of the character of the witness. In either case there is a because whose major premiss is some principle concerning general characters of credibility. To believe without any such ā€˜becauseā€™ is mere credulity.
II. What Faith is
1. It is the recognition by consciousness of itself. It is the strength of that faculty by which abstractions are conceived.
2. It is the hearing of the testimony of consciousness, which developes into trust in every man till there is reason for distrust and a spirit of obedience to the Law of God.
3. It is the vigour of that part of the mind which is in communication with the eternal verities. By this, mountains are moved.
III. Effect of faith on Transcendentalism
1. Criticism is entirely swept away as useless.
2. Transcendentalism as a study of the out-reaching of the human mind retains its full value.
3. This study of consciousness is the examination of abstractions by analysis of conceptions.

BOOK I. PRINCIPLES OF METAPHYSICAL INVESTIGATION

Chapter I. Man the Measure of Things

In the Introduction we have considered the Nature of Metaphysics, and have rejected certain false notions of its procedure.
In our investigations, metaphysics is to be taken as the analysis of Conceptions.
We need not ask the critical question; but still there is a question of uncritical transcendentalism with which every method of philosophy must open. It is, How should the conceptions which spring up freely in our minds by virtue of the constitution thereof be true for the outward world?
In this question we detect three leading conceptions Truth, the Innateness of Ideas, Externality. Let us analyze each of these.

Ā§1. Of Truth

True is an adjective applicable solely to representations and things ...

Table of contents

  1. Cover Page
  2. Peirce on Signs
  3. Copyright Page
  4. Contents
  5. Acknowledgments
  6. Introduction
  7. 1 An Essay on the Limits of Religious Thought Written to Prove That We Can Reason upon the Nature of God
  8. 2 [A Treatise on Metaphysics]
  9. 3 On a New List of Categories
  10. 4 Questions concerning Certain Faculties Claimed for Man
  11. 5 Some Consequences of Four Incapacities
  12. 6 Grounds of Validity of the Laws of Logic: Further Consequences of Four Incapacities
  13. 7 [Fraserā€™s The Works of George Berkeley]
  14. 8 On the Nature of Signs
  15. 9 The Fixation of Belief
  16. 10 How to Make Our Ideas Clear
  17. 11 One, Two, Three: Fundamental Categories of Thought and of Nature
  18. 12 A Guess at the Riddle
  19. 13 Jamesā€™s Psychology
  20. 14 Manā€™s Glassy Essence
  21. 15 Minute Logic
  22. 16 Sign
  23. 17 Lectures on Pragmatism
  24. 18 [ā€œPragmatismā€ Defined]
  25. 19 Prolegomena to an Apology for Pragmaticism
  26. 20 The Basis of Pragmaticism
  27. 21 A Neglected Argument for the Reality of God
  28. Bibliography
  29. Index