Kant's Embedded Cosmopolitanism
eBook - ePub

Kant's Embedded Cosmopolitanism

  1. 225 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Kant's Embedded Cosmopolitanism

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

Kant's omnipresence in contemporary cosmopolitan discourses contrasts with the fact that little is known about the historical origins and the systematic status of his cosmopolitan theory. This study argues that Kant's cosmopolitanism should be understood as embedded and dynamic. Inspired by Rousseau, Kant developed a form of cosmopolitanism rooted in a modified form of republican patriotism. In contrast to static forms of cosmopolitanism, Kant conceived the tensions between embedded, local attachments and cosmopolitan obligations in dynamic terms. He posited duties to develop a cosmopolitan disposition ( Gesinnung ), to establish common laws or cosmopolitan institutions, and to found and promote legal, moral, and religious communities which reform themselves in a way that they can pass the test of cosmopolitan universality. This is the cornerstone of Kant's cosmopolitanism, and the key concept is the vocation ( Bestimmung ) of the individual as well as of the human species. Since realizing or at least approaching this vocation is a long-term, arduous, and slow process, Kant turns to the pedagogical implications of this cosmopolitan project and spells them out in his later writings. This book uncovers Kant's hidden theory of cosmopolitan education within the framework of his overall practical philosophy.

Frequently asked questions

Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Yes, you can access Kant's Embedded Cosmopolitanism by Georg Cavallar in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Filosofia & Filosofia moderna. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Publisher
De Gruyter
Year
2015
ISBN
9783110429459
Edition
1

1 Introduction

The final vocation of the human race is moral
perfection,
so far as it is accomplished through human
freedom
Collins, 27: 470

“Kant was enough of a child of the eighteenth century to be cosmopolitan, not nationalistic, in his feeling”, John Dewey wrote in 1915 (Dewey 1970: 98). With this statement, Dewey reproduces the familiar clichĂ© of the allegedly “cosmopolitan Enlightenment”. Yet recent studies emphasize the diversity and complexity of the term “cosmopolitan” in the eighteenth century, stress that many intellectuals just displayed a pro-European attitude, often equated cosmopolitanism with moderate patriotism, and were frequently challenged by critics (see among others Albrecht 2005, Cavallar 2011). Secondly, Dewey dogmatically assumes that Kant’s cosmopolitanism was “nothing but” a reflex or mirror of widespread intellectual stances. Dewey’s assessment is dogmatic by standards of Kant’s critical epistemology (the causal relationship is never proven), and this study will try to show that Kant’s theory of cosmopolitanism is the outcome of his own systematically developed practical philosophy, not a mere repetition or copy of widely held Enlightenment beliefs. Third, Dewey does not even attempt to understand Kant’s systematic approach, which is not a matter of feeling, but of rational argumentation, not a matter of unthinking copy-and-paste, but of profound reflection, of an analysis of possible alternative positions, and a careful reworking of one’s own thoughts over the years (for a full analysis see Kleingeld 2012). Finally, Dewey’s attempt to situate Kant historically (as a child of the Enlightenment) in turn invites historical contextualization. The context of Dewey’s assessment is the hysteria of the Great War, when one’s enemies and their most formidable thinkers were usually perceived as illiberal, militaristic, nationalistic, and politically extremist. German authors in turn offered similar biased judgements of thinkers allegedly belonging to the allied camp; these Germans were apparently even more radical. And they sometimes believed that Kant should not belong to the camp of the “true Germans”. It is interesting to note here that some German intellectuals before 1945 almost hated Kant for what they perceived as a cosmopolitan attitude or disposition, and believed he should have become an ardent German nationalist instead (cf. Cavallar 1992: 247– 52, 433 – 5, 445 – 50).
dp n="12" folio="2" ?
Roughly one hundred years later, the intellectual climate has considerably changed. For most scholars in the U. S., Germany and elsewhere, the term cosmopolitanism is no longer an insult. Intellectuals outside Germany have started to appreciate Kant’s cosmopolitanism, among them politicians, political scientists like Garrett Brown, philosophers like Martha Nussbaum or Kant scholars like Pauline Kleingeld or Robert Louden. Scholars have started to investigate into the ramifications of the concept in Kant’s philosophy (see among others Bacin et al. 2013). Theories of cosmopolitanism, widely discussed in recent years, are the background of this new focus (see, among others, Fine 2009, Baker 2013, Brown and Held 2010, Halldenius 2010, Lutz-Bachmann, Niederberger and Schink 2010 and Cavallar 2011). Historical studies of the concept are rare, but Kant is usually seen as one of the founding fathers of contemporary cosmopolitanism (see for instance Cheneval 2002, Brown 2009 and Kleingeld 2012). At roughly the same time, cosmopolitan educational theories have been developed, and vigorously discussed (recent contributions include Hansen 2010, McCarty 2010, Nussbaum 2010, Todd 2009, Waks 2009 and 2010, Zembylas 2010). Finally, there has been a renewed interest in Kant and his educational theory (see Breun 2002, Kauder 1999, Koch 2003, Moran 2009, Surprenant 2010, and Roth and Surprenant 2012 among others). Kant’s omnipresence in contemporary cosmopolitan discourses contrasts with the fact that little is known about the historical origins of his cosmopolitan theory.
Kant’s Embedded Cosmopolitanism argues that many contemporary interpretations are potentially anachronistic and one-sided. It examines the historical context of Kant’s cosmopolitanism, and focuses on its neglected pedagogical and republican dimension. It argues that Kant’s cosmopolitanism should be understood as rooted in one’s particular community and thus embedded. Inspired by Rousseau, Kant tried to develop a synthesis of republican patriotism and republican as well as thin moral cosmopolitanism. In contrast to static forms of cosmopolitanism prevalent in traditional conceptions, Kant belonged to a generation of Enlightenment reformers who conceived the tensions between embedded, local attachments and cosmopolitan obligations in dynamic terms. Kant in particular posited duties to promote the legal, moral and religious communities, to establish common laws or cosmopolitan institutions, and to develop a cosmopolitan disposition. This is the cornerstone of Kant’s cosmopolitanism, and the key concept is the vocation (Bestimmung) of the individual as well as of the human species. Since trying to realize or at least approach this vocation was a long-term, arduous and slow process, Kant turned to the pedagogical implications of this “project” and spelled them out in his later writings. Embedding Kant in his proper late eighteenth century context, the book analyses possible influences, in particular the writings of Rousseau and educational reformer Basedow. In short, rather than jumping to the facile and Whiggish conclusion that Kant’s cosmopolitanism merely anticipated contemporary forms of cosmopolitanism, the book emphasizes possible differences and the uniqueness of Kant’s cosmopolitan theory, even by late eighteenth-century standards.
Recent years have witnessed a growing interest in the concept and theories of cosmopolitanism and of cosmopolitan educational theories. So far there has been only one comprehensive interpretation of Kant’s cosmopolitanism, Pauline Kleingeld, Kant and Cosmopolitanism. The Philosophical Ideal of World Citizenship (Cambridge University Press 2012). The main theses of this excellent book are innovative, well argued, and plausible. Yet her book also has a few shortcomings: Rousseau is presented as a critic of cosmopolitanism and is ignored by and large; his possible influence on Kant is not discussed. While Kleingeld’s book is very strong in contrasting Kant’s views with those of his contemporaries, the author has little to say about the moral and educational dimensions of Kant’s cosmopolitan theory. Finally, I claim that Kant’s concept of an ethical commonwealth is deeply rooted in his understanding of Christianity and the role the Christian churches (clearly favoured over other religious traditions). In Kleingeld’s account, the ethical commonwealth, together with the concept of the highest good, are presented as fully secularized notions.
To my knowledge, only one monograph and one dissertation have so far been published on cosmopolitan education. Sharon Todd’s Toward an Imperfect Education. Facing Humanity, Rethinking Cosmopolitanism (Boulder and London: Paradigm Publishers 2009) occasionally refers to Kant. Todd bypasses Kant’s theory of moral formation and its cosmopolitan dimension, and instead offers a brief interpretation of his cosmopolitan right. Matthew J. Hayden’s dissertation Cosmopolitan Education and Moral Education: Forging Moral Beings Under Conditions of Global Uncertainty (Dissertation Columbia University 2012) develops a contemporary theory of moral cosmopolitan education based on the “fundamental fact of shared humanity” (p. 18). He is above all inspired by authors such as Arendt, Nagel, Habermas and Mouffe; Kant plays an insignificant role.
Felicitas Munzel’s excellent Kant’s Conception of Pedagogy. Toward Education for Freedom (Evanston, Illinois: Northwestern University Press 2012) sometimes overlaps with what I try to do in this study. Munzel’s key claim is that Kant’s doctrines of method (Methodenlehren) in the three critiques contain a “fourth critique” (cf. XVf., XIX, 232). According to Munzel, critical philosophy is in fact a pedagogical project, “essentially a paideia” (XXI), which is the programme of cultivating the mind with the goal of wisdom and fulfilling one’s vocation, namely autonomy and inner freedom. “From Kant’s perspective, the basic pedagogical task is not the inculcation of a principle (such as the prevalent effort in the eighteenth century to curb the detrimental effects of the workings of self-interest by instilling some variant of ‘love thy neighbor’), but rather the task is the preparation of the mind to exercise its inherent principle of freedom” (XX). Although Munzel’s monograph and my study sometimes overlap, there are different emphases: Munzel’s goal is to assign Kant a place “among the great pedagogical thinkers” (ibid., 83, cf. 181) and to explore his educational theory, whereas I try to investigate into Kant’s cosmopolitanism (and its educational ramifications). In the first part of her study, Munzel situates Kant’s pedagogy within the divergent educational theories of the 18th century (5 – 183); my own focus is almost exclusively on Rousseau, Basedow and Spalding. Munzel is interested in inner, moral freedom as the transcendental condition of the possibility of external, political freedom: true political freedom presupposes moral freedom (cf. XVI, 83, 171– 9, 233). My own approach looks at the issue from a different angle: external freedom helps humans to cultivate their dispositions and thus also their moral potentials as free moral agents (see chapters 6 and 7). Our respective studies definitely overlap when Munzel develops “Articles for a Cosmopolitan Education” (cf. 285–93).

1.1 Types of cosmopolitanisms

Cosmopolitanism is the belief or the theory that all humans, regardless of race, gender, religion or political affiliation belong to, or should belon...

Table of contents

  1. Kantstudien-ErgÀnzungshefte
  2. Titel
  3. Impressum
  4. Inhaltsverzeichnis
  5. Acknowledgements
  6. Abbreviations
  7. 1 Introduction
  8. 2 Cosmopolitanisms in Kant’s philosophy
  9. 3 Kant’s right of world citizens: a historical interpretation
  10. 4 Educating Émile:Rousseau on embedded cosmopolitanism
  11. 5 Sources of Kant’s cosmopolitanism: Basedow, Rousseau, and cosmopolitan education
  12. 6 Taking a detour: Kant’s theory of moral cosmopolitan formation
  13. 7 Res publica: Kant on cosmopolitical formation
  14. 8 Conclusion: From Kant to the present
  15. Bibliography
  16. Subject index