The Bounds of Reason
eBook - ePub

The Bounds of Reason

Game Theory and the Unification of the Behavioral Sciences - Revised Edition

  1. 288 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

The Bounds of Reason

Game Theory and the Unification of the Behavioral Sciences - Revised Edition

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

Game theory is central to understanding human behavior and relevant to all of the behavioral sciencesā€”from biology and economics, to anthropology and political science. However, as The Bounds of Reason demonstrates, game theory alone cannot fully explain human behavior and should instead complement other key concepts championed by the behavioral disciplines. Herbert Gintis shows that just as game theory without broader social theory is merely technical bravado, so social theory without game theory is a handicapped enterprise. This edition has been thoroughly revised and updated.Reinvigorating game theory, The Bounds of Reason offers innovative thinking for the behavioral sciences.

Frequently asked questions

Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on ā€œCancel Subscriptionā€ - itā€™s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time youā€™ve paid for. Learn more here.
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlegoā€™s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan youā€™ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, weā€™ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Yes, you can access The Bounds of Reason by Herbert Gintis in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Economics & Economic Theory. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Year
2014
ISBN
9781400851348
1
Decision Theory and Human Behavior
People are not logical. They are psychological.
Anonymous
People often make mistakes in their maths. This does not mean that we should abandon arithmetic.
Jack Hirshleifer
Decision theory is the analysis of the behavior of an individual facing nonstrategic uncertaintyā€”that is, uncertainty that is due to what we term ā€œNatureā€ (a stochastic natural event such as a coin flip, seasonal crop loss, personal illness, and the like) or, if other individuals are involved, their behavior is treated as a statistical distribution known to the decision maker. Decision theory depends on probability theory, which was developed in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries by such notables as Blaise Pascal, Daniel Bernoulli, and Thomas Bayes.
A rational actor is an individual with consistent preferences (Ā§1.1). A rational actor need not be selfish. Indeed, if rationality implied selfishness, the only rational individuals would be sociopaths. Beliefs, called subjective priors in decision theory, logically stand between choices and payoffs. Beliefs are primitive data for the rational actor model. In fact, beliefs are the product of social processes and are shared among individuals. To stress the importance of beliefs in modeling choice, I often describe the rational actor model as the beliefs, preferences and constraints model, or the BPC model. The BPC terminology has the added attraction of avoiding the confusing and value-laden term ā€œrational.ā€
The BPC model requires only preference consistency, which can be defended on basic evolutionary grounds. While there are eminent critics of preference consistency, their claims are valid in only a few narrow areas. Because preference consistency does not presuppose unlimited information-processing capacities and perfect knowledge, even bounded rationality (Simon 1982) is consistent with the BPC model.1 Because one cannot do behavioral game theory, by which I mean the application of game theory to the experimental study of human behavior, without assuming preference consistency, we must accept this axiom to avoid the analytical weaknesses of the behavioral disciplines that reject the BPC model, including psychology, anthropology, and sociology (see chapter 11).
Behavioral decision theorists have argued that there are important areas in which individuals appear to have inconsistent preferences. Except when individuals do not know their own preferences, this is a conceptual error based on a misspecification of the decision makerā€™s preference function. We show in this chapter that, assuming individuals know their preferences, adding information concerning the current state of the individual to the choice space eliminates preference inconsistency. Moreover, this addition is completely reasonable because preference functions do not make any sense unless we include information about the decision makerā€™s current state. When we are hungry, scared, sleepy, or sexually deprived, our preference ordering adjusts accordingly. The idea that we should have a utility function that does not depend on our current wealth, the current time, or our current strategic circumstances is also not plausible. Traditional decision theory ignores the individualā€™s current state, but this is just an oversight that behavioral decision theory has brought to our attention.
Compelling experiments in behavioral decision theory show that humans violate the principle of expected utility in systematic ways (Ā§1.5.1). Again, it must be stressed that this does not imply that humans violate preference consistency over the appropriate choice space but rather that they have incorrect beliefs deriving from what might be termed ā€œfolk probability theoryā€ and make systematic performance errors in important cases (Levy 2008).
To understand why this is so, we begin by noting that, with the exception of hyperbolic discounting when time is involved (Ā§1.2), there are no reported failures of the expected utility theorem in nonhumans, and there are some extremely beautiful examples of its satisfaction (Real 1991) Moreover, territoriality in many species is an indication of loss aversion (Gintis 2007b). The difference between humans and other animals is that the latter are tested in real life, or in elaborate simulations of real life, as in Leslie Realā€™s work with bumblebees (Real 1991), where subject bumblebees are released into elaborate spatial models of flowerbeds. Humans, by contrast, are tested using imperfect analytical models of real-life lotteries. While it is important to know how humans choose in such situations, there is certainly no guarantee they will make the same choices in the real-life situation and in the situation analytically generated to represent it. Evolutionary game theory is based on the observation that individuals are more likely to adopt behaviors that appear to be successful for others. A heuristic that says ā€œadopt risk profiles that appear to have been successful to othersā€ may lead to preference consistency even when individuals are incapable of evaluating analytically presented lotteries in the laboratory. Indeed, a plausible research project in extending the rational actor model would be to replace the assumption of purely subjective prior (Savage 1954) with the assumption that individuals are embedded in a network of mind across which cognition is more or less widely distributed (Gilboa and Schmeidler 2001; Dunbar et al. 2010; Gintis 2010).
In addition to the explanatory success of theories based on the BPC model, supporting evidence from contemporary neuroscience suggests that expected utility maximization is not simply an ā€œas ifā€ story. In fact, the brainā€™s neural circuitry actually makes choices by internally representing the payoffs of various alternatives as neural firing rates and choosing a maximal such rate (Shizgal 1999; Glimcher 2003; Glimcher and Rustichini 2004; Glimcher et al. 2005). Neuroscientists increasingly find that an aggregate decision making process in the brain synthesizes all available information into a single unitary value (Parker and Newsome 1998; Schall and Thompson 1999). Indeed, when animals are tested in a repeated trial setting with variable rewards, dopamine neurons appear to encode the difference between the reward that the animal expected to receive and the reward that the animal actually received on a particular trial (Schultz et al. 1997; Sutton and Barto 2000), an evaluation mechanism that enhances the environmental sensitivity of the animalā€™s decision making system. This error prediction mechanism has the drawback of seeking only local optima (Sugrue et al. 2005). Montague and Berns (2002) address this problem, showing that the orbitofrontal cortex and striatum contain a mechanism for more global predictions that include risk assessment and discounting of future rewards. Their data suggest a decision-making model that is analogous to the famous Black-Scholes options-pricing equation (Black and Scholes 1973).
The existence of an integrated...

Table of contents

  1. Cover Page
  2. Title Page
  3. Copyright Page
  4. Dedication Page
  5. Contents
  6. Preface
  7. 1 Decision Theory and Human Behavior
  8. 2 Game Theory: Basic Concepts
  9. 3 Game Theory and Human Behavior
  10. 4 Rationalizability and Common Knowledge of Rationality
  11. 5 Extensive Form Rationalizability
  12. 6 The Logical Antinomies of Knowledge
  13. 7 The Mixing Problem: Purification and Conjectures
  14. 8 Bayesian Rationality and Social Epistemology
  15. 9 Common Knowledge and Nash Equilibrium
  16. 10 The Analytics of Human Sociality
  17. 11 The Unification of the Behavioral Sciences
  18. 12 Summary
  19. 13 Table of Symbols
  20. References
  21. Subject Index
  22. Author Index