The Why of Things
eBook - ePub

The Why of Things

Causality in Science, Medicine, and Life

  1. English
  2. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  3. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

The Why of Things

Causality in Science, Medicine, and Life

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

Why was there a meltdown at the Fukushima power plant? Why do some people get cancer and not others? Why is global warming happening? Why does one person get depressed in the face of life's vicissitudes while another finds resilience?

Questions like these—questions of causality—form the basis of modern scientific inquiry, posing profound intellectual and methodological challenges for researchers in the physical, natural, biomedical, and social sciences. In this groundbreaking book, noted psychiatrist and author Peter Rabins offers a conceptual framework for analyzing daunting questions of causality. Navigating a lively intellectual voyage between the shoals of strict reductionism and relativism, Rabins maps a three-facet model of causality and applies it to a variety of questions in science, medicine, economics, and more.

Throughout this book, Rabins situates his argument within relevant scientific contexts, such as quantum mechanics, cybernetics, chaos theory, and epigenetics. A renowned communicator of complex concepts and scientific ideas, Rabins helps readers stretch their minds beyond the realm of popular literary tipping points, blinks, and freakonomic explanations of the world.

Frequently asked questions

Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Yes, you can access The Why of Things by Peter Rabins in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Philosophy & Philosophy & Ethics in Science. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

1
image
HISTORICAL OVERVIEW
The Four Approaches to Causality
A thing cannot occur without a cause that produces it.
—Pierre Simon de Laplace
The concept of causality is so much a part of our lives that we often think about, discuss, or identify causes without considering the complexity of the underlying concept. Questions about cause touch on issues small and large—questions such as, why did I stumble, what led to that car accident, what caused today’s weather? Why are some people happier than others? Why do some individuals become sick while others avoid an illness that “everyone is getting”? What causes poverty, economic cycles, substance abuse, evil? How did the universe come to be?
It is not the goal of this book to answer any of these questions with absolute certainty—that would not be possible. Rather, its goal is to provide approaches to answering such questions. We will begin by trying to understand what we mean by the word “cause,” since understanding what lies behind the words we use can help focus a search, clarify what is being sought, and settle some of the arguments that arise. This approach shares an assumption, one dating from the ancient Greeks, that human reasoning can be a source of knowledge.
Understanding what we mean by cause is a big question. It is the “why” question asked by two-year-old children, mature adults, historians, geneticists, clergy, and ethicists. Many great thinkers in disciplines as disparate as theology, philosophy, neurophysiology, history, particle physics, and accident prevention have given thought to what is meant by “a cause.” To begin to answer the question, “What do we mean by causality?” we will survey some of the major ideas. This will give the reader an appreciation of how current concepts have developed over time and identify some of the major challenges faced by anyone interested in the question.
However, taking a historical approach in this instance does not mean that ideas and concepts emerged in a specific, ordered sequence or developed in a progressive, linear path. Many of the concepts discussed here developed in widely separated places and reached other parts of the world only centuries later. This is clearly illustrated in the development of similar aspects of causality that emerged in the Eastern and Western worlds at different times and without apparent influence from the other sphere. The benefit of the sequential approach is that it provides a structure upon which disparate ideas can be hung and shows how concepts of causality have changed over time. Perhaps even more importantly, tracing the development of the concept of causality over human written history emphasizes the long struggle that humans have had with the issue and supports the notion that a complete understanding may never develop. A historical review also reveals that our current concepts of causality are an amalgam of ideas that have arisen and developed over thousands of years. They reflect on and derive from long traditions of thought that have engaged many groups and cultures. By necessity, this review will be selective. It will highlight some of the most challenging and contentious issues and set the stage for much of the discussion in succeeding chapters.
HISTORICAL OVERVIEW
The earliest human writings demonstrate the centrality of the concept of causality to humankind. Five-thousand-year-old Sumerian cuneiform tablets and 3,500-year-old Egyptian papyri identify forces or beings that brought about (caused) the world in the way that these cultures (or at least the authors) experienced it. Ancient religious tracts such as the Hindu Rig Veda and the Aramaic Tanakh or Old Testament do the same. These ancient texts also link events of the present to the influence of the initiating being or force. The identification of an initiating cause as the explanation for the universe as we know it not only persists today in many religions but also is a central tenet of such scientific hypotheses as the Big Bang theory, which ascribes the makeup of the current physical universe to events that occurred at the instant of its formation, and the pantheistic Gaia concept, which describes the Earth as an organism constructed such that a change in one aspect leads to an adjustment in others in order to sustain equilibrium. Thus, what is today labeled a supernatural origin of events can be found in many if not all cultures and must be addressed if a thorough accounting of the concept of causality is attempted. This will be the focus of chapter 10.
The idea that individual humans can cause events has also been present in Eastern and Western thought for thousands of years, although it is not possible to prove that all groups of human beings have conceptualized causality in this fashion. The Hindu concept of karma, which assigns to individuals responsibility for their actions and explains the form into which a person is reincarnated as a result of past choices, implies that individuals are the agents of cause. The oldest extant compilation of laws, the Code of Hammurabi, which dates to 1750 BCE, likewise assigns to individuals the responsibility for their actions, as do the biblical stories of Adam and Eve, the Flood, and the Ten Commandments. The importance of these documents demonstrates that the concept of causal agency has long been a central aspect of human thought.
Several hundred years after the story of Moses is said to have occurred, the Greeks developed the Western tradition of analytic thinking as a source of knowledge. Democritus (c. 400 BCE) conceived of events as having ultimate single causes, although he suggested that causality could be so complex that it was often hidden from human observation or at the least very difficult to discern. At about the same time, Plato proposed that objects like chairs and concepts such as cause exist as ideals against which actual chairs and causes can be measured or compared.
Plato’s idea that we use ideal models or “exemplars” as a standard against which an actual event is measured has been shown in recent cognitive neuroscience experiments to be an innate human approach. Inherent in it are two theses that will recur throughout this book. First is the idea that once a standard is identified, it can be approached closer and closer over time, even though perfection is never achieved. Second is the idea that the ideal exists as much in the abstract as in actuality. Plato never applied these concepts to the study of cause. Nevertheless, they underpin the approach taken in this book, which holds that it is possible to develop a model of causality that gets closer to the ideal over time by incorporating into the concept those ideas that improve its accuracy and jettisoning those that are no longer helpful. The implication that the Platonic approach has resulted in an increasingly nuanced and deeper concept of causality is embraced by this book, and so is the recognition that a complete and permanent definition cannot be achieved.
Plato’s pupil Aristotle proposed a multifactorial model of cause and effect that describes cause as existing at several different levels of analysis. Table 1.1 lists the four levels of causality that he identified, provides my adaptation of them, and provides a commonly cited example from Aristotle’s writings. Aristotle’s meaning of “cause” was different than what is generally meant in the present era, but his conception is still strikingly modern. He describes the “cause” of a statue. The material cause is the bronze and the unique properties that make that alloy desirable for the production of a representation of a detailed human body. The formal cause is the conception of the ideal body and the concept of making an idealized representation. The efficient cause is the artisan and the skill the artisan brings to the process. The final cause is the purpose of the statue, for example, to exalt the ideal human body or to honor the god represented. “What causes a statue?” is clearly a question about what brought it into being, a question that addresses one aspect of causality, but it is not a question of primary interest today. Although complex, Aristotle’s multifactor, multilevel model was extraordinarily influential for almost two thousand years. For example, when Thomas Aquinas (c. 1225–1274) discussed cause in a theological context, he conceptualized God as operating at each Aristotelian level. Chapter 2 will present an expanded and modified version of the Aristotelian model adapted to current questions.
Table 1.1 Aristotelian Model of Cause
image
With the emergence and development of the scientific method, the conceptualization of cause and the methods for demonstrating causality have undergone major changes over the past four hundred years. Although the scientific method as we know it today had no single beginning, Francis Bacon (1561–1626), in his Novum Organum (1620), is often cited as the first individual to recognize its characteristics and potential. Not an experimentalist himself, Bacon nonetheless recognized that an approach to knowledge that combined the three elements of repeated observation, integration of positive (confirming) and negative (disconfirming) results, and skepticism toward authority as the primary source of accurate information signaled a new way of seeking knowledge. He cited the Danish astronomer Tycho Brahe’s voluminous collection of data on the movement of celestial bodies and subsequent 1512 discovery of a nova (which demonstrated that the universe was not static, contradicting a basic Aristotelian precept) as examples of this new approach to knowledge acquisition.
Other discoveries in the sixteenth century further contradicted the Aristotelian model of the universe and undermined the absolute acceptance of Aristotelian intellectual authority. For example, Copernicus’s claim that the sun, not the Earth, was at the center of the solar system (his book De Revolutionibus was published at the time of his death in 1543) was supported by Johannes Kepler’s (1571–1630) demonstration that the planets’ motion could be described mathematically as ellipses, not perfect circles as Aristotle claimed, and Galileo Galilei’s (1564–1642) identification of moons revolving around Jupiter contradicted Aristotle’s claim that celestial bodies revolved only around the Earth. Furthermore, his belief that moving objects naturally slow down was replaced by Galileo’s demonstration that falling bodies accelerate at a uniform rate and by Isaac Newton’s (1642–1727) concept of momentum—enshrined as his first law of motion—that objects continue to move in the same direction and at the same velocity unless acted upon by an external force.
Galileo directly attacked the Aristotelian model of cause in his book Discourse on Two New Sciences (1638). He proposed that new knowledge is best gained by observation and measurement, not introspection. In the Discourse, the character representing Galileo’s point of view cites his ability to describe the acceleration of falling bodies mathematically but his concomitant inability to identify the cause of the acceleration as evidence that the search for an Aristotelian final cause is futile.
Galileo’s rejection of the Aristotelian idea that cause has multiple meanings and his emphasis on identifying questions or events in which direct measurements can be made (similar to the aspect of cause that Aristotle referred to as “efficient”) established a narrowed concept of cause that persists today. I will refer to this narrower definition of cause as the categorical model because it seeks as causes single events that are either present or absent. This model will be discussed in detail in chapter 3. As noted earlier, this narrowed concept of cause predated Aristotle, but the Aristotelian model so overshadowed it that the categorical approach only regained a prominent role with the emergence of the scientific method in the seventeenth century.
Another of Galileo’s ideas that has been influential in scholarship about causality was highlighted by John Stuart Mill two hundred years later in his use of the phrase “necessary and sufficient.” This conception of cause states that A is a necessary and sufficient cause of B if A always occurs before B and B never occurs without A. This is a very high standard: it implies that an event can have only one cause. This standard cannot be applied in many situations. However, when it does describe a situation, the likelihood of a causal relationship is high.
While the Galilean view has been presented here as a radical move away from the Aristotelian multifactor, multilevel model of causality, this view becomes absolute only in retrospect. Even the scientists of the time had no sense that the pre-Galilean conceptions of causality had been overthrown. For example, both Isaac Newton and Gottfried Wilhelm von Leibniz, two of the most accomplished and best-known scientists (and sometime rivals) of the seventeenth century, wrote philosophical tracts that identified God as the ultimate cause, much as had Thomas Aquinas four centuries earlier. Newton believed that the regularity of the laws that he discovered demonstrated that they were manifestations of God’s work, and Leibniz believed that the organization of the world reflected God’s plan and was, therefore, the best possible manner in which the world could be organized. Both Leibniz and Newton saw a role for experimental and mathematical study but remained convinced that God was the ultimate explanation. Neither saw this dual model as a contradiction but rather conceptualized science and religion as complementary causal models that confirmed each other.
While the Galilean criticism of Aristotle might be characterized as a reemphasis on precipitating cause rather than a rejection of the Aristotelian model, the change was a radical one, and it significantly influenced the approach to cause over the next 350 years. It made the search for “sufficient” elements the defining criterion of causality and narrowed the search for causes to observable and testable elements. In effect, it defined the essence of causality as the identification of precipitating events. What accounted for—what caused—this dramatic development? I suggest it was the concatenation of events in the West during the sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. They included new technologies, such as the telescope; new methods for gathering and analyzing information, such as probabilistic models; great thinkers such as Leibniz, Newton, and Galileo; economic changes that provided leisure time and fiscal support for brilliant individuals to pursue new knowledge outside of the Church; the development of the printing press, which provided a method of broad and relatively rapid information transfer; and the emergence throughout Europe of educational institutions in which individuals who could put together the new observations, technologies, and methods worked. (This is an example of narrative logic, discussed further in chapter 9.)
LIMITATIONS OF THE SCIENTIFIC METHOD
Doubts about the scientific method’s ability to identify causes quickly followed, however, even among individuals who were practitioners of science. For example, René Descartes (1596–1650), an experimentalist whose contributions included Cartesian two-coordinate geometry, the idea that mathematical relationships underlie the basis of physics, and the concept of momentum, expressed skepticism about the ability to gain knowledge through observation alone. He proposed that one should start from stated principles and deduce truths from them. This led to his claim that one could begin from the statement Cogito ergo sum (I am thinking, therefore I exist) and deduce both the existence of God and the duality of the mind and the body.
Such skepticism about relying upon the senses can be traced back to the Greek Stoics fifteen hundred years earlier, but it is Descartes’s suggestion that the method of deduction is the most useful method for identifying causes that deserves attention here because the deductive method is still with us and because Descartes’s applications of it demonstrate that what one claims to deduce is still open to challenge.
Galileo’s and Bacon’s renewed emphasis on precipitation as the defining feature of causality also came under challenge from the Scottish philosopher David Hume (1711–1776). Hume claimed that causality could never be definitively demonstrated because it relied upon inductive reasoning, that is, it required a leap of belief that two events were inevitably linked and, thus, the drawing of conclusions that go beyond the facts. Even if an event B always follows event A, Hume argued, one could only “guess” that A had caused B. Such associations could never prove causality.
Hume did not totally dismiss induction, however, but said it could never establish causality with certainty. Hume’s skepticism about inductive reasoning persists today, both among scientists who object to seeking broad explanations for natural phenomena and among antiscientists who reject the scientific method as a means of increasing knowledge and understanding.
As pointed out by Karl Popper two hundred years later, Hume’s rejection of induction ...

Table of contents

  1. Cover 
  2. Half title
  3. Title
  4. Copyright
  5. Dedication
  6. Contents 
  7. Preface
  8. Introduction
  9. 1. Historical Overview: The Four Approaches to Causality
  10. 2. The Three-Facet Model: An Overview
  11. 3. The Answer Is Either “No” or “Yes”: Causality as a Categorical Concept
  12. 4. Probabilities, Odds, and Risks: Predispositions and Provocations as Causes
  13. 5. A Third Model of Causality: The Emergent, Nonlinear Approach
  14. 6. Empirical: The Physical Sciences
  15. 7. Empirical: The Biological Sciences
  16. 8. Empirical: Epidemiology
  17. 9. Narrative Truth: The Empathic Method
  18. 10. Cause in the Ecclesiastic Tradition
  19. 11. Seeking the Why of Things: The Model Applied
  20. References
  21. Index