The Practices of the Enlightenment
eBook - ePub

The Practices of the Enlightenment

Aesthetics, Authorship, and the Public

  1. English
  2. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  3. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

The Practices of the Enlightenment

Aesthetics, Authorship, and the Public

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

Rethinking the relationship between eighteenth-century Pietist traditions and Enlightenment thought and practice, The Practices of Enlightenment unravels the complex and often neglected religious origins of modern secular discourse. Mapping surprising routes of exchange between the religious and aesthetic writings of the period and recentering concerns of authorship and audience, this book revitalizes scholarship on the Enlightenment.

By engaging with three critical categories—aesthetics, authorship, and the public sphere— The Practices of Enlightenment illuminates the relationship between religious and aesthetic modes of reflective contemplation, autobiography and the hermeneutics of the self, and the discursive creation of the public sphere. Focusing largely on German intellectual life, this critical engagement also extends to France through Rousseau and to England through Shaftesbury. Rereading canonical works and lesser-known texts by Goethe, Lessing, and Herder, the book challenges common narratives recounting the rise of empiricist philosophy, the idea of the "sensible" individual, and the notion of the modern author as celebrity, bringing new perspective to the Enlightenment concepts of instinct, drive, genius, and the public sphere.

Frequently asked questions

Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Yes, you can access The Practices of the Enlightenment by Dorothea von Mücke in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Philosophy & Aesthetics in Philosophy. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Year
2015
ISBN
9780231539333
PART I
THE BIRTH OF AESTHETICS, THE ENDS OF TELEOLOGY, AND THE RISE OF GENIUS
In her study The Author, Art, and the Market Martha Woodmansee isolates two key concepts of eighteenth-century aesthetics: disinterested interest and original genius. The concern of Woodmansee’s study consists not in elucidating Kant’s aesthetics, nor in writing the history of these concepts as a dialogue between theoreticians and philosophers, but rather in providing an altogether different, until then entirely neglected, rather mundane context to illuminate their sudden emergence: changes in the German-language book market in the second half of the eighteenth century, the sudden rise of general literacy together with a surge of entertainment literature in the vernacular, primarily comical stories, exotic travel narratives, and gothic fiction replacing the predominance of religious devotional literature of the first half of the century.
Woodmansee explains the rise of the concept of disinterested interest as a reaction of ambitious but financially unsuccessful writers to losing out on the market against the writers of popular entertainment fiction. In this light, Karl Philipp Moritz’s concept of the work of art as a self-sufficient, autonomous entity that would not entertain its reader or beholder but instead demand an attitude of disinterested interest becomes a defensive stance of a writer who cannot profitably sell his own products.1 Similarly, Woodmansee situates the rise of the concept of original genius in the context of the utter absence of the protection of intellectual property: writers were at best given an honorarium; publishers and booksellers obtained the profit; however, they too were plagued by the prevalence of unauthorized reprints. Not until Johann Gottlieb Fichte provided a way of distinguishing between three aspects of a literary work—1.) the physical object of the book, which could be sold; 2.) the ideas, which would already be part of common property; and 3.) the specific form, which would retain the work’s individualizing features, derived from the specific character of its author—was there a way of demanding an author’s copyright: The author would own the words in their unique articulation and should be granted legal protection for this kind of intellectual property by way of copyright. The concept of original genius as it became popular especially in Germany in the reception of Edward Young’s Conjectures on Original Composition then needs to be seen as providing the model for this connection between the quasi-organic individuality of the work of art and the unique individuality of its maker. The eighteenth-century concept of original genius would not only provide a rationale for legally protecting an author’s copyright but it would furthermore motivate a set of new procedures for reading and interpreting a work, namely those hermeneutic procedures that would read the text by fully engaging with animating and reconstructing the individualizing totality of the artifact.2
Part 1, “The Birth of Aesthetics, the Ends of Teleology, and the Rise of the Genius,” undertakes a comparable project to that of Martha Woodmansee in that it also privileges “disinterested interest” and “original genius” as crucial innovations of eighteenth-century aesthetics. Like Woodmansee, I am also interested in drawing attention to and examining until now neglected discursive contexts that have been crucial to the fate of these two concepts. First I shall study religious practices of contemplation as providing the background for the emergence of a new kind of disinterested aesthetic contemplation, but I will also look at the philosophical trajectory of conceptualizing this ability for aesthetic contemplation. Moreover, I shall show that the discourse of philosophy alone does not suffice to understand the trajectory of these concepts. Another discursive context, a teleological discourse about the order of nature, needs to be taken into account in order to come to a fuller understanding of the trajectory of these concepts. Thus I shall trace two aspects of a teleological understanding of nature in their relationship to the emergence of eighteenth-century aesthetics: I will show how the functional understanding of an animal’s appetitive and instinctual behavior crucially informs the conceptualization of “disinterested interest” as a feature that sets apart the human animal from all other animals. Already here we can see the decisive break with the moral authority of nature in asserting the human animal’s instinctual weakness as the feature that allows for self-directed behavior that is not automatically self-interested. And then there is the teleological understanding of change in nature, which greatly informs the eighteenth-century concept of original genius as a radical innovator that produces unique individuals. Whereas Woodmansee’s contextualization of “disinterested interest” and “original genius” reduces these concepts to their ideological function in the context of important changes in the print and publishing market of the eighteenth century, the contextualizations I will unfold in the following chapters will show their role in the shaping of a secular humanist Enlightenment.
1
THE SURPRISING ORIGINS OF ENLIGHTENMENT AESTHETICS
Traditionally, when discussing the beginnings of Enlightenment aesthetics, intellectual historians and historians of philosophy point to the philosopher Alexander Baumgarten, who set out to investigate the particularities of sensuous cognition.1 With the creation of a philosophical subdiscipline, which he called aesthetics, Baumgarten designated a domain that valued the lower faculties, that attributed to the work of art a specific insight-generating power, and that reflected on the pleasures of the imagination.2 For the purposes of this chapter, however, I shall bracket this approach. Instead of tracing a certain trend in philosophical discourse about the value of art and the specific kind of access to truth that could be provided by works of art, I shall turn to a set of practices and habits. I am interested in investigating what in the wider population of a general, not philosophically specialized readership would have prepared the ground for radically rethinking the nature of aesthetic pleasure, so that it would be considered no longer an exclusive domain of connoisseurs but instead would become valued as a universal human and humanizing capacity. I shall do so by investigating practices of attention, of serious, committed observation directed at seemingly trivial, mundane, quotidian phenomena, which in the process of contemplation would reveal to the observer a hidden significance. My goal is to show that these practices of attention ultimately served to form habits of cultivating a pure, pleasurable contemplation utterly different from the interested engagement with something agreeable, capable of satisfying the senses. Such practices of attention, capable of endowing objects of observation with the ability to elicit in the observer a pleasure that would transcend sensuous gratification, constitute an important component of many kinds of spiritual exercises and practices of sublimation that can be found throughout history. Thus it is the challenge of this chapter to isolate one specific strand of spiritual exercises, which would have been widespread and enduring enough to be considered relevant for having actually shaped a certain mindset of the general readership of that period.
The practices of attention and observation I shall isolate as the cultural site that prepared the ground for the promotion of “disinterested interest” as the key to Enlightenment aesthetics can be clearly distinguished from other practices of attention that also gained significance during the eighteenth century. In her “Attention and the Values of Nature in the Enlightenment,” Lorraine Daston examines how within the framework of natural theology the practices of observation of eighteenth-century naturalists lead to the enshrinement of the moral authority of nature expressed in Pope’s dictum from his “An Essay on Man”: “Whatever is, is Right.” She shows how such naturalists as Charles Bonnet would devote endless hours to highly focused attention on the lowliest insects, to recording the most exacting, detailed descriptions of these observations, but also to the pleasures and joys they would take in these thus individualized creatures beautified by the art of attention and description. Daston argues that it was especially the focus on “what Bonnet would call the ‘organic Economy’ in which the ‘arrangement and play of different parts of organized bodies’ explained operations like growth and generation” that would guide the focus of these naturalists to analyze “objects into interlocking parts” and trace “the fit of form to function with an eagle eye for ‘fitness.’”3
By contrast, the practices of attention that I will discuss in this chapter did not have as their goal the precise, detailed observation of natural phenomena within an overall framework of natural theology aimed at understanding and explaining the fitness and utility of each and every creature. Their aim instead consisted in the transformation of the observer and in the spiritual growth of the believer. And although these practices might focus on a mundane, lowly object, they are aimed at a spiritual realm beyond that of the senses. They are very distinct from the practices of attention of the naturalists, which involve the observer’s active interaction with concrete natural phenomena, placing them under the microscope, anatomizing, taking notes, and drawing details. The practices I shall study revolve entirely around the training of the observer’s own mental and emotional faculties. The activity of observing a specific sight or object is primarily a means to that other end, and in this regard such practices of attention are highly self-reflexive. These practices of attention began to take hold somewhat earlier than those studied by Daston, and they were much more popular. They emerged in the realm of popular religion, in Protestant areas during the seventeenth century.
In what follows I shall base my argument on the analysis of one of the most popular books among the vernacular literature of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, Johann Arndt’s devotional guide Vom wahren Christenthum (On True Christianity). First published in 1605, True Christianity went through numerous editions throughout the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries and it was translated into many languages. The cultural influence of this book was enormous. Arndt’s True Christianity gave lasting shape to the form of piety that became known as Pietism.4 Its formative, pivotal role for the development and spread of this religious movement can be glimpsed from one moment in its publication history. In 1675 Jakob Spener (1635–1707), generally considered the founder of Pietism, chose to publish his critique of the orthodox church establishment and hope for both institutional reform and religious renewal, his Pia Desideria, as part of a preface to a new edition of True Christianity. Already this move—Spener’s decision to integrate his programmatic manifesto into the preface of Arndt’s by then established devotional guidebook—indicates the kind of intervention that was at stake in this religious reform movement: religion was to rid itself of doctrinal pedantry and institutional authority and be based instead on a lived, practiced spirituality.
Johann Arndt’s True Christianity went through numerous editions, was translated into many languages, and became, among the vernacular literature of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, one of the most widely read, or rather most widely used, books of the Protestant region of that time. It is a book that does not demand a linear reading, but offers itself as an organized resource of instructions for concrete exercises. In that sense, True Christianity is not a book that attempts to deliver a message but rather a guide that aims at recruiting practitioners. In order to get a better understanding of what was so special about Arndt’s approach to spiritual exercises, it is worthwhile to compare True Christianity with another quite popular devotional text. For Arndt was not the only one composing Protestant meditational literature. Beginning with Martin Luther there was an entire tradition of cultivating meditation as a means by which believers were to practice making connections between biblical passages and their own lives. A popular work of Protestant meditational literature (though not quite as popular as Arndt’s) was Johann Gerhard’s Meditationes Sacrae. Its first edition appeared in 1606, just one year after the first edition of Arndt’s True Christianity. Gerhard’s Meditationes were published first in Latin, then also quite frequently in German, and other translations were made into vernacular languages, including translations into verse. Although some editions of Gerhard’s Meditationes were augmented by visual emblems, these never achieved the lasting impact of the equivalent illustrated editions of Arndt’s True Christianity. The most important difference consists in the way in which the meditations are presented. Gerhard’s Meditationes offer a mixture of prayer and admonition with reflections on aspects of the religious message. They are primarily an ongoing back and forth between the address to God and the address to the believer’s soul. They are only interrupted by admonitions to the believer to remember crucial elements from the life and suffering of Jesus and to apply those to her or his own life. Arndt’s meditations, by contrast, as I will show, are quite differently composed. Whereas the meditation in the case of Gerhard is provided by the verbal text of each meditation as a complete unit, which could be compared to a “libretto,” providing the actual words of prayer to God or Christ, of admonishing one’s own soul, of lamenting one’s own depravity, etc., Arndt’s meditations work like a rebus, a complex set of narratives and images that involve the reader more actively and take the reader beyond the text of the meditation. For they focus the readers’ attention on external, secular phenomena, which then are to be considered and compared in their complex way of functioning to a religious phenomenon.5 Thus it is Arndt’s very special use and selection of images that sets his work apart from other devotional literature of his time.6 In Arndt’s work we can find a deployment of images that crucially involves the external, secular world for meditational purposes, an aspect that I will argue had a deeply transformative potential for this religious practice in the sense that it opened it up for its migration toward an exclusively secular context.
In what follows I shall first show how Arndt’s text makes use of verbal images, of similes and comparisons, for the famous visual illustrations were not added to Arndt’s text until the Riga edition of 1678, about fifty years after its author’s death in 1621.7 Then I shall turn to these visual emblems, which in 1696 were enriched by prose explanations. I shall show how these illustrations together with their prose commentaries isolate and heighten the spiritual exercises that are already part of the verbal text such that they prepared the grounds for the cultural practices of observation, contemplation, and reflection that by the second half of the eighteenth century would be considered constitutive of aesthetic experience.
The main goal of True Christianity is to guide each individual believer to become a better Christian, which means to bear the hardships of life without anger or complaint, and to reflect on the basic religious doctrines in terms of their applicability to the reader’s own life. The fallen nature of man, the nature of true faith, the value of patiently enduring suffering—these religious truths are carefully explained in view of complex verbal images that the reader is asked to contemplate.8 Thus, for instance, the second chapter of True Christianity is entirely devoted to bringing home the message of man’s fallen nature. Arndt’s readers are to see themselves as sinful and in dire need of redemption. His method of getting his readers deeply involved in thinking about the fundamental Christian dogma of original sin and applying it to their own lives is already captured in the table of contents below the title of the second chapter:
1) Adam’s fall as the most terrible sin. 2) Can be made clearer by look...

Table of contents

  1. Cover 
  2. Series Page
  3. Title Page
  4. Copyright
  5. Dedication
  6. Contents 
  7. Acknowledgments
  8. Introduction
  9. Part I: The Birth of Aesthetics, the Ends of Teleology, and the Rise of Genius
  10. Part II: Confessional Discourse, Autobiography, and Authorship
  11. Part III: Imagined Communities and The Mobilization of a Critical Public
  12. Notes
  13. Index
  14. Series List