The Indispensable Milton Friedman
eBook - ePub

The Indispensable Milton Friedman

Essays on Politics and Economics

  1. 256 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

The Indispensable Milton Friedman

Essays on Politics and Economics

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

Milton Friedman is one of the most famous economists in history. His writings and theories on everything from capitalism and freedom to deregulation and welfare have inspired movements, influenced government policies, and changed the course of America's economic history.Now, acclaimed Friedman biographer Dr. Lanny Ebenstein brings together twenty of Friedman's greatest essays in his new book, The Indispensable Milton Friedman: Essays on Politics and Economics. The only collection of Friedman's writings to span his entire career, The Indispensable Milton Friedman: Essays on Politics and Economics features some of Friedman's never-before-republished writings as well as the best and most timeless of his works.These exceptional essays not only illuminate the progression of Friedman's thought, but explain how America might overcome some of its most difficult challenges. Broken into two sections, politics and economics, The Indispensable Milton Friedman shows how we can ultimately turn America around, and is more necessary than ever during this critical election year and time of economic uncertainty.

Frequently asked questions

Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Yes, you can access The Indispensable Milton Friedman by Lanny Ebenstein in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Economics & Economic Theory. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Publisher
Regnery
Year
2012
ISBN
9781596988170
PART ONE
POLITICS
dp n="16" folio="" ?dp n="17" folio="3" ?
ESSAY ONE
NEO-LIBERALISM AND ITS PROSPECTS
1951






In his magnificent book, Law and Public Opinion, A. V. Dicey distinguished between the trend of legislation on the one hand and the trend of opinion on the other. Legislation, he argued, is dominated by the underlying current of opinion, but only after a considerable lag. Men legislate on the basis of the philosophy they imbibed in their youth, so some twenty years or more may elapse between a change in the underlying current of opinion and the resultant alteration in public policy. Dicey sets 1870 to 1890 as the period in which public opinion in England turned away from individualism (Manchester liberalism) and toward collectivism; yet he points out that economic legislation was not strongly affected by the new trend of opinion until after the turn of the century.
In most of the world, legislation is still largely dominated by the trend of opinion toward collectivism that Dicey documented some forty-odd years ago. True, there have recently been a whole series of elections in which the Right has gained at the expense of the Left—in Australia, England, and the United States, and continental Europe. But even if a political trend to the right were to develop out of these small beginnings, which is by no means certain, it would probably mean simply collectivist legislation of a somewhat different kind to be administered by different people. The men of the conservative parties, no less than those of the left, have been affected by the underlying current of opinion. Men may deviate in emphasis from basic social values and beliefs but few can hold a thoroughly different philosophy, can fail to be infected by the intellectual air they breathe. By the standards of nineteenth century individualism, we are all of us collectivists in smaller or greater measure.
A number of small incidents will illustrate my point that a political trend to the right is by no means synonymous with a reversal of the trend toward collectivism. A few years ago, I happened to be in England when the Labour Government proposed a higher excise tax on tobacco as a means of curtailing tobacco imports. In reporting this decision, the government spokesman deplored the necessity of using a tax to curtail consumption and justified it on the grounds that direct rationing of tobacco products had been deemed too difficult administratively. Far from applauding the Labour Government for having decided to use the price system rather than direct controls, the Conservatives hastened to condemn the government for rationing “by the purse” instead of directly. More recently, in the United States, the president asked Congress for emergency economic powers to meet the problems raised by re-armament. He did not ask for powers to control prices and wages. The Congress insisted on giving him such powers as well, and many Republicans were among those who insisted he should have them. If I may speak of my own country again, the Republicans profess to be in favour of free enterprise and strongly opposed to a drift toward socialism. Yet their published program favours protective tariffs, agricultural subsidies and support of the prices of agricultural products as well as a number of other measures that can fairly be termed collectivist in their implications.
I do not mean to argue that it makes no difference which party is elected, which side gains votes. It clearly makes a difference of degree if not of kind and offers the opportunity to begin a drift in a new direction. My point is rather that the direction this drift takes will be determined not by the day-to-day shifts in political power or by the slogans of the parties or even their platforms but by the underlying current of opinion which may be already—if only we could penetrate its mysteries—determining a new direction for the future.
While the trend of legislation is still strongly toward collectivism, I have the feeling that this is no longer true of the underlying trend of opinion. Until a few years ago, there was a widespread—if naive—faith among even the intellectual classes that nationalization would replace production for profit with production for use, whatever these catchwords may mean; that centralized planning would replace unplanned chaos with efficient coordination; that it was only necessary to give the State more power in order to solve this supposed paradox of poverty in the midst of plenty and to prevent the “selfish interests” from exploiting the working masses; and that because socialists favoured peace and international amity, socialism would in some unspecified way further these goals. The experience of the last few years has shaken if not shattered these naive beliefs. It has become abundantly clear that nationalization solves no fundamental economic problems; that centralized economic planning is consistent with its own brand of chaos and disorganization; and that centralized planning may raise far greater barriers to free international intercourse than unregulated capitalism ever did. Equally important, the growing power of the State has brought widespread recognition of the extent to which centralized economic control is likely to endanger individual freedom and liberty.
If these judgments are correct, we are currently at one of these periods when what Dicey called the “cross-currents” of public opinion are at a maximum, a period at which underlying opinion is confused, vague and chaotic. The same beliefs are still largely held by the same people, but there is no longer the same unthinking acceptance of them. Stubbornness and unwillingness to relinquish a faith once blindly held are taking the place of fanaticism. The stage is set for the growth of a new current of opinion to replace the old, to provide the philosophy that will guide the legislators of the next generation even though it can hardly affect those of this one.
Ideas have little chance of making much headway against a strong tide; their opportunity comes when the tide has ceased running strong but has not yet turned. This is, if I am right, such a time, and it affords a rare opportunity to those of us who believe in liberalism to affect the new direction the tide takes. We have a new faith to offer; it behooves us to make it clear to one and all what that faith is.
The major fault of the collectivist philosophy that has dominated the western world is not in its objectives—collectivists have wanted to do good, to maintain and extend freedom and democracy, and at the same time to improve the material welfare of the great masses of the people. The fault has rather been in the means. Failure to recognize the difficulty of the economic problem of efficiently coordinating the activities of millions of people led to a readiness to discard the price system without an adequate substitute and to a belief that it would be easy to do much better by a central plan. Together with an overestimate of the extent of agreement on detailed objectives, it lead to a belief that one could achieve wide-spread agreement on a “plan” couched in precise terms and hence avoid those conflicts of interest that could be received only by coercion. The means collectivists seek to employ are fundamentally inconsistent with the ends they seek to attain. A state with power to do good by the same token is in a position to do harm; and there is much reason to believe that the power will sooner or later get into the hands of those who will use it for evil purposes.
The collectivist belief in the ability of direct action by the State to remedy all evils is itself, however, an understandable reaction to a basic error in nineteenth-century individualist philosophy. This philosophy assigned almost no role to the state other than the maintenance of order and the enforcement of contracts. It was a negative philosophy. The state could do only harm. Laissez-faire must be the rule. In taking this position, it underestimated the danger that private individuals could through agreement and combination usurp power and effectively limit the freedom of other individuals; it failed to see that there were some functions the price system could not perform and that unless these other functions were somehow provided for, the price system could not discharge effectively the tasks for which it is admirably fitted.
A new faith must avoid errors. It must give high place to a severe limitation on the power of the state to interfere in the detailed activities of individuals; at the same time; it must explicitly recognize that there are important positive functions that must be performed by the state. The doctrine sometimes called neo-liberalism which has been developing more or less simultaneously in many parts of the world and which in America is associated particularly with the name of Henry Simons is such a faith. No one can say that this doctrine will triumph. One can only say that it is in many ways ideally suited to fill the vacuum that seems to me to be developing in the beliefs of intellectual classes the world over.
Neo-liberalism would accept the nineteenth century liberal emphasis in the fundamental importance of the individual, but it would substitute for the nineteenth-century goal of laissez-faire as a means to this end, the goal of the competitive order. It would seek to use competition among producers to protect the consumer from exploitation, competition among employers to protect workers and owners of property and competition among consumers to protect the enterprises themselves. The state would police the system, establish conditions favorable to competition and prevent monopoly, provide a stable monetary framework, and relieve acute misery and distress. The citizens would be protected against the state by the existence of a free private market; and against one another by the preservation of competition.
The detailed program designed to implement this vision cannot be described in full here. But it may be well to expand a bit on the functions that would be exercised by the state, since this is the respect in which it differs most from both nineteenth century individualism and collectivism. The state would of course have the function of maintaining law and order and of engaging in “public works” of the classical variety. But beyond this it would have the function of providing a framework within which free competition could flourish and the price system operate effectively. This involves two major tasks: first, the preservation of freedom to establish enterprises in any field, to enter any profession or occupation; second, the provision of monetary stability.
The first would require the avoidance of state regulation of entry, the establishment of rules for the operation of business enterprises that would make it difficult or impossible for an enterprise to keep out competitors by any means other than selling a better product at a lower price, and the prohibition of combinations of enterprises or actions by enterprises in restraint of trade. American experience demonstrates, I think, that action along these lines could produce a high degree of competition without any extensive intervention by the state. There can be little doubt that the Sherman anti-trust laws, despite the lack of vigorous enforcement during most of their existence, are one of the major reasons for the far higher degree of competition in the United States than in Europe.
The provision of monetary stability would require a reform of the monetary and banking system to eliminate the private creation of money and to subject changes in the quantity of money to definite rules designed to promote stability. The provision of money, except for pure commodity money, cannot be left to competition and has always been recognized as an appropriate function of the state. Indeed, it is ironic and tragic that the consequences of the failure of government planning in this area—which, in my view, include both extreme inflations and deep depressions—should form so large a part of the alleged case against private enterprise, and be cited as reasons for giving government control over yet other areas.
Finally; the government would have the function of relieving misery and distress. Our humanitarian sentiments demand that some provision should be made for those who “draw blanks in the lottery of life.” Our world has become too complicated and intertwined, and we have become too sensitive, to leave this function entirely to private charity or local responsibility. It is essential, however, that the performance of this function involve the minimum of interference with the market. There is justification for subsidizing people because they are poor, whether they are farmers or city-dwellers, young or old. There is no justification for subsidizing farmers as farmers rather than because they are poor. There is justification in trying to achieve a minimum income for all; there is no justification for setting a minimum wage and thereby increasing the number of people without income; there is no justification in trying to achieve a minimum consumption of bread separately, meat separately, and so on.
These are broad powers and important responsibilities that the neoliberal would give to the state. But the essential point is that they are all powers that are limited in scope and capable of being exercised by general rules applying to all. They are designed to permit government by law rather than by administrative order. They leave scope for the exercise of individual initiative by millions of independent economic units. They leave to the unparalleled efficiency of the impersonal price system the coordination of the detailed economic activities of these units. And above all, by leaving the ownership and operation of economic resources predominantly in private hands, they preserve a maximum of individual freedom and liberty.
002
Even if I am right in my belief that the underlying trend of opinion toward collectivism has passed its peak and been reversed, we may yet be doomed to a long period of collectivism. The trend of legislation is still in that direction; and, unhappily, collectivism is likely to prove far more difficult to reverse or change fundamentally than laissez-faire; especially if it goes so far as to undermine the essentials of political democracy. And this trend, which would be present in any event, is certain to be radically accelerated by the cold war, let alone by the more dreadful alternative of a full-scale war. But if these obstacles can be overcome, neo-liberalism offers a real hope of a better future, a hope that is already a strong cross-current of opinion and that is capable of capturing the enthusiasm of men of goodwill everywhere, and thereby becoming the major current of opinion.
dp n="24" folio="10" ?dp n="25" folio="11" ?
ESSAY TWO
LIBERALISM, OLD STYLE
1955






Liberalism, as it developed in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries and flowered in the nineteenth, puts major emphasis on the freedom of individuals to control their own destinies. Individualism is its creed; collectivism and tyranny its enemy. The state exists to protect individuals from coercion by other individuals or groups and to widen the range within which individuals can exercise their freedom; it is purely instrumental and has no significance in and of itself. Society is a collection of individuals and the whole is no greater than the sum of its parts. The ultimate values are the values of the individuals who form the society; there are no super-individual values or ends. Nations may be convenient administrative units; nationalism is an alien creed.
In politics, liberalism expressed itself as a reaction against authoritarian regimes. Liberals favored limiting the rights of hereditary rulers, establishing democratic parliamentary institutions, extending the franchise, and guaranteeing civil rights. They favored such measures both for their own sake, as a direct expression of essential political freedoms, and as a means of facilitating the adoption of liberal economic measures.
dp n="26" folio="12" ?
In economic policy, liberalism expressed itself as a reaction against government intervention in economic affairs. Liberals favored free competition at home and free trade among nations. They regarded the organization of economic activity through free private enterprise operating in a competitive market as a direct expression of essential economic freedoms and as important also in facilitating the preservation of political liberty. They regarded free trade among nations as a means of eliminating conflicts that might otherwise produce war. Just as within a country, individuals following their own interests under the pressures of competition indirectly promote the interests of the whole; so, between countries, individuals following their own interests under conditions of free trade, indirectly promote the interests of the world as a whole. By providing free access to goods, services, and resources on the same terms to all, free trade would knit the world into a single economic community.
“Liberalism” has taken on a very different meaning in the twe...

Table of contents

  1. Praise
  2. Title Page
  3. Dedication
  4. Introduction
  5. PART ONE - POLITICS
  6. PART TWO - ECONOMICS
  7. APPENDIX - COMMANDING HEIGHTS INTERVIEW
  8. ORIGINAL PUBLICATION INFORMATION
  9. Copyright Page