Knowledge and Scientific and Religious Belief
eBook - ePub

Knowledge and Scientific and Religious Belief

  1. 243 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

Knowledge and Scientific and Religious Belief

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

The present book is a book on epistemology with the special and new focus on the relation of different types of knowledge and a differentiated comparison to both scientific and religious belief. The present book distinguishes seven types of knowledge and compares them with both scientific and religious belief.

The ususal view is that scientific and religious belief have nothing or not much in common. Although there are important differences, in contradistinction to this widespread view it is shown that there are also many similarities between them. There are similarities concerning the reasons for belief, with respect to the action of believing, concerning a similar voluntary component, or even concerning properties of the content of belief.

A detailed discussion of many types of knowledge and a differentiated comparison to scientific and religious belief is an important new contribution to the scientific literature in epistemology.

Frequently asked questions

Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on “Cancel Subscription” - it’s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time you’ve paid for. Learn more here.
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlego’s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan you’ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, we’ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Yes, you can access Knowledge and Scientific and Religious Belief by Paul Weingartner in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Philosophy & Epistemology in Philosophy. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Publisher
De Gruyter
Year
2018
ISBN
9783110584516

1Whether it is Possible to Know Something

1.1Arguments Contra

1.11 As Georgias of Leontini (483 B. C.) says we cannot know something since:
(1) Suppose there is nothing; then there is no knowledge because to know means to know something.
(2) Suppose there is something; then it could not be known. For if there is knowledge of being, then what is thought must be and not-being could not be thought at all; in which case there could be no error, which is absurd.1
Thus it seems doubtful whether it is possible to know something.
1.12 To know something about real things means to judge them as they are in reality. As Sextus Empiricus says, it is impossible to judge things as they really are.
The Mode based upon relativity as we have already said is that whereby the object has such and such an appearance in relation to the subject judging and to the concomitant percepts, but as to its real nature, we suspend judgement.2
Therefore it seems doubtful whether it is possible to know something about real things.
1.13 An assertion can be called knowledge only if the assertion is true. As Sextus Empiricus says, if someone claims that his assertion is true he ought to give a proof for the truth of his assertion. And then again a proof for this proof and so on.
The Mode based upon regress ad infinitum is that whereby we assert that the thing adduced as a proof of the matter proposed, needs a further proof, and this again another, and so on ad infinitum so that the consequence is suspension, as we posses no starting point for our argument.3
This leads to an infinite regress without terminus. Thus the original claim cannot be proven to be true, and consequently an assertion cannot be called knowledge.

1.2Arguments Pro

1.21 “Bodily Awareness” is one type of direct, immediate knowledge.
...the body is originally constituted in a double way: first it is a physical thing ... secondly I find on it, and I sense ‘on’ it and ‘in’ it: warmth on the back of the hand, coldness in the feet, sensations of touch in the fingertips.4
‘My body’ is the body of which, when I am conscious, I have self-conscious knowledge.5
Therefore it is possible to know something.
1.22 To be able to calculate with the help of the multiplication table implies to have knowledge within a small part of finite number theory. Every educated child manages to calculate with the calculation table. Therefore it is possible to know something.

1.3Proposed Answer

The statement “it is possible to know something” can have different meanings. For a more accurate analysis, we shall understand “something” as some state of affairs, which can be represented by some statement or proposition p. Then to know something can be understood as to know that p is the case or to know that p is true. Under this interpretation, the statement “it is possible to know something” can have three meanings which differ in strength:

1.3.1Three Meanings, Different in Stength

(1) It is possible that someone (i. e. some human being) has knowledge concerning some proposition p (i. e. knows that some proposition p is true or that the respective state of affairs obtains). Symbolically: ♢(∃x∈H, ∃p) xKp
(2) It is possible that everyone (i. e. every human being) has knowledge concerning some (or other) proposition p. Symbolically: ♢(∀x∈H, ∃p) xKp
(3) It is possible that there is some proposition p such that everyone has knowledge concerning p (i. e. knows that p is true or that the respective state of affairs obtains). Symbolically: ♢(∃p, ∀x∈H) xKp
In the arguments contra, the possibility to know something is denied. This means that these arguments claim the negation of (1) or (2) or (3). The respective negations are the following:
(1’) It is not possible that someone has knowledge concerning some proposition. Symbolically: ¬♢(∃x∈H, ∃p) xKp
(2’) It is not possible that everyone has knowledge concerning some (or other) proposition. Symbolically: ¬♢(∀x∈H, ∃p) xKp
(3’) It is not possible that concerning some proposition p, everyone has knowledge of p. Symbolically: ¬♢(∃p, ∀x∈H) xKp
Statement (1) is the weakest claim concerning human knowledge and consequently claim (1’) is the strongest kind of skepticism concerning human knowledge. Such a claim can be refuted by a single example of human knowledge possessed by a single person as the self-conscious knowledge (“bodily awareness”) of the own body or as a calculation according to the multiplication table. On a higher level (1) also claims that there is expert-knowledge, some selected (by education and training) people know some specific things. To deny this, i. e. to claim (1’) is certainly absurd. We need experts all the time (physicians, technicians, pilots, bus drivers, chemists, peasants, ...). Statement (2) is stronger than (1) claiming that it is possible that everyone has some knowledge in some domain or other. If someone denies this possibility, i. e. if he claims (2’) then he denies that all people have knowledge in some domain. It is clearly absurd to deny this since very simple things like self-conscious knowledge or E1–E4 below everyone will know. Statement (3) is even stronger than (2) claiming that it is possible that there are some propositions with respect to which everyone has knowledge. A statement of the form “it is possible that p” is proved if one can give an example for an actual instance of p, since if p is the case, then possible p holds. Several kinds of such examples can be given which justify statement (3). Some famous ones from the philosophical tradition are these:

1.3.2Famous Examples E 1–E 5

E 1 “If there is only one sun then there are not two.”; “Either the world is finite, or the world is infinite.”6
E 2 “If he doubts he knows that he doubts ... if he doubts he knows that he does not know.”7
E 3 “Si enim fallor, sum.” Since he who does not exist cannot err. Therefore I am if I err.8
E 4 “Cogito ergo sum.” I think, therefore I am.9
Examples E 2 – E 4 are concerned with self-reflecting knowledge. E 1 is concerned with knowledge of simple logical propositions. In this respect Aristotle has proposed his principle of non-contradiction as the most general and the most basic logical principle which implies and justifies statement (3) above: “Let this, then, suffice to show that the most indisputable of all beliefs is this:
E 5 Contradictory statements are not at the same time true.”10
The principle E 5 is the most tolerant formulation of the principle of non-contradiction which is invariant w. r. t different types of systems of logic like classical two-valued logic, intuitionistic logic, minimal logic, different types of many-valued logic.11
E 1–E 5 refute the claim that knowledge is not possible, expressed in different strength by (1’), (2’) and (3’). By this, they justify the statements (1) and (2) and (3).

1.4Answers to the Objections

1.41 (To 1.11:) There are at least three possibilities to interpret Gorgias’ claims. First, he did not take them serious himself, but, as a Sophist, wanted just to provoke. Second, he took them serious because he gave some arguments of defence, although these arguments contain untenable premises like “being can neither be one nor be many.”12 Third, he wanted to stress the fallibility of human knowledge. In this case, he starts with the experience that there is error in human thinking. Moreover, if knowledge is not compatible with that kind of error we have to give up knowledge. “What is thought must be, and not-being could not be thought of at all” is not a literal quotation from the fragments but seems to be a reasonable interpretation. If correct, it shows that Gorgias did not differentiate between being and being so, and not between existing and non-existing objects to which our thoughts are directed.13 It is correct that thinking is intentionally directed to some object. However, such objects may exist (in space-time like Venus or independent of space-time like the prime number between 5 and 11) or not exist (in space-time like a perpetuum mobile or independent of space-time like the prime number between 31 and 37). Thus there can be error concerning the existence or non-existence (being or not-being). However, errors occur much more frequently concerning being so or not being so, i. e. concerning the question whether t...

Table of contents

  1. Cover
  2. Title Page
  3. Copyright
  4. Preface
  5. Contents
  6. 1 Whether it is Possible to Know Something
  7. 2 Whether it is Possible to Know Something with Certainty
  8. 3 Whether it is Possible to Know Something Universal
  9. 4 Whether Knowledge is Justified True Belief
  10. 5 Whether Knowledge is Possessing Information
  11. 6 Whether there are Properties Common to All Seven Types of Knowledge
  12. 7 Whether it is Necessary to Believe Something
  13. 8 Whether to Believe is the Same as not to Know
  14. 9 Whether Knowledge of Reasons for Belief is a Necessary Condition of Belief
  15. 10 Whether there are Supporting Reasons for Religious Belief
  16. 11 Whether There is a Voluntary Component in Scientific and in Religious Belief
  17. 12 Whether Religious Belief Can Be a Kind of Knowledge
  18. 13 A Theory of Knowledge, Belief and Assumption
  19. Bibliography
  20. Index