The Animal Catalyst
eBook - ePub

The Animal Catalyst

Towards Ahuman Theory

  1. 224 pages
  2. English
  3. ePUB (mobile friendly)
  4. Available on iOS & Android
eBook - ePub

The Animal Catalyst

Towards Ahuman Theory

Book details
Book preview
Table of contents
Citations

About This Book

The Animal Catalyst deals with the 'question' of 'what is an animal' and also in some instances, 'what is a human'? It pushes critical animal studies in important new directions; it re-examines basic assumptions, suggests new paradigms for how we can live and function ecologically, in a world that is not simply "ours." It argues that it is not enough to recognise the ethical demands placed upon us by our encounters with animals, or to critique our often murderous treatment of them: this simply reinforces human exceptionalism. Featuring contributions from leading academics, lawyers, artists and activists, the book examines key issues such as: - How "compassion" for animals reinforces ideas of what distinguishes human beings from other animals.
- How speciesism and human centricity are built into the legal system.
- How individualist subjectivity works in relation to animals who may not think of themselves in the same way.
- How any consideration of animal others must involve a radical deconstruction of our very notion of the "human."
- How art, philosophy and literature can both avoid speciesism and deliver the human from subjectivity. This volume is a unique project which stands at the cutting edge of both animal rights philosophies and posthuman/artistic/abstract philosophies of identity. It will be of great interest to undergraduates and researchers in philosophy, ethics, particularly continental philosophy, critical theory and cultural studies.

Frequently asked questions

Simply head over to the account section in settings and click on ā€œCancel Subscriptionā€ - itā€™s as simple as that. After you cancel, your membership will stay active for the remainder of the time youā€™ve paid for. Learn more here.
At the moment all of our mobile-responsive ePub books are available to download via the app. Most of our PDFs are also available to download and we're working on making the final remaining ones downloadable now. Learn more here.
Both plans give you full access to the library and all of Perlegoā€™s features. The only differences are the price and subscription period: With the annual plan youā€™ll save around 30% compared to 12 months on the monthly plan.
We are an online textbook subscription service, where you can get access to an entire online library for less than the price of a single book per month. With over 1 million books across 1000+ topics, weā€™ve got you covered! Learn more here.
Look out for the read-aloud symbol on your next book to see if you can listen to it. The read-aloud tool reads text aloud for you, highlighting the text as it is being read. You can pause it, speed it up and slow it down. Learn more here.
Yes, you can access The Animal Catalyst by Patricia MacCormack, Patricia MacCormack in PDF and/or ePUB format, as well as other popular books in Philosophy & Philosophical Criticism. We have over one million books available in our catalogue for you to explore.

Information

Year
2014
ISBN
9781472527752
PART ONE
New Abolitionist Approaches
CHAPTER ONE
The War on Compassion
Carol J. Adams
In our lifetime, what was not supposed to happen ā€˜ever againā€™ ā€“ genocide ā€“ has instead happened again and again. As Samantha Power shows in A Problem from Hell (2002), her study of genocide in the twentieth century, the perception of genocide is all in the framing. Governments acting against a minority want the violence to be perceived as civil war or tribal strife, as quelling unrest and restoring order, as a private matter that does not spill over into the international community. Other governments weigh their own national interests against the needs of those being killed. After watching the movie Hotel Rwanda and as I began reading A Problem from Hell, among the many disturbing questions that surfaced for me, besides the obvious one ā€“ ā€˜How could we have let this happen?ā€™ ā€“ was the question, How can we get people to care about animals when they do not even care when people are being killed? But as this question came to mind, I realized that it was the wrong one because it accepts a hierarchy of caring that assumes that people ļ¬rst have to care about other people before they care about animals and that these caring acts are hostile to each other. In fact, violence against people and that against animals is interdependent. Caring about both is required. While I could not read about genocide without thinking about the other animals and what humans do to them, I am sophisticated enough to know that this thought is experienced as an offense to the victims of genocide. However, I am motivated enough to want to ask more about the associations I was thinking about and sensing because human and animal are deļ¬nitions that exist in tandem, each drawing its power from the other in a drama of circumscribing: the animal deļ¬ning the human, the human deļ¬ning the animal. As long as the deļ¬nitions exist through negation (human is this, animal is not this, human is not that, animal is that ā€“ although what is deļ¬ned as human or animal changes), the inscription of human on something, or the movement to be seen as human (for example, Feminism is the radical notion that women are human), assumes that there is something ļ¬xed about humanness that ā€˜humansā€™ possess and, importantly, that animals do not possess. Without animals showing us otherwise, how do we know ourselves to be human?
Despite all the efforts to demarcate the human, the word ā€˜animalā€™ encompasses human beings. We are human animals; they, those we view as not-us, are non-human animals. Discrimination based on colour of skin that occurs against those above the humanā€“animal boundary is called racism; when it becomes unspeakably murderous, it is called genocide. Discrimination by humans that occurs against those below the humanā€“animal boundary is called speciesism; when it becomes murderous, it is called meat eating and hunting, among other things. The latter is normalized violence. Is it possible that speciesism subsumes racism and genocide in the same way that the word ā€˜animalā€™ includes humans? Is there not much to learn from the way normalized violence disowns compassion? When the ļ¬rst response to animal advocacy is, ā€˜How can we care about animals when humans are suffering?ā€™, we encounter an argument that is self-enclosing: it re-erects the species barrier and places a boundary on compassion while enforcing a conservative economy of compassion; it splits caring at the humanā€“animal border, presuming that there is not enough to go around. Ironically, it plays into the construction of the world that enables genocide by perpetuating the idea that what happens to human animals is unrelated to what happens to non-human animals. It also fosters a fallacy: that caring actually works this way. Many of the arguments that separate caring into deserving/undeserving or now/later or ļ¬rst those like us/then those unlike us constitute a politics of the dismissive. Being dismissive is inattention with an alibi. It asserts that ā€˜this does not require my attentionā€™ or ā€˜this offends my sensibilityā€™ (that is, ā€˜We are so different from animals, how can you introduce them into the discussion?ā€™). Genocide, itself, beneļ¬ts from the politics of the dismissive. The difficulty that we face when trying to awaken our culture to care about the suffering of a group that is not acknowledged as having a suffering that matters is the same one that a meditation such as this faces: ā€˜How do we make those whose suffering does not matter, matter?ā€™
False mass terms
All of us are fated to die. We share this fate with animals, but the ļ¬nitude of domesticated animals is determined by us, by human beings. We know when they will die because we demand it. Their fate, to be eaten when dead, is the filter by which we experience their becoming ā€˜terminal animalsā€™. The most efficient way to ensure that humans do not care about the lives of animals is to transform non-human subjects into non-human objects. This is what I have called the structure of the absent referent (Adams 2000: 51). Behind every meal of meat is an absence: the death of the non-human animal whose place the meat takes. The absent referent is that which separates the meat eater from the other animal and that animal from the end product. Humans do not regard meat eating as contact with another animal because it has been renamed as contact with food. Who is suffering? No one.
In our culture, meat functions as a mass term (Quine 1960; Adams 1994: 27), deļ¬ning entire species of non-humans. Mass terms refer to things like water or colours; no matter how much of it there is or what type of container it is in, water is still water. A bucket of water can be added to a pool of water without changing it. Objects referred to by mass terms have no individuality, no uniqueness, no speciļ¬city, no particularity. When humans turn a non-human into ā€˜meatā€™, someone who has a very particular, situated life, a unique being, is converted into something that has no individuality, no uniqueness, no speciļ¬city. When ļ¬ve pounds of meatballs are added to a plate of meatballs, it is more of the same thing; nothing is changed. But taking a living cow, then killing and butchering that cow, and ļ¬nally grinding up her ļ¬‚esh does not add a mass term to a mass term and result in more of the same. It destroys an individual. What is on the plate in front of us is not devoid of speciļ¬city. It is the dead ļ¬‚esh of what was once a living, feeling being. The crucial point here is that humans transform a unique being, and therefore not the appropriate referent of a mass term, into something that is the appropriate referent of a mass term. False mass terms function as shorthand. They are not like us. Our compassion need not go there ā€“ to their situation, their experience ā€“ or, if it does, it may be diluted. Their ā€˜massiļ¬cationā€™ allows our release from empathy. We cannot imagine ourselves in a situation where our ā€˜I-nessā€™ counts for nothing. We cannot imagine the ā€˜not-Iā€™ of life as a mass term.
To kill a large number of people efļ¬ciently, the killers succeed when they have made the people they are targeting into a mass term. Philip Gourevitch, writing of the genocide in Rwanda, explains: ā€˜What distinguishes genocide from murder, and even from acts of political murder that claim as many victims, is the intent. The crime is wanting to make a people extinct. The idea is the crime. No wonder itā€™s so difficult to picture. To do so you must accept the principle of the exterminator, and see not people, but a peopleā€™ (1998: 202).
Gourevitch says that ā€˜the idea is the crimeā€™. The victims are seen as a mass term by their oppressors: ā€˜not people, but a peopleā€™. When a group is regarded as a people, not as being composed of individual people, certain conventions of thought and stereotypes take over. The claim is made that the people can be deļ¬ned as a group, through racial, ethnic or species characteristics: in Germany in the 1930s and 1940s, what Jews are like and what Jews do; in Rwanda in the 1950s and forward, what Tutsis are like and what Tutsis do. These characteristics heighten the idea of their existence as being a threat to others or as being dirty. Then the false characteristics become ļ¬xed through their existence as a metaphor.
The presumptions and mistakes of racial biology reiterate similar presumptions and mistakes in ā€˜speciesā€™ biology. Humans think they can know ā€˜cowsā€™ or ā€˜birdsā€™ and use adjectives drawn from this assumption: cowlike, birdbrain. Susanne Kappeler observes that
Western theories of racism attained proper ā€˜scientiļ¬cā€™ status in the nineteenth and twentieth centuries in the guise of medicine, psychiatry, eugenics, anthropology, demography, and so forth. They stand in direct continuity with the theories that categorize non-human animals in species, and living beings into humans, animals, and plants ā€“ categories modelled on the paradigms of the natural sciences. These included attempts to established classiļ¬cations of ā€˜kindsā€™ of people based on ā€˜typicalā€™ data ā€“ be it measurements of bodies and body parts, genetic data, or behavioral features. (1995: 327)
Gourevitch (1998) writes, ā€˜The idea is the crimeā€™, seeing a people, not people. One explanation for the appalling indifference of those of us who live in the United States, Europe, Great Britain, Australia and New Zealand to mass killings is that we, like their oppressors, may see the targeted victims as a mass term. When people are not experienced in their individuality, their deaths may not feel immediate. During the genocide in Rwanda, one American officer explained the calculations they were doing: ā€˜one American casualty is worth about 85,000 Rwandan deadā€™ (quoted in Power 2002: 381). The ā€˜massiļ¬cationā€™ of beings permits the dilution, the diminution of our attention. The more of a mass term they become, the less concern they need provoke. It is like an hourglass: the sands of our compassion drain into the bottom. How do we ļ¬‚ip the hourglass? How do we revive or awaken compassion?
Mass terms are linked to subjects being diminished. In their diminishment, as I pointed out in The Sexual Politics of Meat (2000), all that is left for them is to become metap...

Table of contents

  1. Cover
  2. Halftitle Page
  3. Title Page
  4. Dedication Page
  5. ContentsĀ 
  6. Notes on Contributors
  7. Acknowledgements
  8. Introduction
  9. Part One: New Abolitionist Approaches
  10. Part Two: Animal Mediators: Philosophy, Film, Literature
  11. Part Three: Ahumanity: A Liberation of Life
  12. Bibliography
  13. Index
  14. Imprint