Reimagining Human Rights
eBook - ePub

Reimagining Human Rights

Religion and the Common Good

William R. O'Neill

  1. 192 Seiten
  2. English
  3. ePUB (handyfreundlich)
  4. Über iOS und Android verfügbar
eBook - ePub

Reimagining Human Rights

Religion and the Common Good

William R. O'Neill

Angaben zum Buch
Buchvorschau
Inhaltsverzeichnis
Quellenangaben

Über dieses Buch

In Reimagining Human Rights, William O'Neill presents an interpretation of human rights "from below, " showing how victims of atrocity can embrace the rhetoric of human rights to dismantle old narratives of power and advance new ones. Topics covered include race and mass incarceration, immigration and refugee policy, and ecological responsibility.

Häufig gestellte Fragen

Wie kann ich mein Abo kündigen?
Gehe einfach zum Kontobereich in den Einstellungen und klicke auf „Abo kündigen“ – ganz einfach. Nachdem du gekündigt hast, bleibt deine Mitgliedschaft für den verbleibenden Abozeitraum, den du bereits bezahlt hast, aktiv. Mehr Informationen hier.
(Wie) Kann ich Bücher herunterladen?
Derzeit stehen all unsere auf Mobilgeräte reagierenden ePub-Bücher zum Download über die App zur Verfügung. Die meisten unserer PDFs stehen ebenfalls zum Download bereit; wir arbeiten daran, auch die übrigen PDFs zum Download anzubieten, bei denen dies aktuell noch nicht möglich ist. Weitere Informationen hier.
Welcher Unterschied besteht bei den Preisen zwischen den Aboplänen?
Mit beiden Aboplänen erhältst du vollen Zugang zur Bibliothek und allen Funktionen von Perlego. Die einzigen Unterschiede bestehen im Preis und dem Abozeitraum: Mit dem Jahresabo sparst du auf 12 Monate gerechnet im Vergleich zum Monatsabo rund 30 %.
Was ist Perlego?
Wir sind ein Online-Abodienst für Lehrbücher, bei dem du für weniger als den Preis eines einzelnen Buches pro Monat Zugang zu einer ganzen Online-Bibliothek erhältst. Mit über 1 Million Büchern zu über 1.000 verschiedenen Themen haben wir bestimmt alles, was du brauchst! Weitere Informationen hier.
Unterstützt Perlego Text-zu-Sprache?
Achte auf das Symbol zum Vorlesen in deinem nächsten Buch, um zu sehen, ob du es dir auch anhören kannst. Bei diesem Tool wird dir Text laut vorgelesen, wobei der Text beim Vorlesen auch grafisch hervorgehoben wird. Du kannst das Vorlesen jederzeit anhalten, beschleunigen und verlangsamen. Weitere Informationen hier.
Ist Reimagining Human Rights als Online-PDF/ePub verfügbar?
Ja, du hast Zugang zu Reimagining Human Rights von William R. O'Neill im PDF- und/oder ePub-Format sowie zu anderen beliebten Büchern aus Teología y religión & Teología cristiana. Aus unserem Katalog stehen dir über 1 Million Bücher zur Verfügung.

Information

CHAPTER ONE

Interpreting Rights

When sufferings become unendurable the cries are no longer heard. The cries, too, fall like rain in summer.
—Bertolt Brecht
The killings began on the evening of Easter Wednesday, April 6, 1994, and continued for three months. By the end over eight hundred thousand Tutsis as well as Hutus who opposed the genocide were massacred. Between that second week of April and the third week of May it is estimated that the daily rate of killing was at least five times that of the Nazi death camps. Three-quarters of the Rwandese Tutsi population fell victim to the genocide; the elderly, children, the infirm—none were spared. Nor was there haven. The churches, formerly offering sanctuary, were the first places attacked.1 In their environs “more Rwandese citizens died . . . than anywhere else.”2 The horror was unmitigated but not inexplicable, for the killing was due less to atavistic enmity than to a racist mythology nurtured in the colonial period and abetted by Belgian and later French realpolitik.3 Although favoring elite interests, the totalizing myth of Hutu supremacy divested the imagined “other” of moral standing so that the massacres by the Interahamwe (the militia) seemed banal.4 In a perverse inversion of Emmanuel Lévinas’s dictum, neighbor refused to see the neighbor’s face upon which was inscribed the command “Thou shalt not kill.”5 So, too, members of the United Nations Security Council refused to acknowledge the Rwandan killings as genocide lest they incur legal obligations under the Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of the Crime of Genocide to which they were signatories. At the behest of the United States, United Nations peacekeeping troops in Rwanda (UNIMIR) were summarily withdrawn, along with all foreign nationals.6 Others were left to die.
Yet mere wretchedness, Albert Camus reminds us, is not tragedy.7 Whether we see these cruelest months as morally tragic or merely an unimportant failure of realpolitik depends upon evoking what was effaced: bringing to word the transgressed command. And recognizing the nature, force, and scope of victims’ claims, as I noted in the introduction, is the first, indispensable critical or deconstructive role of rights.8 Yet memory speaks, I will argue, as command in the solidarity of remembrance, through what Benjamin calls anamnestic solidarity: the constructive role of rights.9 Here the interpretative burden shifts to identifying correlative duties and duty-bearers in redeeming claim-rights. Finally, the deconstructive and constructive uses combine in a hermeneutic of reconstructive redress. For the denial of rights leaves moral traces, such as in victims’ claims to repentance or reparation. As we shall see, these distinct yet finally inseparable uses of rights configure not only the legal/juridical and ethical but also the religious interpretation of rights. Indeed, our differences regarding the fit of these terms explain, in part, why social reconciliation remains such a vexed issue. Desmond Tutu’s pleas for “confession, forgiveness and reconciliation in the lives of nations” meet with his fellow Nobel laureate Wole Soyinka’s objection, that justice is ill served by “discharging the guilty without evidence of mitigation—or remorse.”10
How, then, can the exigent demands of individual rights be reconciled with “the healing of breaches, the redressing of imbalances, the restoration of broken relationships”?11 Must we choose between the “politics of [individual] rights” and the “politics of the common good” in restorative justice?12 Or is Tutu’s appeal to Ubuntu—the fusing of liberal justice and communitarian solidarity—merely a religious bricolage of incommensurable warrants and backings? As will be shown, any rapprochement must take seriously the genealogy of our differences. For it is only against the inherited theoretical background that the originality of Tutu’s translation appears. Let me first, then, offer a brief genealogy of our rival rhetorics and then elaborate the threefold use of rights at play in “telling the story.” I conclude with a brief response to several salient criticisms of rights rhetoric.

I. A GENEALOGY OF DIFFERENCE

Natural rights, it seems, are the currency of modernity—the coin of a disenchanted realm. The “ultimate and most sublime values have retreated from public life,” wrote Max Weber, while our fragmented values (a demystified polytheism) succeed to the “grandiose moral fervor of Christian ethics.”13 With the eclipse of the religiously inspired ideal of the common good, the liberties of the moderns reign supreme.14 Grotius’s modern heirs speak not of the divine finality of natural law (the jus naturale of the medievals) but of the natural, inalienable, and sacred rights of man.15 So it is for partisans and critics alike: the Western effective history of rights begins with what Jürgen Habermas calls the “positivization” (Positivierung) of the classical jus naturale of modernity. Civic virtue gives way to “a neutral sphere of personal choice” in which, as Mandeville put it, private vice makes public virtue.16
Recent historiography, as noted in the introduction, belies the secular myth of origins. In his magisterial treatise Brian Tierney contends that the origins of subjective natural rights in late twelfth-century canonical jurisprudence betrayed little of the “atomic individualism” of the “more egotistical impulses of early modern capitalism.” The use of rights was not “necessarily opposed to the communitarian values of traditional societies. Nor was the idea dependent on any particular version of Western philosophy; rather, it coexisted with a variety of philosophies, including the religiously oriented systems of the medieval era and the secularized doctrines of the Enlightenment.”17 Indeed, as we shall see, the originality of Tutu’s translation of rights in the South African TRC—one not beholden to the antinomies of modern liberal theory—rests in part on recovering the communitarian values of traditional societies, including the religiously oriented ideal of Ubuntu as expressed in victims’ narrative testimony.18 Yet the history of rights is also a history of forgetting. The secularized doctrines of the Enlightenment set the stage for our (post)modern rhetorical rivalries: variations wrung from the modern strain of natural rights and the neo-Hegelian or Aristotelian ethical riposte.19

The Liberal Metanarrative

While for Aquinas natural law (lex naturalis) preserves “happiness and its parts for the body politic,” for modern social-contract theorists, influenced as they are by nominalist legal theory, social obligation is incurred voluntaristically.20 Divested of its inner teleology, nature, one might say, has ceased to tell a moral tale. For there is, says Hobbes, “no such Finis Ultimus, (utmost ayme,) nor Summum Bonum, (greatest Good).” Augustine’s cor inquietum is now but “a continuall progresse of the desire, from one object to another”—the natural bonum commune of “the old Morall Philosophers” becomes the war “of every man against every man.”21 In this nominalist vein Hobbes opposes liberty as the “RIGHT OF NATURE” (Jus Naturale) “to use his own power, as he will himselfe, for the preservation of his own Nature” to the “LAW OF NATURE, (Lex Naturalis),” which “determineth, and bindeth.”22 For, stripped of Grotius’s natural sociability, it is “the foresight of their own preservation” that leads men “who naturally love Liberty, and Dominion over others” to submit to “that restraint upon themselves, (in which wee see them live in Common-wealths).”23 Society is itself a grand artifice, “an Artificiall Person” created by our mundane fiat.24 And hence the irony: to attain our mortal ends we must sacrifice our natural right of liberty to the ordained order of Hobbes’s “Mortall God,” Leviathan.25
Locke’s state of nature is, by contrast, a relatively peaceable kingdom. Deferring to the “judicious Hooker,” Locke grounds nature’s civility of mores in our natural equality, from which springs “the obligation to mutual love.” Yet the “law of nature” regulating our natural “state of liberty” turns less on Aquinas’s (or Richard Hooker’s) bonum commune than on the domain of individual, prepolitical rights.26 For Locke, writes Louis Dupré, “the existence of individual rights precedes that of the community, which previously had been considered the concrete source of right.”27 Private property (even in one’s “own person”) becomes the regnant metaphor of rights, the preservation and protection of which underwrite the social contract.
Rousseau, too, appeals to the doctrine of a social contract. Yet where Hobbes’s pactum subjectionis resolves the will of all into the will of one, Rousseau depicts the social bond (lien social) as the will’s self-limitation; indeed, it is only “with civil so...

Inhaltsverzeichnis

  1. Cover
  2. Half title
  3. Title
  4. Copyright
  5. Contents
  6. Preface
  7. Introduction
  8. Chapter One: Interpreting Rights
  9. Chapter Two: Justifying Rights
  10. Chapter Three: Rights and Religion
  11. Chapter Four: Applying Human Rights
  12. Conclusion
  13. Bibliography
  14. Index
  15. About the Author
Zitierstile für Reimagining Human Rights

APA 6 Citation

O’Neill, W. (2021). Reimagining Human Rights ([edition unavailable]). Georgetown University Press. Retrieved from https://www.perlego.com/book/1438184/reimagining-human-rights-religion-and-the-common-good-pdf (Original work published 2021)

Chicago Citation

O’Neill, William. (2021) 2021. Reimagining Human Rights. [Edition unavailable]. Georgetown University Press. https://www.perlego.com/book/1438184/reimagining-human-rights-religion-and-the-common-good-pdf.

Harvard Citation

O’Neill, W. (2021) Reimagining Human Rights. [edition unavailable]. Georgetown University Press. Available at: https://www.perlego.com/book/1438184/reimagining-human-rights-religion-and-the-common-good-pdf (Accessed: 14 October 2022).

MLA 7 Citation

O’Neill, William. Reimagining Human Rights. [edition unavailable]. Georgetown University Press, 2021. Web. 14 Oct. 2022.